BEAUTYPAYS
DANIELS.HAMERMESH
BEAUTY
PAYS
WhyAttractivePeople
AreMoreSuccessful
Copyright©2011byDanielS.Hamermesh
Requestsforpermissiontoreproducematerial
fromthisworkshouldbesenttoPermissions,
PrincetonUniversityPress
PublishedbyPrincetonUniversityPress,41
WilliamStreet,Princeton,NewJersey08540
IntheUnitedKingdom:PrincetonUniversity
Press,6OxfordStreet,Woodstock,Oxfordshire
OX201TW
press.princeton.edu
AllRightsReservedLibraryofCongressCataloging-in-Publication
Data
Hamermesh,DanielS.
Beautypays:whyattractivepeoplearemore
successful/DanielS.Hamermesh.
p.cm.
Includesbibliographicalreferencesandindex.
ISBN978-0-691-14046-9(hardcover)1.Successinbusiness.2.Success.3.Beauty,
Personal.I.Title.
HF5386.H2432010
650.1—dc22
2011013548
BritishLibraryCataloging-in-PublicationData
isavailable
ThisbookhasbeencomposedinBauerBodoni
andGaramondPremierPro
Printedonacid-freepaper.∞
PrintedintheUnitedStatesofAmerica
10987654321
CONTENTS
Preface
PARTIBackgroundtoBeauty
CHAPTERITheEconomicsofBeauty
CHAPTERIIIntheEyeoftheBeholder
DefinitionsofBeauty
WhyDoBeautyStandardsMatter?
HowDoWeMeasureHumanBeauty?
DoObserversAgreeonBeauty?
DoesBeautyDifferbyGender,Race,orAge?WhatMakesYouBeautiful?
CanWeBecomeMoreBeautiful?
TheStageIsSet
PARTIIBeautyontheJob:WhatandWhy
CHAPTERIIIBeautyandtheWorker
TheCentralQuestions
HowCanBeautyAffectEarnings?
HowMuchMoreDoGood-LookingPeopleMake?
IsBeautytheRealCause?
WhyAreBeautyEffectsSmallerAmongWomen?
DoBeautyEffectsDifferbyRace?
DoBeautyEffectsDifferbyAge?
CompensatingtheBeauty-DamagedWorker?
LooksMatterforWorkers
CHAPTERIVBeautyinSpecificOccupations
BeautyandChoosinganOccupation
HowBigAreBeautyEffectsWhereBeautyMightMatter?
HowBigAreBeautyEffectsWhereBeautyMightNotMatter?
SortingbyBeauty
CHAPTERVBeautyandtheEmployer
ThePuzzles
DoGood-LookingEmployeesRaiseSales?
HowDoesBeautyAffectProfits?
HowCanCompaniesPayforBeautyandSurvive?
DoCompanieswithBetter-LookingCEOsPerformBetter?
BeautyHelpsCompanies—Probably
CHAPTERVILookismorProductiveBeauty,andWhy?
WhattheBeautyEffectMeans
HowCanBeautyEffectsBeDiscrimination?
HowCanBeautyBeSociallyProductive?
WhatAretheSourcesofBeautyEffects?
WhatIstheDirectEvidenceontheSources?
TheImportanceofBeauty
PARTIIIBeautyinLove,Loans,andLaw
CHAPTERVIIBeautyinMarketsforFriends,Family,andFunds
BeyondtheLaborMarket
HowIsBeautyExchanged?
HowDoesBeautyAffectGroupFormation?
HowDoesBeautyAffectDating?
HowDoesBeautyAffectMarriage?
CouldThereBeaMarketforBeautifulChildren?
DoesBeautyMatterWhenYouBorrow?
TradingBeautyinUnexpectedPlaces
CHAPTERVIIILegalProtectionfortheUgly
FairnessandPublicPolicy
WhatKindsofProtectionArePossible?
HowHaveExistingPoliciesBeenUsed?
IsItPossibletoProtecttheUgly?
WhatJustifiesProtectingtheUgly?
WhatJustifiesNotProtectingtheUgly?
WhatIsanAppropriatePolicy?
ProtectingtheUglyintheNearFuture
PARTIVTheFutureofLooks
CHAPTERIXProspectsfortheLooks-Challenged
TheBeautyConundrum
AreBeautifulPeopleHappier?
WhatWillBeBeautiful?WhatShouldBe?
WhatCanSocietyDo?
WhatCanYouDoIfYou’reBad-Looking?
Notes
Index
PREFACE
I got involved instudyingtheeconomicsofbeautyinacuriousway.Earlyin
1993, I noticed that the data I was using on another research project included
interviewers’ ratings of the beauty of the survey’s respondents. I thought it
would be fun to think about how beauty affects earnings and labor markets
generally.TheresultwasthefirstofthesixrefereedscholarlypapersthatIhave
publishedonthistopic.Aseriousdifficulty formein thislineof researchhas
beenthatmanyeconomistsfindworkonthistopic,andeventhiskindoftopic,
tobebeyondthescopeofeconomicresearch.Thatkindofnarrow-mindedness
hasconspiredinthepasttomakeeconomicsappearboringintheeyesofmany
non-economists.AstheworkofGaryBecker,SteveLevitt,and,toamuchlesser
extent,myownhasshown,economicresearchcanbeanythingbutboring.Many
ofthetopicsthatweworkon,andonwhichseriouseconomicthinkingcanshed
light,arefunandinvolveissuesthatcouldnotbeunderstoodusingthemethods
ofanyotherscholarlydiscipline.
Ibeganworkingnearlytwentyyearsagotodiscoverwhateconomicshasto
sayonthetopicofphysicalappearance.Manyofthethemesthatarediscussed
inthisbookwerefirsttestedoutinscholarlypapers,andlaterbecamepartofan
ever-evolving lecture that I have delivered in various venues, entitled “The
EconomicsofBeauty.”Indevelopingthescholarlypapersandinpresentingthe
public lecture, I have received numerous comments from listeners, both other
economistsand the smartpeoplewho happened toshowup to hearme.Large
numbersofthecommentshavebeenuseful;andevenwheretheyhavenotbeen,
they have still been fun to receive. Perhaps themost amusing was acomment
fromadistinguishedeconomistwhoasked,“Areyousurethatbeautyisn’tjust
correlated with early-birdness [a term whose meaningwas initiallycompletely
opaque to me and most of the audience,but presumably alludes to earlybirds
catchingworms]?”
Iwasnotthefirst to look at the relationship betweenbeautyandeconomic
outcomes—that’s an old topic. I was, however, the first to examine it using a
nationally representative sample of adults, and to do so in the context of
economic models of the determination of earnings. My subsequent work
broadenedthisapproachintoaresearchagendathatinquiredintothe“Why?”of
this relationship and, more generally, into the meaning of discrimination as
perhaps represented by the economic roles of beauty and ugliness. As one
formerstudentofmineputit,allofthishasledtothedevelopmentofasubfield
thatonemightdubpulchronomics.
Many of my colleagues have contributed indirectly to this book. The most
importanthavebeenthecoauthorswhohaveworkedonbeautytopicswithme,
includingthestudentsCiskaBosmanandAmyParker,andmyfriendsXinMeng
andJunsenZhang.CrucialthroughouthavebeenJeffBiddleandGerardPfann,
who have become the most frequent coauthors in my now forty-three-year
professional career. Seminar attendees at a very large number of universities,
and especially at the National Bureau of Economic Research Labor Studies
meetings,havemadecommentsthathaveimprovedsomeofthepapersIdiscuss
inthisvolume.MylaboreconomistcolleaguesGeraldOettingerandSteveTrejo
were also very generous with theirtimetolistentomyideas,aswasMelinda
Moore.
The authors of all the economic studies that have been published since the
early1990shavealso,withoutintendingit,contributedsubstantiallytothework.
Threereviewersofanearlierdraftofthemanuscriptmadecogentcommentsthat
greatlyimprovedthepresentation.Particularcontributionstothebookwerealso
madebyJudithLanglois,ViceProvostattheUniversityofTexasatAustin,and
probably the leading expert on the perception of beauty by infants. My law
professorbrothermade helpful comments on chapter8,andat age ninety-one,
my late mother, Madeline Hamermesh,solved mysearch for a good title.Her
contributionisthefirstthingthatthereadersees.
Usingthe5to1scalethatIdiscussinchapter2,Iama3.Inmyeyes,my
wifeofforty-fouryears,FrancesW.Hamermesh,isa5.(Idid,however,make
themistakeofcommentinginawidelycirculatednewspaperinterviewthatshe
was not Isabella Rossellini,nor was I AlecBaldwin.) She has encouragedmy
work on thistopic over nearly twodecades. Still more important,she made it
clearwhenitwastimetostopproducingnewworkandmaketheentireoeuvre
accessibleoutsidethenarroweconomics specialty.Hercommentsonall drafts
ofthemanuscriptimprovedittremendously.Idedicatethisbooktothisamazing
woman:Shewalksinbeauty,likethenightOfcloudlessclimesandstarryskies:
Andallthat’sbestofdarkandbrightMeetinheraspectandhereyes:
Thesmilesthatwin,thetintsthatglow,Buttellofdaysingoodnessspent,
Amindatpeacewithallbelow,
Aheartwhoseloveisinnocent!
“SheWalksinBeauty,”GeorgeGordon,LordByron
DanielS.Hamermesh,Austin,TexasNovember2010
PARTI
Background
toBeauty
CHAPTER1
TheEconomicsofBeauty
Modern man is obsessed with beauty. From the day we are old enough to
recognizeourfacesinamirroruntilwellaftersenilitysetsin,weareconcerned
with our looks. A six-year-old girl wants to have clothes like those of her
“princess”dolls;apre-teenageboymayinsistonahaircutinthelateststyle(just
asIinsistedonmycrewcutin1955);twenty-somethingsprimpatlengthbefore
a Saturday night out. Even after our looks, self-presentation, and other
characteristicshavelandedusamate,westilldevotetimeandmoneytodyeing
our hair, obtaining hair transplants, using cosmetics, obtaining pedicures and
manicures,anddressingintheclothesthatwespentsubstantialamountsoftime
shopping for and eventually buying. Most days we carefully select the right
outfitsfromourwardrobesandgroomourselvesthoroughly.
The average American husband spends thirty-two minutes on a typical day
washing, dressing, and grooming, while the average American wife spends
forty-four minutes. There is no age limit for vanity: Among single American
womenageseventyandolder,forsomeofwhomyoumightthinkthatphysical
limitationswouldreducethepossibilityofspendingtimeongrooming,wefind
forty-three minutes devoted to this activity on a typical day.
1
Many assisted
living facilities and nursing homes even offer on-site beauty salons. For most
Americans, grooming is an activity in which they are willing to invest
substantialchunksoftheirtime.
Wenotonlyspendtimeenhancingourappearance—wespendlargesumsof
money on it too. In 2008, the average American household spent $718 on
women’sandgirls’clothing;$427onmen’sandboys’clothing;$655oninfants’
clothing, footwear, and other apparel products and services; and $616 on
personalcareproductsandservices.
2
Suchspendingtotaledroughly$400billion
andaccountedfornearly5percentofallconsumerspendingthatyear.Nodoubt
some of this spending is necessary just to avoid giving olfactory or visual
offensetofamilymembers,friends,andotherswhomwemeet;butthatminimal
amountisfarlessthanweactuallyspendontheseitems.
There is nothing uniquely modern or American about concerns about dress
and personal beautification. Archaeological sites from 2500 BCE Egypt yield
evidence of jewelry and other body decoration, and traces of ochre and other
bodypaintsarereadilyavailableevenearlier,fromPaleolithicsitesinsouthern
France.Peopleinotherindustrializedcountriesearlyinthetwenty-firstcentury
show similar concerns for their appearance and beauty: For example, in 2001
German husbands spent thirty-nine minutes grooming and dressing, while
German wives spent forty-two minutes in these activities, quite close to the
American averages. This similarity is remarkable, since you would think that
cultural differences might lead to different outcomes.
3
It suggests the
universalityofconcernsaboutbeautyanditseffectsonhumanbehavior.
The public’s responses to beauty today are fairly similar across the world.
TheChineseproducersofthe2008SummerOlympicsmusthavebelievedthis
whentheyputan extremely cute nine-year-old girlonworldwide television to
lip-syncthesingingofalessattractivechildwhohadabettervoice.
4
Thesame
attitudes underlay the worldwide brouhaha about the amateur English singer,
Susan Boyle, whose contrasting beautiful voice and plain looks generated
immensemediaattentionin2009.
Ourpreoccupationwithlookshasfosteredthegrowthofindustriesdevotedto
indulging this fascination. Popular books have tried to explain the biological
basisforthisbehaviorortoexhortpeopletogrowoutofwhatisviewedasan
outdated concern for something that should no longer be relevant for purely
biologicalpurposes.
5
Newsstandsineverycountryareclutteredwithmagazines
targeting people of different ages, gender, and sexual preference, counseling
their readers on methods to improve their looks. A typical example from the
coverofalifestylemagazineforwomenoffersadviceon“BeautySecretsofthe
Season.”Oneofitscounterpartscounselsmen onhowto“GetFit,Strongand
Leanin6Weeks.”
6
Theimportanceofbeautyisevidentintheresultsofatelephonesurveyinthe
United States.
7
Among the randomly selected people who responded to the
survey, more felt that discrimination based on looks in the United States
exceeded discrimination on ethnicity/national background than vice-versa.
Slightly more people also reported themselves as having experienced
discriminationbasedontheirappearancethanreporteddiscriminationbasedon
theirethnicity.AverageAmericansbelievethatdisadvantagesbasedonlooksare
realandeventhattheyhavepersonallysufferedfromthem.
Allwellandgood—thetimeandmoneythatwespendonitshouldenhance
ourinterestinbeautyanditseffects,andwe areworriedaboutandexperience
negativefeelingsifourlooksaresubpar.Butistheconcernofeconomistsmore
thanjustaprurientoneinresponsetothisintriguingtopic?Partoftheanswerto
this question stems from the nature of economics as a discipline. A very
appealingcharacterizationisthat economicsis thestudyofscarcityand ofthe
incentivesforbehaviorthatscarcitycreates.Aprerequisiteforstudyingbeauty
asaneconomicissuemustbethatbeautyisscarce.Forbeautytobescarce,as
buyersofgoodsandrentersofworkers’timepeoplemustenjoybeauty.Ifthey
cannotfindsufficient beauty suppliedfreely,and are thereforewillingto offer
moneytoobtainmoreofit,itmustbethatbeautyisscarce.
Take as given the notion that the scarcity of beauty arises from genetic
differencesinpeople’slooks,sothatbysomesociallydeterminedcriteriasome
people are viewed as better-looking than others. (I discuss what I mean
operationallyby“beauty”inthenextchapter.)Wouldbeautystillbescarceifwe
wereallgeneticallyidentical?Ofcourse,thiseventualityisnotabouttooccur,
butevenunderthisunrealisticscenarioitwouldstillmakesensetotalkaboutan
economics of beauty. So long as people desire to distinguish themselves from
others, someofthesehypotheticalcloneswillspend more on their appearance
thanothersinordertostandoutfromthecrowd.SomeofDr.Seuss’sSneetches
—a tribe of birdlike creatures who look identical—illustrate this desire for
distinctionalongonedimensioninthefaceofboringsamenessalongallothers
byputtingstarsontheirbellies.Theterm“scarcebeauty”isredundant—byits
nature,beautyisscarce.
The other part of the answer to this question stems from what I will
demonstrate are the large number of economic outcomes related to beauty—
areaswheredifferencesinindividuals’ beauty can directly influence economic
behavior.Marketsforlaborofavarietyoftypes,perhapsevenalllabormarkets,
mightgeneratepremiumpayforgoodlooksandpaypenaltiesforbadlooks.The
measurement of pay premia and penalties in different jobs and for people
belonging to different demographic groups is a standard exercise among
economic researchers. Doing so in the case of beauty is a straightforward
application.
Witheveryeffectonthepriceofagoodorservice,inthesecaseswagerates,
which are the prices of workers’ time, there is an effect on quantity. How a
personal characteristic alters the distribution of workers across jobs and
occupations is standard fodder for economists; and beauty is surely a personal
characteristic that can change the kinds of jobs and occupations that people
choose.
Ifbeautyaffectsbehaviorinlabormarketsandgeneratesdifferencesinwages
and the kinds of jobs that we hold, it may also produce changes in how we
choosetouseourtimeoutsideourjobs.Howwespendourtimeathomeisnot
independentofhowwespendourtimeatworkorofthekindsofoccupationswe
choose.Ifdifferencesinbeautyalteroutcomesintheworkplace,theyarelikely
toalteroutcomesathometoo.
A characteristic like beauty that affects wages and employment will also
affectthebottom line of companies andgovernmentsthatemploy the workers
whose looks differ. Are certain industries likely to be more significantly
affected? How does the existence of concerns about beauty affect companies’
salesandprofitability?Howisexecutives’payaffectedbytheirbeauty?Perhaps
mostimportant,howcancompaniessurviveifbeautyisscarceandthusaddsto
companies’costsandpresumablyreducestheirprofitability?
Themorebasicquestioniswhythesedirecteffectsonlabor-marketoutcomes
arise.Whosebehaviorgeneratestheoutcomesthatwehopetomeasure?Aside
from allowing us to measure the importance of the phenomenon of beauty in
economicbehavior,economicsasapolicyart/scienceshouldbeabletoisolate
themechanismsbywhichitaffectsoutcomes.Itiscrucialtoknowhowbeauty
generates its effects if we are to guard against giving undue importance to its
role in the functioning of labor markets. It is also important in weighing the
benefitsandcoststosocietyofourattitudesabouthumanbeauty.
Allofthesepossibleeconomicinfluencesofbeautyaredirectandareatleast
potentially measurable. And those measurements can readily be made in
monetaryterms,oratleastconvertedintomonetaryequivalents,sothatwecan
obtainsomefeelforthesizeoftheimpactsrelativetothoseofothereconomic
outcomes.Becauseofthescarcityofbeauty,itseffectsoutsidemarketsforlabor
andgoodscanalsobestudiedineconomicterms.Marriageisjustsuchamarket,
althoughhusbandsandwivesarenotboughtorsoldinrichcountriestoday.Yet
theattributesthatwebringtothemarriagemarketaffecttheoutcomesweobtain
inthatmarket,specificallythecharacteristicsofthepartnerwhowematchwith.
Beautyisoneofthoseattributes,soitisreasonabletoassumethatdifferencesin
thebeautythatwebringtothemarriagemarketwillcreatedifferencesinwhat
wegetoutofit.Wetradeourlooksforotherthingswhenwedateandmarry;but
whatarethoseother things, and how much of themdoourlooks enable us to
acquire?
Takingallofthistogether,theeconomicapproachtreatsbeautyasscarceand
tradable. We trade beauty for additional income that enables us to raise our
living standards (satisfy our desires for more things) and for non-monetary
characteristicsofworkandinterpersonalrelations,suchaspleasantcolleagues,
anenjoyableworkplace,andsoon,thatalsomakeusbetteroff.Researchersin
other disciplines, particularly social psychology, have generated massive
amounts of research on beauty, occasionally touching on economic issues,
particularlyinmarriagemarkets.Buteconomistshaveaddedsomethingspecial
and new to this fascinating topic—a consistent view of exchange and value
relatedtoacentralhumancharacteristic—beauty.
Theeconomicsofbeautyillustratesthepowerofusingverysimpleeconomic
reasoning to understand phenomena that previously have been approached in
otherways.Thatpower,thetimeandmoneythatarespentonbeautyworldwide,
and human fascination with beauty, are more than sufficient reasons to spend
time thinking about beauty from an economic point of view. The economic
approachtobeautyisanaturalcomplementtoeconomicresearchonlessgeneral
topicssuchassuicideandsumowrestling,sleepandcommercialsex.
8
I concentrate on economic issues, introducing studies from the psychology
and other literatures only where they amplify the economics or contribute
essential foundations to understanding the economics of beauty. These other
approaches are important; they have provided many insights into human
behaviorandgarneredalotofmediaattention.Butbecausetheydonotrestona
choice-basedeconomicapproach,theycannotprovidetheparticularinsightsthat
economicthinkingdoes.
9
The economic approach is broad, but not all-encompassing. Economic
analysiscannotexplainwhatmakessomepersonalcharacteristicsattractiveand
othersnot—orwhythesameindividual’slooksevokedifferentresponsesfrom
eachdifferentobserver.Wetakethesourcesofdifferencesinpreferencesinthe
samecountryandatthesametimeasoutsideourpurview.Itdoesnotdescribe
how responses to personal characteristics differ over the centuries or among
societies.Ittreatsthesetooasgiven.Butknowingwhathumanbeautyis—what
aretheattributesthatmakethetypicalonlookerviewsomepeopleasattractive
andothersasnot—istheessentialpre-conditionforthinkingabouttheeconomic
impacts of beauty. For that reason, the next chapter describes what we know
about the determinants of human beauty, a topic that has received a lot of
attentionfromsocialpsychologistsandthatunderlieswhateconomicshastosay
abouttheroleofbeauty.
CHAPTER2
IntheEyeoftheBeholder
DEFINITIONSOFBEAUTY
Whatishumanbeauty?Howdoesbeautyvarybygender,race,andage?Most
important,doobservershaveatleastsomewhatconsistentviewsofwhatmakes
apersonbeautiful?Inordertoanswerthesequestions,wefirstneedtoattemptto
definebeauty.Oneonlinedictionaryoffersadefinitionofbeautythatisrelevant
forourpurposes:“Thequalityoraggregateofqualitiesinapersonorthingthat
givespleasuretothesensesorpleasurablyexaltsthemindorspirit.”
1
Theterm
“aggregate of qualities in a person” comes close to describing beauty in an
economiccontext;butitstillleavesthedefinitionvagueforpracticalpurposes—
whatqualities,whataggregate?“Beautyisintheeyeofthebeholder,”thefirst
stockphrasethatcomestoyourmindwhenaskedabouthumanbeauty,suggests
thatpeople’sopinionsaboutthisquestionofhumanbeautydiffer.
Foreconomicpurposesthequestionsarewhatcharacteristicsmakeaperson
beautiful, and do people agree on what these characteristics are and what
expressionsofthemconstitutehumanbeauty.YouandImaydifferinourviews
about what beauty is. But if our views about human beauty are somewhat
similar, and we are typical individuals, then our opinions are valuable
representativesofhowthegeneralpopulationviewsbeauty.Andifweexamine
how people have viewed beauty over the ages, we can acquire a more
sophisticated understanding of what humanbeauty isand havemore informed
opinionswhenwejudgepeople’slooks.
Even if people agreed completely on what expressions of various
characteristicsconstitutebeauty,wewouldstillneedtodecidewhichparticular
constellationofcharacteristicsshouldbeconsideredinthedefinition.Isithairor
hair color? Weight? Height? Physiognomy—just the face? Internal beauty—
character and its expression—reversing the popular saying that beauty is only
skindeep?Isitgenerosity?Sympathy?Facialexpression?Dress?Combinations
ofthese?Todiscusstheeconomiceffectsofbeauty,Iwanttonarrowthefocus
asmuchaspossibletofaces.Onemightarguethatphysiognomyrepresentsonly
atinypartofhumanbeauty—andthatiscorrect.Nonetheless,physiognomycan
beisolatedandusedasabasisforjudgmentsabouthumanbeauty:
She reminded me of the daughter that I always had wished for. Bright
eyes, a mouth ready to laugh, high cheekbones and luxurious shoulder-
length brown hair. The photo didn’t show if she was short or tall, fat or
thin,bentorerect—itwasonlyapassportphoto.
2
Or,asthepsychoanalystOliverSacksputit,“itistheface,firstandlast,thatis
judged‘beautiful’inanaestheticsense.”
3
Asthesequotationssuggest,peoplecananddomakejudgmentsaboutbeauty
based only on physiognomy. Throughout this book I examine how judgments
aboutthisonemanifestationofbeautyaffectbehavior.
No doubt standards of beauty do change over time. The Renoir nudes that
enthralled the art world from the 1880s through the early twentieth century
wouldnotberegardedasgreatbeautiestoday—whilenotunattractive,theyare
probablytoozaftigforcontemporarytastes.Ontheotherhand,late-nineteenth-
centuryobservers almostcertainly wouldhave regardedtoday’s modelson the
runways of Parisian haute couture as incipiently consumptive, perhaps a
character out of La Bohème (just as my late grandmother, born in Europe in
1887, viewed my thin face as suggesting that I am dangerously underweight).
Evenwithinasociety,standardsoffacialbeautydochangeovertime.Standards
alsodiffer,oratleastusedtodiffer,acrosssocietiesatroughlysimilarpointsin
time.Thegentlemaninfigure2.1isRudolfValentino,theHollywoodheartthrob
ofthe1920s.Mostpeopleeventodaywouldagreethathewasquitebeautiful—
presumablythatwasamajorunderpinningofhissuccessasamovieactor.The
gentleman in figure 2.2 also lived in the early twentieth century, but in the
Arctic.Whilehis fellows would haveagreedthathe is beautiful, itisunlikely
thathislookswouldhavelandedhimaHollywoodmoviecontract.
Within a society at a point in time, including the worldwide society of
developed nations, there is substantial agreement on what constitutes human
beauty. I asked three women, ages twenty, thirty-five, and sixty-five, who the
sexiestmenintheworldaretoday.AllthreeincludedGeorgeClooneyintheir
list.Havingpresentedhispictureandthoseofanumberofothermen,including
Asian and American politicians and actors, to audiences in the United States,
Asia,Australia,andEurope,Iamcertainthatthereisnearlyuniversalagreement
thatGeorgeClooneyisconsideredbetter-lookingthanalmostanyoneelse.
Figure2.1.RudolfValentino,actor,1920s.©Bettmann/CORBIS
Figure2.2.Inuitman,1920s.PhotofromMaritimeHistoryArchive,MemorialUniversityof
Newfoundland,St.John’s,NL.
It is not that George Clooney is a Westerner and there is some kind of
universalprejudiceinfavorofWesternfaces.Takethetwowomeninfigures2.3
and 2.4. I would wager that most readers, be they Western or not, would
considerSouthCarolinagovernorNikkiHaley,whoisofSouthAsiandescent,
much better-looking than U.S. senator Barbara Mikulski. These cases at least
provideanecdotalevidenceofthecurrentnear-universalityoftoday’sstandards
ofhumanbeauty.
Figure2.3.NikkiHaley,U.S.politician,2000s.APPhoto/AlexBrandon,File.
Cultural differences do still exist. A recent report on a “fat farm” in
Mauritania, one of the poorest countries in the world, illustrates their
persistence.
4
Thisisnotthekindof “fatfarm” towhichrichNorthAmericans
retreattoloseweight,butonewhereyounggirlsarefed,andevenforce-fed,to
producerotundyoungadultswhoareviewedasattractive.Buteventhisunusual
cultural difference appears to be diminishing in importance as Mauritania
industrializesandbecomesmoreintegratedwiththeoutsideworld.
5
Figure2.4.BarbaraMikulski,U.S.politician,2000s.OfficialgovernmentphotofromtheU.S.Senate
HistoricalOffice.
WHYDOBEAUTYSTANDARDSMATTER?
Unlesspeopleagreeonwhatconstituteshumanbeauty—unlessthereisatleasta
somewhat common standard of beauty—it cannot haveany independenteffect
onoutcomessuch as earnings.Itmight seemtohave an effect,evenif people
disagreedaboutbeauty,butthatcouldonlybeifothercharacteristicsthataffect
thoseoutcomesarerelatedtobeauty.
These same arguments apply to the role of beauty in other areas in which
humanbeingstrade.Wetradeourcharacteristicswhenweenterintoamarriage.
AsthestoryofJacob’seffortstowinthehandofRachel“ofbeautifulformand
fair to look at” illustrates, throughout human history men who can raise more
sheep,producemorecrops,orearnmoredollarsinthestockmarkethaveused
thesecharacteristicstoobtainmoredesirable(and,insomesocietiesandepochs,
more)wives.
6
Ifmenagree on feminine beauty, just as inlabormarkets those
womenviewedasbeautifulwillcommandahigherprice,eitherexplicitlyorin
the form of husbands who can provide them with more resources. They will
obtainmoreandbetterfood,aneasierlifestyle,morefreedomtodowhatthey
want,andotherbenefits.Asmenandwomenbecomemoreequaleconomically,
solongaswomenhavecommonviewsaboutmen’sbeauty,thesamebehavior
will apply in reverse: Women who have more to offer men, including the
economicadvantagestheycanofferprospectivehusbands,willobtainthebetter-
lookinghusbands.
Solongastherearecommonstandardsofbeauty,theywillaffectoutcomes
inanymarketwherebeautyaffectstransactions—whereitaffectswhatistraded.
Thatisastrueforhiringworkersasitisformarriagecontracts.Thequestionfor
analyzingtheeconomiceffectsofbeautyiswhethertheideaofcommonbeauty
standardsisrepresentedbymorethanjustthepictorialanecdotespresentedhere.
Do people agree, at least to some extent, on which of their fellows are good-
lookingandwhicharenot?Dotheysharecommonviewsofhumanbeauty?
HOWDOWEMEASUREHUMANBEAUTY?
Wecan’tseewhethertherearecommonstandardsofbeautyunlessweareable
tocomparedifferentpeople’sviewsaboutbeauty.Andwecan’teasilycompare
them unless we can somehow measure them. The difficultyis that thereis no
singlewaytoattachnumericalscorestoobservers’beliefsaboutthebeautyof
thepeopletheysee.WhenIwasaseniorinhighschoolwereadMarlowe’sDr.
Faustus, in which the title character describes a vision of Helen of Troy and
declaims,“Isthisthefacethatlaunch’dathousandships,andburntthetopless
towers of Ilium?” This prompted one of my fellow nerds to suggest that we
shouldmeasurethepulchritudeofthegirlsinourclassinmilli-Helens!Thisis
as reasonable a subjective measuring device as another, but perhaps
unsurprisinglyithasnotbeenappliedinresearchonbeauty.
One might, for example, use a numerical rating scheme and use a 10 to 1
scale.Onemightinsteadusea5to1scale.Toseethatthesearenotthesame,
lookatthenextfivepeopleyouseeandgiveeachonearatingona5to1scale.
Askyourselfafterward:“IfIhadinsteaduseda10to1scale,wouldmyratings
just have been double those that I gave on the 5 to 1 scale?” I doubt it. In
particular, I would bet that scores of 10 on the 10 to 1 scale would be
substantiallylessfrequentthanthetopscoreonthe5to1scale.
Inaskingonlookerstoratepeople’sbeauty,doweattachverbaldescriptions
to the numerical ratings that observers are asked to give, or are they simply
askedtochooseascore?Evenwiththesamescale,say5to1,theanswerswill
differdependinguponwhat,ifanything,theobserveristoldaboutthemeaning
ofthescores.
What are the observers asked to rate—people standing in front of them, or
pictures? Both approaches have been used, and the difference between them
formsthemainunderlyingdistinctionamong studies of beauty. Ratings of the
same person by the same observer will differ between the two methods. The
picture may show her looking radiant upon her college graduation, or him
beamingonhisweddingday.Peopledonotreactthesamewaytothecamera,
and it is impossible to adjust for differences in their reactions when we use
observers’ratingsofpictures.Somemaybedressedwellforthepicture,others
dressedsloppily.Somemaybecapturedscowling,whileothershaveasmilethat
isglowingenoughtoturna4intoa5.
Assumingthatwerelyonratingsofpictures,whataretheypicturesof?What
are the observers asked to rate?Faces alone? Headand shoulders?Full body?
Posed or not? Since I have defined beauty for the purpose of this study as
physiognomy, head and shoulders, or even the face alone, would be best; but
pictureslikethatarenotalwaysavailable.
Theproblemisequally,but differently,challengingifwerelyonratingsof
peoplewhoarebeinginterviewedface-to-face.Ifnothingelse,andevenwiththe
mostexplicitinstructions,interviewerswilltendtobasetheirassessmentsonthe
natureoftheinteractionsthattheyhavealready hadwiththeperson.Does the
intervieweeanswerthedoorinadresssuit,orinasweatsuitpost-workout?Is
sheattheendofatiringday,orisshefreshandreadytodealwithwhateverthe
world may bring? All of these variations in appearance and behavior will
conditionhowtheinterviewerassessesherlooks.
With both photographs and interviews, it is impossible to be sure that the
raterisbasingtheratingsolelyonphysiognomy.Arestrictiontophysiognomyis
more likely with pictures, but even there, weight may enter into the rating
(remembertheRenoirmodel).Intheend,itisimpossibletorestrictratingstobe
objective—the rating of beauty is inherently subjective. People will always
disagreetosomeextent.
While there may be universal standards of beauty, and thus substantial
agreementonwhatisbeautiful,therearenouniversalstandardsonhowpeople
indifferentcountriesandculturesrespondwhenconfrontedbywhatappeartobe
identical requests to rate others’ beauty. Even with the best translation, what
appeartobethesameratingsystemsmay havedifferentmeanings indifferent
societies. And there may be international differences in raters’ generosity or
willingnesstomakefinedistinctions.
There is no way of avoiding these problems. The best we can do in
interpreting studies of the effects of beauty is to be sure that raters of beauty
were monitored so that they adhered to strict guidelines that are at least
internallyconsistentwhentheyprovidedtheirratings.
Themostwidelyusedscaleinthebeautyliteraturehasbeena5to1rating
scheme, usually with instructions to the interviewers/raters about what these
ratingsmean.Thenumericalscoresweredefinedininstructionstointerviewers
in a nationally representative 1971 survey conducted by the University of
Michigan. They have been used with minor variations in many subsequent
studies,boththosebasedonobservationsduringliveinterviewsandthosebased
onratingsofphotographs.
7
NeartheendofalengthyinterviewintheMichigansurvey,theinterviewer
wasinstructedto“ratetherespondent’sphysicalappearance”usingthescale:
5 Strikinglyhandsomeorbeautiful
4 Good-looking(aboveaverageforageandsex)
3 Averagelooksforageandsex
2 Quiteplain(belowaverageforageandsex)
1 Homely
Notetheparentheticalqualifiersthatwereincludedtoinducetheinterviewersto
abstract from preconceptions that they might have about age or gender
differencesinlooks.
Togetafeelfortheuseofthisratingscheme,lookatthenexttenstrangers
you see and try rating their looks along this scale. Don’t intellectualize about
your rating—as the interviewers did, it should be a snap response to your
impressions.Iwouldbesurprisedifyoucannoteasilydistinguisha“4”froma
“2”amongthepeopleyouencounter.
IwasobsessedbythesedatainthefirstfewdaysafterIdiscoveredthem.I
walked around my campus mentallyrating the beauty of mostof the people I
passedonthis5to1scale.IadmitthatIalsoratedmycolleagues’looksonthis
scale,thusviolatingtheanonymitythat should exist between subject and rater
butthatisnecessarilyviolatedinratingsbasedoninterviews.
Thedistributionsoftheseinterviewers’ratingsalongthe5to1scaleinthis
studyandinarelatedstudyconductedlaterinthe1970sareshownintable2.1,
separately for men and women. Here, as in many subsequent tabulations of
ratingsofbeautybasedoninterviews,moreindividualsareassessedasbeingin
the top two categories than inthebottom two. Interviewers’ formal subjective
ratings of beauty are not quite characterized by a Lake Wobegon effect—not
everyone is above average in beauty—but the average person whose beauty is
assessedinthisstudyisconsideredaboveaverage.
TABLE2.1
RatingsofAppearance,QualityofAmericanLife,andQualityofEmploymentSurveys,AmericansAges
18–64,1970s(percentdistributions)*
*Tabulationsfromrawdatadescribing1,495womenand1,279men.
Interviewer-based ratings from vastly different cultures produce the same
generalresults.EvidencefromasurveyinShanghai,China,fromthemid-1990s
demonstratesthesimilarityofratingstothoseintheUnitedStates.TheChinese
interviewers were, though, particularly unwilling to rate people as below-
averageinlooks—only1percentofmen,and1percentofwomen,wereratedas
below-averageorugly.Nearlytwo-thirdsofeachgroupwasratedasaverage.
Using the same 5 to 1 scale as in table 2.1, raters examined nearly 2,500
photographs of students who entered a large, prestigious law school between
1969and1984.Eachphotograph(typicallyhead-and-shouldersshots)wasrated
byfourdifferentobservers.Aswiththeinterviewratings,nearlyhalfthepeople
wereratedasaverage-looking.
The 5 to1 scale ora minor variant is most common, but others have been
used. One study asked six raters (three male and three female undergraduate
students)tousea10to1scaletoexaminephotographstoassessthelooksofa
groupofninety-fourprofessors(whomthesixstudentsdidnotknow).
8
Asinthe
lawstudents’study,therewasnotendencytoratetheprofessors’looksasabove
themiddle ofthe 10-pointscale—indeed,morewererated 5or lessthanwere
rated6orabove.Partlythismaybeduetotheprofessors’ages(averagingfifty)
beingso differentfromthose oftheundergraduates doingtheratings. Partlyit
mayjustbethesample:Whenaskedwhyhisratingswereparticularlylow,one
malestudentremarked,“Becausetheseprofsarereallyugly!”
DOOBSERVERSAGREEONBEAUTY?
That people are biased in favorof judging others’ beauty as onaverage being
above-average,orevenasbelow-average,isnotaproblem—itiseasytoadjust
statistically for these biases in drawing conclusions about the relationship
betweendifferencesinbeautyandanyeconomicorotheroutcome.Thetougher
questioniswhetherpeopleagreeonthebeautyofaparticularindividual,andthe
extent of that agreement, if any. Without that there would be no common
standards of beauty. Beauty would have no meaning in an economic context,
since its diffuseness would mean it could not be scarce. And I would not be
writingthisbook!
Therearetwodifferentwaystodiscovertheextentofraters’agreementabout
people’s beauty. The first,which has been usedonly rarely, is tolook at how
raters’assessmentsofpeople’sbeautyvarywhentheyviewthesameindividuals
atdifferenttimes.Answersusingthisapproachcanbeseenfromastudybased
onpicturesofeconomists.Iaskedfour studentswho werejust beginningtheir
graduate studies to rate the looks of a large number of pictures of leading
economists, many of whom were included multiple times and submitted a
differentphotographeachtime.Ofcourse,thesameindividualreceiveddifferent
ratingsfordifferent pictures,butthose differencesweresmallcomparedtothe
differencesintheaverageratingsreceivedbydifferenteconomists.
9
Answers based on interviews can be seen from a nationally representative
studyundertakeninCanada,inwhichthesamepeoplewereinterviewedin1977,
1979,and1981.Eachindividualwascontactedbyadifferentinterviewerineach
year,allowinganopportunityfordifferentviewsoftheinterviewee’slookstobe
expressed. The interviewerswereaskedtoassess looks using the 5 to 1 scale.
Comparing ratings in adjacent years, 54 percent of women and 54 percent of
men were rated identically in each of the two years; and only 3 percent of
womenand2percentofmenreceivedaratinginthesecondyearofapairthat
differedbymorethan1fromtheratingthattheyhadreceivedinthefirstyearof
thatpair.
10
Evenindifferentinteractionswithdifferentinterviewerstherewasa
remarkabletendencytoviewtheinterviewees’looksverymuchthesameway.
Thesecondwayoftestingforconsistencyinourviewsofothers’beautyisto
ask a group of individuals to provide independent ratings of another person’s
looks. Typically this has been done by showing each of a number of people,
noneofwhomcancontacttheothers,thesamephotograph.Whiletherewillbe
disagreements, the question is whether they are small, so that the averages
informusaboutgeneralperceptionsofeachperson’slooks.
Asanexample,taketheratingsofthelawstudents’photosdescribedearlier.
Complete agreement—all four observers giving the exact same score to a
photograph—wasfairlyuncommon,occurringforonly14percentofthephotos.
Butnearagreement,definedasallfourratingsthesame,asthreeoffourraters
ratingthepictureidentically,orastwopairsofraterswhodifferbyonly1point
on the 5-point scale, occurred with the photos of 67 percent of the female
studentsand75percentofthemalephotos.Onlyone-tenthof1percentofthe
studentswererateddifferentlybyallfourraters.Completedisagreementabout
looksisanextraordinarilyrareevent.
Even in the case of the professors, where the 10 to 1 scale allows for a lot
moreminordisagreementamongthesixraters,54percentoftheprofessorswere
ratedidenticallybyatleastthreeofthesixraters.Amongtheeconomists,who
werealsoratedonthe10to1scale,28percentofthepicturesreceivedthesame
scorefrom threeof thefour raters,and 80percent wererated identicallyby at
leasttwoofthefour.
Thereareconsistentdifferencesinhowindividualsrateeachother’sbeauty.
Within the same culture some people are always harsh in rating their fellow
citizens’ looks, and others are consistently more generous. In the study that
establishedthe5-pointratingscheme,eachofsixtyinterviewersratedatleastten
subjects.Theaverageratingsranged from3.6 (closerto above-averagethanto
average)bythemostgenerousinterviewerdownto2.4(closertoplainthanto
average)bythemostnegativeinterviewer.Butonly10percentofthedifferences
intheratingsofintervieweescanbeascribedtojudgmentsbyraterswhoapplied
particularly harsh or generous standards. While interviewers do have different
standards,theeffectsoftheirdifferencesaredwarfedbytheinherentdifferences
inpeople’slooks.
11
About half of the interviewers in thatstudy were between ages twenty-two
andforty-nine,theotherhalfwerebetweenagesfiftyandseventy-four.Despite
their possibly different perspectives on the subjects’ looks, there were no
statistically meaningful differences in the ratings given by interviewers of
differentages. But while interviewers’age was independent oftheratings that
they assigned, there were differences by gender. Men seemed to be stingier
ratersofthesubjects’beauty.
There are also differences across countries, probably having to do with
culturaldifferencesinpeople’swillingnesstosaysomethingnegativeabouttheir
fellows.Forinstance,AmericansseemslightlymorewillingthantheirCanadian
neighbors to label someone as plain or homely. As noted earlier, in the
Shanghainese data, only 1 percent of the interviewees were rated as below
average. The only useful distinction in those data is between those rated as
averageandthoseratedasprettyorverypretty.
Despite these consistent disagreements and biases, the answer to the titular
question of this section is a resounding, “MOSTLY!” There is no universal
agreementbygroupsofpeopleonanyoneelse’sbeauty.Somepeopleareharsh
judgesofothers’looks,whileotherpeoplearegenerousintheirappraisals.But
individuals do tend to view others’ beauty similarly, although not identically.
Someone who is considered above-average in looks by one observer will be
viewed the same way by most other observers. Someone who a randomly
selectedpersonthinksisquiteuglywillbeviewedasquiteuglybymostother
observers. Yes, there are disagreements, but there is also a lot of agreement.
Thereisnouniqueviewaboutbeauty—nouniquestandard.Butbecausepeople
tendtoviewhumanbeautysimilarly,thosewhoaregenerallyviewedasgood-
looking possess a characteristic—their beauty—that appeals to most other
human beings in similar ways and that ipso facto is in short supply. Human
beautyisscarce.
DOESBEAUTYDIFFERBYGENDER,RACE,OR
AGE?WHATMAKESYOUBEAUTIFUL?
Arewomenbetter-lookingthanmen?IthinksowhenIthinkromantically,but
you no doubt have your own views on this subject. The question, though, is
whetherwethinkthatwaywhenwetrytoassesspeople’slooksobjectively.The
averagemaleinthedataunderlyingtable2.1wasratedalmostthesameasthe
average woman. In the Shanghai data, women were rated as slightly better-
lookingthanmen,withthedifferenceresultingfrommorewomenbeingratedas
beautiful.
This near equality only arises if the individuals being rated are chosen
randomly.Womenconstitutedonly12percentofthelawstudentswhoentered
theprestigiouslawschoolbetween1969and1974.Theaverageratingoftheir
lookswas3.1,comparedtothe2.8averageratingoftheirmalefellowstudents,
perhapsbecausethosefewwomenwerespecialinmanyotherways.Bythenext
decade,femalestudentshadincreasedto31percentoftheenteringclasses,and
thedifferenceinaveragelooksbetweenmaleandfemalestudentswasonlyhalf
aslargeasbefore.Selectionintothesamplecanproduceunequalaveragesofthe
ratingsofthelooksofmenandwomen.Butwheremenandwomenareroughly
equally represented among the subjects, the average ratings of men’s and
women’slooksareusuallynearlyidentical.
Whileaverageratingsoflooksareroughlyequalbygender,thedistributions
differ, as the columns in table 2.1 illustrate. Ratings of women’s looks were
moreextremethanratingsofmen’s:Morewereratedasplainorhomely,more
were rated as strikingly beautiful or above-average, and fewer were rated as
possessing average looks. Interviewers react more strongly to women’s looks,
both positively and negatively in other interview studies too; and in studies
examiningphotographs,womenarealsoviewedmoreextremelythanmen.For
example,14percentoftheratingsoffemaleprofessorswereabove7,whileonly
6percentoftheratingsofmaleprofessorswere.
Whether beauty differs by race is another concern—if, for example,
employersperceive AfricanAmericans’ beautydifferently fromthat ofwhites,
any differences in earnings related to race could be confounded by disparate
treatment based on looks rather on than on race per se. In the two American
studies from the 1970s the interviewers, nearly all of whom were white, gave
almostidenticalratingson averageto whitesand AfricanAmericans.Butthey
did rate subjects of different races differently, reacting more extremely to the
whitesthantotheAfricanAmericans.Thirteenpercentofwhiteswereratedas
plainorhomely,whileonly10percentofAfricanAmericanswere.Attheupper
end, 32 percent of whites were viewed as being at least above-average, while
only 28 percent of African Americans were. There may well be differences
betweenhow membersofother races—AsianAmericans,for example—would
beratedbythewhiteraters,butwejusthavenoinformationonthatpossibility.
Whetherweconsiderlooksbygenderorrace,wereachthesameconclusion.
Therearenodifferencesinaverages,butthedistributionsofratingsofwomen’s
looksaremoredispersedthan those of men’s, and of whites’ looks morethan
thoseofAfricanAmericans.
The same conclusion cannot be drawn about differences in ratings of the
beautyofpeopleofdifferentages.Ratingsofwomen,andofmenfromstudies
conductedinthe1970s,demonstratethatthelooksofyoungerpeoplearerated
onaveragemorefavorablythanthoseofolderpeople.Eventhoughinterviewers
wereexplicitlyinstructedtoadjust“forageandsex,”theycouldn’t.
The differences in ratings by age are not small. Of women in the 18–29
group, 45 percent were rated at least above-average, while only 18 percent of
women50–64wereratedthatfavorably,aremarkabledrop-off.Thedeclinein
perceived looks with age is smaller among men, with 36 percent of men ages
18–29 rated above-average, while 21 percent of men 50–64 were rated that
favorably.Ageisharsheronourperceptionsofwomen’slooks.
Thereisnothinguniqueaboutthedifferencesinperceivedbeautybyagein
ourWesternculture.EveninChina,wherethestereotypeisoneofgreatrespect
forolderpeople,youngerpeople’sbeautyisratedmorepositively.Theaverage
ratingofpeopleages22–34 intheShanghaidatawas3.5;thatofpeopleages
35–49 was 3.4, while people 50 and over received ratings that only averaged
3.3.
12
The Chinese observers were no more able to separate beauty from age
thantheirAmericancounterparts.
Whytheseagedifferencespersistisnotatopicforthisbook—theirexistence
isallthatisimportant,asthecorrelationofperceivedbeautywithagedictates
thatanystudyoftheimpactofbeautymustadjustforageifwebelievethatage
mightalso affecttheoutcome. Itisinteresting, though,to speculate whythese
differences arise. It might be that people’s inability to adjust mentally for age
when they rateothers’ looks is evolutionarily valuable. We are conditioned to
believethatyouthandbeautygotogether,sincethatbeliefencouragesmatingat
atimewhenfecundityisnearitsmaximum.
13
Thisevidenceonbeautyandagedoesnotcomparethesamepeopleovertheir
lifetimes, and no large-scale study has followed the same people’s looks over
largepartsoftheirlives.Smallerstudieshavedonethis,though,takingpictures
ofpeopleatanearlyageandaskingraterstoratethemandphotosofthesame
people taken much later in life. The ratings were very highly correlated. The
generalconclusionis,“Uglyducklingsgenerallyblossomintouglyducks.”
14
Whatisitaboutaperson’sfacethatleadsmostobserverstoviewitasgood-
looking? What characteristics of another person’s face cause most of us to
consider it plain or even homely? The answers to these questions are not
requiredforourpurposeshere:Solongaspeopleagreeaboutothers’looks,and
so long as we can adjust for any systematic differences across culture, age,
gender, race, or other characteristics in how looks are viewed, we can use
observers’commonagreementsaboutindividuals’lookstoanalyzetheimpacts
oflooksonoutcomesandevenonsuccessinavarietyofareas.
Althoughnoteconomic,thesequestionsarefascinating;andtheyhavebeen
studied by a number of social psychologists. The leading work, by my
University of Texas colleague Judith Langlois, has produced a number of
interestingresults,amongwhichare:(1)Agreementonwhatconstituteshuman
beauty, and especially human ugliness, is formed very early in life—probably
during infancy. (2) Symmetry is beauty—a symmetric face is considered
beautiful,whileincreasinglyasymmetricfacesareviewedasincreasinglyugly.
15
CANWEBECOMEMOREBEAUTIFUL?
The evidence makes it clear that people’s looks relative to those of others of
theiragedonotchangegreatlyovertheirlifetimes.Butwithcommonagreement
on looks, why don’t people alter them to meet the commonly agreed-upon
standardsofbeauty ofthesociety wheretheylive?Ifbeautycanpayoff,why
notbecomebeautiful?
Theprospectofbecomingbetter-lookingisendlesslyappealingtopeople.But
even fiction, such as the movie Face-Off with John Travolta, recognizes that
greatly changing one’s looks is exceedingly difficult. Procedures to remove
blemishes and wrinkles are done all the time, as is evidenced by actors,
actresses, and politicians who have “had a lot of work done,” using the
Hollywoodterminology.In2007,Americansreceivedover4.6millioninjections
of Botox, had 285,000nose-reshaping surgeries, and 241,000 eyelidsurgeries.
Allofthiswasgoodbusinessforplasticsurgeons,tothetuneof$12billionon
cosmeticplasticsurgery.
16
Citizensofotherwealthycountriesarelessweddedtotheseprocedures,but
they too devote substantial resources to them. In 2006, Britons devoted about
$800 million to cosmetic procedures, about one-third as much per capita as
Americans,butenoughtoleadtheEUonaper-capitabasis.Thiswasfourtimes
morethantheyhadspentin2001.ItaliansrankedsecondinEuropeinspending
oncosmeticsurgery,Francecamethird,closelyfollowedbyGermany.
17
While fictional beautification methods may convert “3” or even “1” people
into“5’s,”theirreal-worldcounterpartsdonotandcannotremovetheessential
asymmetries that detract from how their beauty is perceived by the rest of
humankind.Theeffortscanhelp,totheextentthatperceptionsofhumanbeauty
arebasedincharacteristicsotherthanthesymmetryoffacialfeatures.Weknow
thatthebeautyofyoungerpeopleisperceivedmorepositivelythanthatoftheir
elders,sothatattemptingtofindsurgicalfountainsofyouthwillhelp improve
howourbeautyisperceived.Nonetheless,thesechangesarelikelytobesmall.
Perhapsthepayoffstoplasticsurgeryaresimplynotgreatenoughtojustify
thespendingthatmightmakeonesubstantiallymorebeautiful.Perhapstheyare,
butthecostsoftheimprovement,bothindollartermsandinpainandsuffering,
are too large to get people to undergo the surgery. These possibilities are
suggestedbysomeresultsdescribingexamplesofplasticsurgeryinKorea.For
most people, the potential economic gains from the improvements in beauty
wereveryfarfromjustifyingeventhemonetarycostoftheprocedure,muchless
thepsychologicalcost—the“painandsuffering”—ofundergoinganysurgery.
18
If plastic surgery cannot convert usall tobeauties, orwe cannotafford the
costofsurgery,orwedon’twanttobearthepainofthesurgerythatwouldbe
requiredtoaccomplishthis,maybeasimplerapproachwouldwork:Buybetter
clothing,usemorecosmetics,getbettercoiffed,etc.Magazinesandnewspaper
columns are devoted to “dressing for success” and “beauty makeovers,”
includingrecommendationsoftheappropriateclothing,hairstyle,manicure,etc.
Doesthiskindofspendingreallywork?Canwemakeourselvesmorebeautiful
byspendingmoreonnon-surgicalmethodsofbeautyenhancement?
TheShanghaisurveycollectedinformationontheamountthateachwoman
spenteachmonthonclothing,cosmetics,andhaircare,aswellasonherlooks,
as rated by the interviewer. Comparing the woman who spent the average
amount on these items per month, to another who spent nothing, the average
woman’sspendingonlyraisedherlooksfrom3.31to3.36.Onemightthinkthat
thesewomencoulddobetterbyspendingstillmore;anditistruethatincreasing
spending to five times the average (over 20 percent of average household
income)wouldraisetheratingoftheaveragewoman’sbeautyto3.56.Butthe
datamakeitveryclearthattheextraeffectofthisspendingdiminishesthemore
onehasalreadyspent.
19
Many popular stories suggest that people believe that wardrobe, hairstyle,
cosmetics, and surgery will improve their economic outlook.
20
The evidence
indicates that this is simply wrong: in the Chinese study each dollar spent on
improvingbeautybroughtbackonlyfourcentsonaverage.Justasmuchofour
spending on health may not increase our longevity, but may let us enjoy life
more,sotooitmaymakesensetospendonplasticsurgeryandbetterclothes.
Thebestreasonforthiskindofspendingisthatitmakesyouhappier.Itisnota
goodinvestmentifyouseekonlythenarrowgoalofeconomicimprovement.
Somedaytechnologymayallowustoreachthepointwherewecanimprove
ourbeautyeasilyandwithoutgreatcost.Rightnow,though,wearesofaraway
from that point that for most of us the beauty that we have attained as young
adults is not going to be greatly altered, compared to the beauty of our
contemporaries,bynaturalchangesthatoccurasweage,norbyanysurgicalor
cosmeticeffortsthatweundertaketoimproveit.Barringdisfiguringaccidents,
wearebasicallystuckwithwhatnatureandperhapsearlynurturehavegivenus.
THESTAGEISSET
The array of evidence presented here provides the background for discussing
howaneconomicwayofthinkingabout beautymightproceed—howwhatwe
know about human perceptions of human beauty conditions the analysis of
beauty’seffects.Themainconsistentresultsare:
1. Most important of all, there is substantial agreement among observers
aboutwhatconstitutesfacialbeauty.Beautyisintheeyeofthebeholder,
but most beholders view beauty similarly. Some people are consistently
regarded as above-average or even beautiful, while others are generally
regardedasplainorevendownrighthomely.
2.Inmanystudies,morepeopleareratedasgood-thanasbad-looking.
3. Beauty is fleeting—and youth is beauty. Even when we are asked to
accountfor individuals’agesin judgingtheir looks,wejust cannotdo it.
Peopletendtorateyoungadultsasmoreattractivethanolderpeople.
4.Peoplewhoareviewedasrelativelygood-lookingwhenyoungtendtobe
ratedasrelativelygood-lookingwhenolder.
5. While looks can be altered by clothing, cosmetics, and other short-term
investments, the effects of these improvements are minor. Even plastic
surgerydoesn’tmakeahugedifference.Theoldadage,“Youcan’tmakea
silkpurseoutofasow’sear,”appliestohumanlooksaswellastoporcine
purses. Even with today’s technology and lower costs, we are generally
stuckwithwhatnaturehasgivenusinthewayoflooks.
6.Women’slooksareperceiveddifferentlyfrommen’s—observersaremore
likelytoratewomenasbeautifulorugly,andaremorelikelytodisagree
aboutwomen’slooks.
Taking all theseconsiderations together, our agreementon what constitutes
beauty allows sufficient scope for beauty to affect behavior in many facets of
economiclife.Becausepeopleagreeaboutothers’lookstoatleastsomeextent,
marketsforlabor,mates,credit,andnodoubtothermarkets,canbeaffectedin
ways that alter how participants in those markets behave and that help to
determinethebenefitsthattheyobtain.
PARTII
BeautyontheJob:
WhatandWhy
CHAPTER3
BeautyandtheWorker
THECENTRALQUESTIONS
Everybody assumes that better-looking people make more money. But why
shouldthatbe?Isiteventrue?Andifitistrue,howmuchmoredotheymake?
Putsimply,howmuchextradoesagood-lookingworkerearnthananaverage-
looking worker? How much less than an average-looking worker does a bad-
looking worker make? These sound like simple questions, but they aren’t.
Becausebeautymayberelatedtoothercharacteristicsthatworkerspossess,we
needtoseparateouttheeffectsofbeautyonincomefromthoseofotherthings
thatmayberelatedtobothbeautyandincome.Answerstothesequestionsare
the most widely available in the burgeoning literature in pulchronomics—the
economicsofbeauty.Wehaveaprettygoodfeeltodayforthegeneralsizesof
thebeautypremiumandtheuglinesspenalty.
Does beauty affect income differently for men and women? Does it affect
income differently among older workers than among younger workers? How
aboutbyraceorethnicity?WhileIconcentrateontheUnitedStatesthroughout
mostofthisbook,onewonderswhethertheimpactsofbeautyonincomesdiffer
betweentheUnitedStatesandothercountries.Isthereaspecial“hang-up”with
beauty in the American labor market that produces unusually large effects on
incomes compared to elsewhere? How have gains in income that result from
one’sbeautychangedovertime?Areweoutgrowingafixationonlooks,ordoes
theeffectoflooksinlabormarketsloomevenlarger?
HOWCANBEAUTYAFFECTEARNINGS?
Imagineaworldwithonlytwocompanies,eachwithasinglebosswhomakes
allthehiringdecisions.CallthebossesCathyandDeb.Theircompaniesmake
completely different products—they do not compete with each other in what
they sell; and each employs half of the workersin this imaginaryworld. Both
Cathy and Deb like to surround themselves with workers whom they view as
beautiful.Doingsomakesthemfeelbetterandenhancestheirwell-beingbeyond
thetremendousprofitstheywillearnfromtheirworkers’efforts.Alltheworkers
are equally productive—each has the same set of skills, each can help the
employerproduceasmuchasanyotherworkercan.Allworkersworkthesame
numberofhoursperyear.Halftheworkersareclonedfromoneparent,Al;the
otherhalfareclonedfromanotherparent,Bob.AllAlworkerslookalike,asdo
allBobworkers;butanAlworkerlooksdifferentfromaBobworker.
HowmuchwilleachAlworkerbepaid?HowmuchwilleachBobworkerbe
paid?WeknowthateachAlworkerwillearnthesameaseveryotherAlworker
—theyareidenticalinallrespects.ThesameistrueforeachoftheBobworkers
—theytooareidenticaltoeachother.TheonlyissueishowAlworkers’wages
willdifferfromBobworkers’wages.
Becausethey,likepeoplegenerally,sharecommonstandardsofbeauty,it’s
likely that Cathy and Deb think somewhat similarly about the looks of their
potential employees. What if both Cathy and Deb think that Al workers are
beautiful,whileBobworkersarenot?IfAlandBobworkerswerepaidthesame
wage,bothCathyandDebwouldwanttohirealltheAlworkers.Butthereare
onlyenoughAlworkersforoneofthem.Theonlywaythatcompetitionforthe
AlworkerscanassignthemtoCathyorDebisifthewagesofAlworkersare
biduptothepointwheretheirextrapayjustoffsetstheextrasatisfactionthatthe
“winning”employergetsfromemployingtheAlworkers.
Towinthe competition for the(good-looking)Al workers, Cathy mustpay
them a premium,just enough to outbid Deb. Her costs are higher than Deb’s,
who is stuck with the Bob workers who both Deb and she view as ugly. But
Cathy is just as happy about her employees as Deb, since her extra costs are
offsetbythe extra satisfactionshe gets fromemployingthe Al workerswhom
Debandshebothviewasbeautiful.Withacommon standardofbeauty,labor
markets establish premium pay for the good-looking workers—or, viewed in
reverse, penalty pay for the ugly workers—based on the extent to which
employersvaluelooks.InthiscasethepremiumistheamountthatCathyhasto
paytoovercomeDeb’sdesireforthegood-lookingAlworkers.
ThisexampleassumedthatCathy’sandDeb’spreferencesfortheirworkers’
beautydeterminewhatwageswouldbe.Whatif,though,CathyandDebdon’t
reallycareabouttheirworkers’looks,buttheircustomerscareaboutthelooksof
theworkerswhomakethegoodstheybuy,ormorerealistically,aboutthelooks
of the workers who are selling to them? If both Cathy’s and Deb’s customers
prefer Al-type workers, Al-type workers will receive higher wages than Bob-
typeworkers.Theoutcomesarethesame,whetheritisCathy’sandDeb’sown
preferences that determine the effect of looks on wages, or whether their
behaviorjustexpressestheircustomers’preferences.
Whose preferences generate premium pay for beauty, and penalties for
ugliness, can’t be determined just by showing the existence and size of those
differencesinearnings—itrequiresadeeperinvestigationofunderlyingcauses.
Wemustfirstseewhetherandbyhowmuchbeautyisrewarded,aswedointhis
chapter. We need to discover how it affects people’s choices of what work to
undertake;andweneedtoseehowcompanies’salesandprofitsrelatetotheir
employees’looks.
HOWMUCHMOREDOGOOD-LOOKINGPEOPLE
MAKE?
To begin answering these questions, take the most important: To what extent
doesbeautyaffecttheearningsofthetypicalworker?Onitsfacethisseemsto
be a simple task: Find a large group of individuals, randomly chosen from a
country’s population; get measures of their looks, by one of the methods we
havediscussed;obtaininformationontheirearnings;andcomparetheirearnings
totheirlooks.
ThisisnotsoeasytodofortheUnitedStatesasonemightthinkorhope—
the most recent nationally random data that provide this information are from
surveys collected in the 1970s—the data underlying table 2.1. Regrettably, no
nationally representative set of data since the 1970s contains information on
earnings and also ratings of the respondents’ beauty. This means that these
effects are best described as what were the effects of beauty on earnings. But
using these data we can get an initial picture of how beauty and earnings are
relatedinthegeneralpopulation.
Usingtheselargerandomsamplesofwomenandmen,wecancomparetheir
earnings to the ratings of their looks. Compared to the average group (people
ratedas3onthe5to1scale),below-averagelookingwomen(rated2or1onthe
scale) earn 3 percent less, while below-average looking men earn 22 percent
less.Above-averagelookingwomen(rated 4 or 5 on the scale) earn 4 percent
morethantheaverage-looking,whileabove-averagelookingmenearn3percent
more.Thereisapremiumforgoodlooks,apenaltyforbadlooks.Exceptforthe
penaltyforthe11percentofmenwhoselooksareratedasbelow-average,these
differences in earnings are not large; but they are in the directions that you
wouldexpect.
These simple differences are interesting; but are they genuine, or do they
merely reflect the strong possibility that beauty and other things that increase
one’searningsarerelated?Thenumberof“otherthings”ispotentiallyhuge;but
a thorough approach would take anything that has repeatedly been shown to
affectearnings,andwouldthenadjustforitsimpactsinordertoisolatetheeffect
ofbeautyonearnings.Theseotherfactorsinclude:
• Education (increasing earnings)—what if better-looking people are better
educated?
•Age(increasingearningsuptosomepoint,perhapstothemid-fiftiesfora
typicalworker,thenreducingearnings)—weknowthatageandbeautyare
related
•Health(healthierpeopleearnmore)—beautymayberelatedtohealth
•Unionmembership(increasingearnings)
•Maritalstatus(positiveeffectsamongmen,negativeeffectsamongwomen)
—beautymayberelatedtowhetheryouaremarriedornot
•Race/ethnicity(minoritiesearnlessthannon-Hispanicwhites)
•Sizeofcity(higherearningsinbiggercitiesandinmetropolitanasopposed
tonon-metropolitanandruralareas)
•Region(higherintheEastthanintheSouth)
•Nativity(immigrantsearnlessthannatives)
•Familybackground(loweramongpeoplewhoseparentswereimmigrants)
•Sizeofcompany(higherinbigfirms)orplant(higherinlargerplants)
•Yearswiththecompany(increasingearningsuntillateinaperson’stenure
withthecompany)
Numerousstudieshaveshownthateachofthesefactorsaffectsearnings.Since
mostorevenallofthemmightdiffersystematicallywithanindividual’slooks,
toisolatetheeffectoflooksonearningsweneedtoadjustearningsusingdataon
asmanyofthemaswecan.
Table3.1showstheaverageimpactsofbeautycombiningdatafromthetwo
samplesofAmericansinthe1970s.Thepenaltiesforbelow-averagelooks,and
the premia for above-average looks, are based on statistical analyses that
adjustedearningsformostoftheseotherfactorsinordertoisolatetheeffectof
differences in beauty. An asterisk (*) denotes that the impact is statistically
meaningful—thatwecanbefairlysurethatlookshavesomeeffectonearnings.
TABLE3.1
PercentageImpactsofLooksonEarnings,U.S.,1970s(comparedtoaverage-lookingworkers,rated3),
AdjustedforManyOtherDeterminantsofEarnings
Notethatthesenumbersareinthesamedirectionsasthenumbersthatdidnot
accountforalltheotherdeterminantsofearnings.Theydochange—theseother
determinants of earnings do matter; but the basic conclusion, that there is a
penaltytoearningsforbadlooksandpremiumpayforgoodlooks,isunaltered.
Ifasked,“WhatistheoveralleffectoflooksonearningsintheU.S.?”thebest
answer, based on table 3.1, is thatthe bottom 15 percent of women by looks,
those rated as below-average (2 or 1), received 4 percent lower pay than
average-looking women. The top one-third of women by looks, those ratedas
above-average(4or5),received8percentmorethanaverage-lookers.Formen,
thecomparablefiguresarea13percentpenaltyanda4percentpremium.
There is nothing written in stone about these numbers. No doubt, if other
nationally representative data were available, the estimates of these effects
woulddiffer.Butwecanbefairlysurethattheeffectsofbeautyonearningsare
intheballparkofthefiguresintable3.1.
Thesenumbersmeanlittlebythemselveswithoutcomparisonstotheeffects
ofotherdeterminantsofdifferencesinearnings.Howdoesthe17percentexcess
of good-looking men’s earnings over those of bad-looking men’s (13 percent
penaltyplus 4percent premium)comparetotheeffects ofdifferences inother
characteristicsonmen’searnings?Howdoesthe12percentshortfallofplainor
homelywomen’searningsfromabove-averageorbeautifulwomen’s(4percent
penaltyplus8percentpremium)comparetoothereffectsonwomen’searnings?
Byfarthemostthoroughlyexamineddeterminantofearningsiseducation.A
good estimate for the United States today is that each additional year of
schooling raises the earnings of otherwise identical workers by around 10
percent.
1
This effect is a bit more than that of women’s good looks; and it
impliesthatmen’sgoodlookshaveanimpactontheirearningsatleastaslarge
asanadditionalone-and-a-halfyearsofschool.
Amongtheotherfactorsthataffectearningsareworkexperienceandwhether
aworkplaceisunionized.Foraforty-year-oldmantheimpactofgoodlookson
earningsisaboutthesameasthatofanadditionalfiveyearsofworkexperience,
and also about the same as that of working in a unionized workplace.
2
The
effectsofbeautyonearningsarenotimmense,buttheyarecertainlysubstantial.
Whenviewedinthecontextofanentireworkinglife,theyseemevenlarger.
In 2010, the average worker earned about $20 per hour. Averaging male and
female workers, someone employed 2,000 hours per year over a work life of
fortyyearswouldearn$1.60million.Butwithbelow-averagelookstheworker
would earn only $1.46 million, while with above-average looks, lifetime
earningswouldbe$1.69million.
3
A3or4percentpremiumforgood-looking
workersdoesn’tseemthatbig;butplacedintoa lifelongframework,$230,000
extra earnings for being good-looking instead of bad-looking no longer seems
small. Comparing the bad-looking to the average-looking worker the effect is
smaller—“only”$140,000overalifetime—butstillquitelarge.Comparingthe
average-lookingtothe above-averagelooking worker the effect is smallerstill
—“only”$90,000overalifetime—butstillsubstantial.
Alloftheseeffectsrefertoaverages:Theytellusthatatypicalgood-looking
malewillearn4percentmorethanthetypicalaverage-lookingmale,andthata
typicalbelow-average-lookingwomanwillearn4percentlessthanthetypical
average-lookingwoman.Thisdoesnotmeanthateachgood-lookingmalewill
earn4percentmorethaneachaverage-lookingmale.Wehaveseenthatthereare
manyotherfactorsthataffectearnings,andthesewilldifferbetweenmenwhose
looks are viewed as the same. Even more important, there is tremendous
randomnessinearningsthatisunrelatedtolooksoranyoftheotherthingswe
canmeasureandthataffectearnings.Amongarandomlychosengroupofmale
workers,orfemaleworkers,atleasthalfofthedifferencesinearningsaredueto
things that we can’t measure; and among those that we can measure, looks
accountforonlyasmallfractionofthedifferences.Looksdomatteralot;but
otherthingsmattermuchmore.
Becausesofewpeopleareclassifiedasbeautiful(rated5)orhomely(rated
1),itisnotpossibletodistinguishstatisticallytheimpactofbeingbeautifulfrom
being above-average (rated 4), or of being homely from being plain (rated 2).
Despite that, and even though the differences are not statistically meaningful,
additional analyses of these same data show that the beautiful man or woman
earns more than the above-average, and the homely earn less than the plain.
Extreme looks are uncommon, but they generally produce extreme effects on
successinlabormarkets.
Theword“generally”iskeyhere.Manypeoplebelievethata“bimboeffect”
exists—that extremely good-looking women are somehow penalized in labor
markets. In my own research I have found only one bit of evidence for this
effect:Inastudyofattorneys,theverybest-lookingfemaleattorneyswereless
likely to achieve partnership before their fifth year after graduation from law
schoolthanaverage-lookingwomenattorneys.
4
Liketheirbrethren,though,their
extreme beauty did give them higher earnings. There may be bimbo effects in
someinstances,buttheyareprettyrare.
There have been many efforts to measure the effect of beauty on earnings
usingdataonindividualsinothercountries.Interestinthetopicishardlylimited
to the United States. All of these have tried to adjust for many of the same
determinantsofearningsthatIhaveusedtoisolatetheeffectsofbeautyinthe
United States. The availability of information on all these measures differs
across countries and sets of data, so that the studies are neither entirely
comparabletothosefromtheUnitedStatesnortoeachother.Theyarealsonot
comparable for another crucial reason: We saw that there are international
differences in the willingness of raters of beauty to classify people as being
below-average in looks. Americans are remarkably willing to make these
relatively harsh judgments when they interview respondents or evaluate their
photographs.Thistoomightcausetheestimatedeffectsofbeautyelsewhereto
differfromthoseintheUnitedStates.
IhavefoundstudiesforAustralia;Canada;Shanghai,China;Korea;andthe
United Kingdom.
5
They show that in other countries too there are significant
negative impacts on earnings of being below-average in looks. In most cases
therearealsopositiveeffectsofbeingabove-average.Nogeneralizationsabout
cross-countrydifferencesintheeffectsof beautyonearnings arepossible.But
the negative effects of being below-average in looks typically exceed the
positiveeffects of being above-average.One explanation is thatso few people
are classified as below-average in these studies that being called “below-
average”indicatesseriouslydeficientlooks.
Althoughmakingcomparisonsoftheseeffectstothoseshownintable3.1for
theUnitedStatesisdifficult,theeffectsofbeautyinothercountriesdonotseem
that different from those in the United States. Theeffects in the UnitedStates
maybe somewhatlarger, butnothugely so.As intheUnitedStates,so tooin
mostofthesecountries,goodlooksarerewarded,andbadlooksarepenalized,
evenafteraccountingforalargevarietyofotherfactorsthataffectearnings.
TheAmericandataclearlyaresomewhatoutdated.Withcurrentdatawould
wefindthesameeffects?PerhapsAmericansarenolongersoconcernedabout
looks when they react to co-workers, employees, or people selling them a
product or a service. Perhaps the opposite has occurred, so that, given the
preoccupationwithlooksintheAmericanmediatoday,withtheriseofcelebrity
magazines,andwiththegrowthofthesocialnetworkingInternetsite,Facebook,
theeffectsareevengreaterthantheywereinthe1970s.
The absence of data makes it impossible to obtain updated estimates of the
impactofbeautyonearningsforthegeneralpopulation,butbeautyratingsfrom
anationalsurveyofyoungadultsintheearly2000shavebeenusedtoexamine
this question. Looking only at male high school graduates, going from
“unattractive” (rating of 2 on the commonly used 5 to 1 scale) to “very
attractive”(ratingof4)generatedanincreaseinearningsofcloseto11percent
among young women, and 17 percent among young men.
6
These effects are
remarkablyclosetothoseintable3.1,offeringahintthatperhapstheeffectsof
beautyonearningsremainsubstantialandsubstantiallyunchanged.
Withoutanyadditional evidence on thegeneralpopulation,there is no sure
way of deciding this issue. Either possibility may be correct. My best guess,
though, absent any reason to believe that labor markets have changed in one
directionortheother,isthattheeffectsofbeautytodayarenotmuchdifferent
fromthosethatprevailedintheUnitedStatesinthe1970s.
Theeffectsoflooksonearningsmightwellchangeoverthebusinesscycle,
as the economy moves between recession and full employment. From the
employer’s side of labor markets, having more unemployed workers available
allows greater choice about workers’ characteristics. In bad times, Cathy and
Deb might have more scope to indulge their desires for beautiful workers. In
discussingraceinlabormarkets,wegenerallybelievethatunemploymentgives
employers more latitude to discriminate.
7
If looks are treated the same way,
beautymighthelpagood-lookingworkermoreduringarecession,whenthereis
morecompetitionfromotherjobseekers.Itseffectswillbelesswhenworkers
arescarceandemployerscannotaffordtobesochoosy.
No study has looked at this question generally. But among law school
graduateswhoenteredthelabormarketwhenjobsfornewattorneyswerevery
plentiful,theimpactofdifferencesinlooksontheirearningswassmall.Among
attorneyswhosoughtworkwhenjobswerelessreadilyavailable,earningswere
morestronglyaffectedbydifferencesintheirbeauty.Thissinglecomparisonis
not definitive, but itdoes suggestthat the effects of beautyon earnings might
riseinrecessions.
ISBEAUTYTHEREALCAUSE?
Therearealotofotherfactorsthatmightaffectearningsandthatcouldnotbe
accounted for in most of these studies. One concern is that beauty may just
reflect self-esteem. Perhaps people’s self-confidence manifests itself in their
behavior,sothattheirlooksareratedmorehighly,andtheirself-esteemmakes
themmoredesirableandhigher-paidemployees.TheCanadianstudyincludeda
setofquestionsthatpsychologistsusetomeasureself-esteem.Self-esteemand
looks were positively related—but the correlations in these data were quite
weak:Thetypicalgood-lookingpersonwasonlyslightlymorelikelytoexpress
substantialself-esteemthan the typical bad-looking person. Adjusting earnings
for the effects of self-esteem, workers who expressed greater self-esteem did
earnmore.Butthisadditionaladjustmentdidnotchangetheestimatedeffectsof
looks on earnings in the Canadian data that had information on this
characteristic. The constancy of the beauty effect suggests that its impacts on
earningsdonotarisebecausebeautyenhancesaworker’sself-esteem.
Yet another possibility is that beauty and the attractiveness of one’s
personality are positively related, and that it is the general sparkle of one’s
personality, not one’s beauty, that increases earnings. Measuring the
attractiveness of someone’s personality is more subjective than measuring
someone’s beauty, butboth have been measured for the same group of young
Americansearlyinthetwenty-firstcentury.Askingwhetheradjustingearnings
for the attractiveness of personality affected the implied impacts of beauty,
researchersfoundonlyaslightimpactonyoungAmericanadults.
8
TheBritish
studyofbeautydidadjustformeasuresofaperson’ssociabilityatagesixteen,
and that adjustment didn’t affect the estimates of the impact of beauty on
earnings in adulthood either. Generally, the impact of beauty on earnings is
essentiallyindependentofanyrelationbetweenbeautyandpersonality.
It might be that the beautiful are more intelligent too, so that what we
attribute to beauty is more appropriately attributable to intelligence. This is
possible;butinlightofpopulardiscussion(theuglynerd?),theoppositeseems
justaslikely—thatfailingtoaccountfordifferencesinintelligencemeansthat
wemightbeunder-estimatingtheimpactofbeautyonearnings.
None of the studies of random samples of Americans or people in other
countriescontainsagoodmeasureofintelligence,sowecan’tbesureaboutthis.
ButthedataonyoungadultsintheUnitedStatesintheearly2000sdocontaina
measure of intelligence. Adjusting for differences among individuals in both
intelligence and beauty, those data show that the effect of beauty remains
substantial even among people with similar intelligence. Interestingly, the
premium for beauty is greater if you are smarter, as is the penalty for being
unattractive.
9
Looking at the same question in the context of a particular occupation, the
data on attorneys included a partial measure of intelligence (the score on the
LawSchoolAptitudeTest—LSAT).Therewasnorelationbetweenastudent’s
LSAT and his or her looks. This supports my guess that there generally is at
mostatinycorrelationbetweenbeautyandintelligence;sofailingtoaccountfor
intelligencedoesn’taffecttheestimatedimpactofbeautyonearnings.
In all the studies summarized so far, the assumption has been that the
interviewers’ratingsofbeautyarebasedontheinterviewees’faces. We made
thatassumptionin chapter2,arguingthatobservers canassessthebeautyof a
face independently of the weight and height of an individual. This is an
importantproblem,foriftheycan’t,andifweightand/orheightaffectearnings,
then all the inferences made here so far would be confounding the effects of
beauty on earnings with those of height and weight. So the first question is
whether weight and height, or some combination of the two, even affect
earnings.
Fortunately,alotofresearchbyeconomistsandothersoveralongperiodof
time, both in the United States and other countries, has looked at this. The
answersseemfairlyclear,forbothweightandheight.Obesitylowersearnings,
allelseequal,andthatisespeciallytrueamongwomen.
10
Soifpeoplejudgethe
appearanceofobesepeopleasbeingbelowaverage—ifobesityequalsugliness
—theapparentnegative effectofbad looks on earningscould just be masking
theeffectofbeingobese.Studiesontheimpactofheightonearningshavealso
used data from many countries, including the United States, Britain, and
China.
11
Thegeneralresultisthatheightalsomatters,withthedifferencebeing
that,unlikeweight, thepositiveeffects ofheightonearningsarelargeramong
menthanamongwomen.
Todisentangletheeffects,weneedtolookatstudiesthatincludebothbeauty
and weight/height to describe interpersonal differences in earnings. The
Americandataunderlyingtable3.1,andtheBritishstudy,includedinformation
onbothheightandweight.Adjustingfordifferencesintheheightandweightof
theintervieweeshardlychangedtheestimatedeffectsofbeautyonearnings.A
study of job applications in Sweden similarly suggested that the impacts of
beauty on the chance of a person getting a job interview were mostly
independentoftheeffectsoftheapplicant’sweight.
12
Howcanweightandheightnotchangetheimpactsofbeautyonearnings,if
theythemselvesaffectearnings?Theanswerisveryclearandalsoencouraging:
Observersareabletoseparatebeautyfromphysique—therelationshipbetween
ratings of beauty and height/weight is very weak. Physiognomy and physique
bothaffectearnings,buttheyaremostlyindependentofeachother.Afaceona
talloroverweightbodyisjudgedaboutthesameastheidenticalfaceonashort
orthinbody.Beautyis,withinbounds,moreorlessindependentofphysique.
Onemightalsowonderwhetheritisaperson’sbeautythatisaffectinghisor
herearnings,orwhetherbeautyisjustratedhigheramongthosewhoarebetter
dressed. Dressing better does raise perceived beauty, but only slightly; but
perhaps those who dress better also earn more, so that some of the effect on
earnings that we have attributed to differences in beauty stems instead from
differences in dress. In several studies, earnings have also been adjusted for
differencesindress(forexamples,whetheramaninaphotographwaswearinga
coat and tie, whether a woman was wearing a blouse). Having a photograph
depictingoneselfdressedmoreformallyisassociatedwithhigherearnings.But,
becausetherelationshipbetweenbeautyanddressisquiteweak,thisadditional
adjustmenthardlychangestheinferencesaboutthesizeoftheimpactofbeauty
onearnings.Thebeautyeffectdoesnotarisefromanycorrelationofbeautyand
beingbetterdressed.
WHYAREBEAUTYEFFECTSSMALLERAMONG
WOMEN?
Thecarefulreaderwillnotethattheestimatedeffectsonearningsarelargerfor
maleworkersthanforfemaleworkers.ThisistrueintheAmericandata,andit
isalsogenerallytrueinstudiesforothercountries.Howcanthisbe?Don’tthe
beauty ratings summarized in chapter 2 suggest that people make finer
distinctionsaboutwomen’slooksthanaboutmen’s?Afterbeingpresentedwith
theresultsofsomeearlystudiesin1993,aleadingobserveroftheroleofbeauty
commented, “Women face greater discrimination when it comes to looks,”
essentially dismissing the facts that confronted her but that contradicted her
preconceptions.
13
AlbertEinstein’scomment,“Itiseasiertosplitanatomthana
preconception,”isrelevantinstudyingbeautytoo.
14
Foravarietyofreasons,someofwhichIdiscussinlaterchaptersinvarious
contexts,thisdismissal,andthesegeneralbeliefs,mayberight,eventhoughthe
inference that the earnings penalty for bad looks among women is larger than
among men is also correct. To see why, ask what we would observe if both
genders faced the same penalty on their earnings, say 10 percent for being
below-average, and the same premium for having above-average looks, say 5
percent. Assume too that all adults were working for pay. What if there were
also no differences by gender in the underlyingdistributions of beautyratings
(eventhoughweknowtheratingsofwomenaremoredispersed)?Thenitwould
bethecasethatcarefulmeasurementsoftheeffectsofbeautyonearningswould
showthattheyarethesameforwomenandmen.
Thispointsoundsreasonable,butitiswrong,becausetheassumptionthatall
adultsworkisincorrect:Evenin2008,afteralongriseinthefractionofadult
women at work or looking for work (in the labor force), only 72 percent of
Americanwomenages25–54wereinthelaborforce,comparedto86percentof
Americanmeninthatagegroup.Womenaremuchmorelikelythanmentostay
outofthelaborforce.Thisisnotsurprising,sincemassiveamountsofeconomic
evidencedemonstratethatwomen’sdecisionsaboutwhethertoworkforpayare
more responsive to pay, other incentives, and the presence of young children
thanaremen’s.
15
Gender differences in labor-force participation would be irrelevant here if
non-participationwererandom—ifthechoiceofstayingoutofthelabormarket
were unrelated to beauty. But it is not reasonable to expect that the choice is
random.Peoplechoosetoworkifthegainsfromworkingexceedthegainsfrom
staying at home. The gains from working are what you can earn—and beauty
affects what you earn. The gains from staying at home are the enjoyment of
leisure and the value to you and your family of what you do while at home
(cooking,cleaning,fixingtheplumbing,takingcareofkids,watchingtelevision,
etc.)andsavingsofcostsforcommutingandchildcare.
Itispossiblethatbetterlooksmightmakewomensomuchmoreproductive
athomeastooffsetthepaygainstheywouldobtain,butthatseemsunlikely.It
seemsmuchmorelikelythattheincentivesthatbeautyprovideswomentowork
for pay, and the disincentives that bad looks give women to avoid the labor
market, are more important than differences in the value of time at home by
looks. We would expect better-looking women to be working more than bad-
lookingwomen.
Intheend,thisisanempiricalissue.OneoftheAmericandatasetsfromthe
1970sandtheCanadiandataallowustoinfertheeffectsofbeautyonwhether
womenormenwillchoosetoworkornot.Inbothsetsofdata,thereisnoeffect
ofeitherabove-orbelow-averagebeautyonwhetheramanisworkingforpay.
Butbeingabove-averageinlooksraisesthelikelihoodthatawomanworksby
about 5 percent compared to the average-looking woman. And the relatively
small fraction of women whose looks are rated below-average are about 5
percentless likelythan average-lookingwomen tobein thelabor market(and
that much more likely to stay at home). The effects of looks on a woman’s
likelihoodofworkingarenotsmall,giventhattheaverage-lookingwomanages
25–54todayhasonlya72percentchanceofworking.
AsigninacountrystoreinFredericksburg,Texas,read,“Houseworkmakes
youugly.”Thatmaybetrue;buttheevidencealsodemonstratesthatthereverse
is true: Being ugly causes women to do house work, because the gains to
workingforpayarelessthantheyareforbetter-lookingwomen.
Imadethispointtoagroupoffivehundredstudents,mostofthemMormons,
in a lecture at Brigham Young University. An unusually large percentage of
female Mormon college graduates do not workfor pay. Thewomen attending
the lecture were very upset with my comments, since they believed that, by
notingthatworse-lookingwomenarelesslikelytoworkforpay,Iwasimplying
that Mormon stay-at-home moms are bad-looking. Not at all! If Mormon
women’s looks are no different from other American women’s, the correct
inference from the response of women to the disincentives to ugly workers to
work, coupled with Mormon women’s preference for staying at home, is that
Mormon stay-at-home moms will be better looking on average than non-
Mormonstay-at-homemoms.
Thisdiscussion and theevidencethat supports itshow that oneexplanation
forthesurprisinglylargereffectoflooksonmen’sthanonwomen’searningsis
that women have much more latitude than men in choosing whether or not to
work for pay, and that beauty affects that choice. Part of the reason for the
gender difference in the effects of beauty on earnings is that beautyalters the
mix of female workers, so that the distribution of workers contains
proportionatelyfewerbelow-averagelookingwomen.Thatislesstrueformen.
DOBEAUTYEFFECTSDIFFERBYRACE?
The average beauty rating of African American respondents is essentially
identical to that of whites, but the dispersion of the ratings is less. Thismight
suggestthattheeffectsofbeautywithintheAfricanAmericanpopulationmight
besmaller,sincemostlywhiteemployersandcustomersdonotappeartobeable
todistinguishbeautyaswellamongblackemployeesasamongwhites.Perhaps;
butunfortunately,thereisnosufficientlylargenationallyrandomsampleofdata
onwhichtoexaminethispossibility.
A bit of light is shed on the issue by evidence on the role of African
Americans’skintoneontheirearnings.Skintonedoesnotequatetobeauty,but
typical employers or customers may treat it similarly to beauty. The evidence
from a smallrandomsampleofAfricanAmericanssuggeststhatlight-skinned
AfricanAmerican malesearn about12 percentmorethan domedium ordark-
skinned black men, after adjusting for many earnings-enhancing
characteristics.
16
Perhaps beauty effects on earnings are just as large among
AfricanAmericansasamongwhites.
DOBEAUTYEFFECTSDIFFERBYAGE?
Despiteinstructionstoadjustforpeople’sages,observersareincapableofrating
olderpeople’slooks ashighlyasthoseof youngerpeople.Olderpeoplein the
labor market are on average rated as less good-looking than their youngerco-
workers. Nonetheless, older people, generally up through age fifty-five or so,
tend to earn more than younger people in the same occupation, industry, and
location.The question,though,is: Ifweadjust forthesedifferences andmany
others,doestheimpactonearningsofdifferencesinappearancegrow,staythe
same, or decline as people age and gather more work experience? In succinct
terms,howdothebeautypremiumanduglinesspenaltyinthelabormarketvary
withage?
Whatmightweexpecttheanswertothisquestiontobe?Whileaveragelooks
decline with age, the dispersion of looks—the variation around the declining
average—doesn’tchangeverymuch.Itisjustthattherearemorebelow-average
people, and fewer above-average looking people. Thinking about this issue
forces us to dig more deeply into the roots of the beauty premium in labor
markets.Earlyin theirjobs,workers aretosomeextentunknownquantitiesto
their employers. The employerhas interviewedthem, examined their resumés,
testedthem,etc.;buttheirwillingnesstoworkhard,theirattitudes,andhowthey
getalongwiththeirfellowemployeesandcustomersarelesswellknowntothe
employer. The employer, in screening them, may rely on their looks as an
indicatorofsuccessalongtheseotherdimensions.Lateron,oncetheemployee
has established a record of interacting with customers, other workers, and the
boss, looks might become less important. The degree of uncertainty about the
worker’s true productivity should diminish over time. If that is true, then the
impactofbeautyonearningswilldiminishwithageandexperience.
Ontheoppositeside,earlyinacareergoodlooksmaygivetheworkeraccess
tomoreopportunitiestobuildskills,meetcustomers,impressthebossfavorably,
and so on, than would be given to a worse-looking co-worker. The beautiful
worker would have the chance to build her skills, perhaps with only small
investmentsofher time. Skills arecreatedthrough beauty in this case,butthe
enhancedskillsare mannafromheaven, in thesensethat the workerhasdone
nothingtocreateheradditionalearningpower.Rather,theskillsarethrustupon
her by virtue of her good looks. In this case the effect of looks on earnings
wouldrisewithage,anditisarealeffect,resultingfromthegrowingskillsthat
aworker’sbeautygeneratesoverhercareer.
Theevidenceismixedonthisissue.Takingthedataunderlyingtheoutcomes
intable 3.1 andmaking the sameadjustments forotherfactors, thepremiafor
goodlooks,andthepenaltiesforbadlooks,areessentiallythesameforworkers
underandoverageforty.Thisisnottrueinthedataonattorneys.Followingthe
attorneysoverthefirstfifteenyearsoftheircareers,andadjustingformanyof
thefactorsdiscussedearlierinthischapter,thereisaclearpattern.Atthestartof
their careers, beauty has only a small effect on their earnings. The impacts of
beautyonearningsrisewithexperience,whichisveryhighlycorrelatedwithage
inthisgroupofattorneys.
Onemightthinkthatbeautyofferstheyoungattorneyadvantagesinbuilding
up a client base and that, as she acquires more experience, the work that she
performedforclientswhowereattractedtoherearlyinhercareergeneratesstill
moreclientsashercareerprogresses.ThisisthesecondpossibilitythatInoted
above. Among workers in occupations where earnings are less dependent on
generating business, the effects discussed here may offset each other, as
suggested by the absenceof anydifference in the earnings-beauty relationship
by age in the United States generally. It is unlikely that there is any uniform
patternintherelationshipbetweenearningsandbeautyacrossallcountriesand
occupations. It depends on the specific nature of the occupation and on the
specificfactorsthatcauseearningstodifferamongitspractitioners.
COMPENSATINGTHEBEAUTY-DAMAGED
WORKER?
Ifyouseverelyinjuredyourbackandcouldn’tworkforyears,yourlostearnings
would usually be compensated by the person or company whose negligence
causedtheaccident.Whatifinsteadyouwereatworkandagastankexploded,
leaving your face severely scarred? Having read this far, you now know that
yourfacialdisfigurementmeansthatyouarelikelyto beearning lessover the
restofyourcareer.Andifyouhadbeenseverelydisfiguredinchildhood,your
entirecareerwouldhavebeendifferent—yourdamagedlookswouldaffectyour
earningsfromthetimeyouleftschooluntilretirement.
Should you be compensated for your potential loss of earnings? After all,
your economic losses are just as real as if your back had been broken. My
answer on this is yes; and the only economic question is how large your
compensationshouldbe.Howmuchshouldyourecover?
AssoonasthefirstbeautystudyIwrotewasmadepublicanddrewattention
from the media, I began receiving calls from attorneys involved in personal-
injurycases.Insuchcases,plaintiffs’attorneys seekdamagesfortheimpaired
earningssufferedbytheirclientsasaresultofaccidents.Withtherecognitionof
the labor-market payoff to beauty, the attorneys realized that the earnings lost
becauseoftheplaintiffs’impairedbeautywereapreviouslyunmeasuredelement
ofdamagesthattheycouldobtainfortheirclients.
OvertheyearsIhaveconsultedincasesinvolvinganexecutiveinjuredinan
oil-field explosion; several cases involving young children severely bitten by
dogs;achildmaimedinahospitalaccident;andanumberofothers.Imaginea
damagedface,perhapsthatofaburnvictim,orofachildpermanentlyscarred
byaseveredogbite.Asaneconomist,myjobisnottoopineontheextentofthe
impairmenttothevictim’slooks,buttoassumeadropinbeautyandprovidean
estimateofthesizeoftheearningslossesthattheindividualhadsufferedbased
onthatdrop.
Typicalapproachesmightinvolveassumingthataninjuredworkerhadbeen
above-averageinlooksandthattheinjuryreducedherlookstoaverage;thatshe
had been above-average and became below-average; or that she had been
average-looking and became below-average looking. These three transitions
capturethepossibledownwardchangesamongthethreecategoriesoflooksin
table 3.1. I used the estimates in that table to infer the earnings loss that one
victim, a womanwho was thirty-six years old in 2009,suffered or willin the
futuresufferasaresultofherinjury.
Toestimatetheexpectedlifetimeearningsthatshewouldreceiveabsentthe
injury, I assumed that she is typical for someone of the same race/ethnicity,
education,andgenderwhoresidesinthesamelabormarket.Soifthevictimhad
been a white male physician in a high-wage area—say, New York City—I
would assume that his lifetime earnings would have been higher, absent the
injury;ifthevictimhadbeenaminorityhighschooldropoutworkinginafast-
foodrestaurantinSouthDakota,theywouldhavebeenlower.
Weneedtomeasuretheearningsthatshewouldreceiveinthepossiblyquite
distant future, perhaps thirty years from now, and compare them to the
compensation that she should receive in 2009. The solution is simple and
standardinfinanceandeconomics:Discountthefuturedollarsbysomerateof
interest to make them comparable to dollars today. For example, taking a
standardinterestrateof3percentafterinflation,theearningsof$52,000thatshe
mightreceivein2038,atagesixty-five,isequivalentin2009toonly$20,000.
Themagnitudeofherlossdependsontheseverityoftheimpairmenttoher
beauty.Ifshewentfrombeingabove-averagetobelow-average,thelosswillbe
greater—becausethedifferenceintheimpactonearningsofthischangeislarger
thanifshewentfromaveragetobelow-average.Inhercase,dependingonhow
oneviewstheseverityoftheimpairmenttoherbeauty,thepresentvalueofthe
lostearningsoverherremainingworkinglifeisbetween$24,000and$66,000.
In each case the size of the losses will vary. It is larger if the beauty
impairment is greater, which is unsurprising. It is greater for men than for
women, because the average unimpaired man earns more than the average
unimpairedwoman,andbecausetheeffectsofdifferencesinbeautyonearnings
arelargeramongmen.Thelossesarelowerforaseven-year-oldthanafifteen-
year-old,becausethelatter’slostearningsareinthenearerfuture.Thethirty-six
year-old woman’s losses are not much bigger than a teenage girl’s losses,
because her injuryoccurred after she hadalready had the benefit of her looks
overasubstantialpartofhercareer.
Is it worthwhile thinking about the economics of beauty in the context of
injury-basedlawsuits?Aretheseearningslossesreallywortharguingabout?By
the criterion of net benefit to the plaintiff, the answer is a clear yes. The
settlement or jury award might include one-half of the projected earningsloss
fromtheimpairedbeauty.Withmysmallfee,andtheone-thirdofthesettlement
that is typically claimed by the plaintiff’s attorney, even the smallest of the
losses incurred by the thirty-six-year-old woman would net her about $7,000
beyondwhatwouldshehavereceivedhadtheeconomiceffectofherimpaired
beautybeenignored.
LOOKSMATTERFORWORKERS
The most heavily researched issue in the economics of beauty involves
measuringthe effectsof lookson earnings.Howmuchmoredo better-looking
peopleearnthanaverage-lookingpeople?Howmuchlessdobad-lookingpeople
earn?Theevidenceonthesequestionsisbynowabundantlyclear.Beinginthe
top third of looks in America generates around 5 percent more earnings as
comparedtotheearningsreceivedbytheaveragepersonwho,exceptforbeauty,
is identical. People whose looks are in the bottom seventh earn perhaps 10
percentlessthantheotherwiseidenticalaverageperson.
Inothercountries,theimpactsoflooksonearningsmaybesmallerorlarger
thanintheUnitedStates—it’shardtosay.Butthatworse-lookingworkersearn
less than their good-looking fellows appears to be a characteristic of
industrializedcountriesgenerally.Thesamemayalsobetrueinlessdeveloped
countries, and I think it is. But therejust have notbeen enough studiesof the
impactof beautyinpoor countriestoconfirm mysuspicion.The effectsdiffer
acrosscountries;butitisfairtosaythattheimpactoflooksonpayisuniversal.
CHAPTER4
BeautyinSpecific
Occupations
BEAUTYANDCHOOSINGANOCCUPATION
Youarealmostcertainlynotgoingtochoosetobecomeanoperasingerunless
you have some natural vocal gifts; and you are not going to become a
professionaltennisplayerunlessyouhaveatleastsomebasiclevelofphysical
coordination.
1
These are fairly esoteric occupations with few practitioners.
Unlikevocalabilityorphysicalcoordination,beautyisageneralcharacteristic.
How does your beauty affect the occupation you choose to enter? It seems
reasonabletobelievethatyourbeautywillhelptodeterminethecareerchoices
thatyou make asa worker. Towhat extentarebetter-looking peoplechoosing
occupationswherewethinktheirlooksmightpayoffmore?Putcrudely,does
the old saying, “A beautiful face for radio,” describe people’s behavior
generally?
If beautiful people tend to enter certain occupations, or if bad looks lead
otherstoenterdifferentoccupations,howdoesthisaffectthepayoffstobeauty
inbothtypesofoccupation?Moregenerally,aretheredifferencesacrosscareers
intheimpactsthatbeautyhasontheirpractitioners’incomes?Forexample,do
good-lookinglawyersattracthigherfees?Doprofessors’looksmatterfortheir
salaries,orforhowfavorablytheirstudentsevaluatetheirteaching?
The role of beauty is especially interesting in certain occupations.
Prostitution,forexample,isoneareawherewewouldthinkthatbeautywould
matteralot.Dogood-lookingpoliticiansdobettertoo—arepeoplemorelikely
to vote for beautiful politicians independent of their stands on the issues? In
other occupations you might think that beauty would not matter at all. Why
shoulditmatterforprofessionalathletes?Whyshouldagood-lookingcriminal
bemoresuccessfulthananuglyone?Crimemaynotalwayspay;butdoesitpay
tobeagood-lookingcrook?
At first glance the “face for radio” bon mot suggests that beauty will not
matter in radio broadcasting. Conversely, one might think that the effects of
beauty will be large in occupations like door-to-door sales, movie acting, and
electoral politics, where the “worker’s” physiognomy confronts the buyer so
directly.Ononeleveltheseassumptionsarecorrect:Mostuglypeoplewillnot
succeed as door-to-door salespeople, movie actors, or politicians, occupations
where we think that there willbe a premium on looks. Perhaps a bad-looking
actormightmakealivinginafewcharacterroles;butmostuglypeople,ifthey
were required to become screen actors, would spend much of their time
unemployed.Thebeautifulactorswouldearnmuchmorethanthehypothetical
ugly actors, and we would see huge effects of beauty on earnings in screen
acting.
Nobody is required to enter a particular occupation. We choose our
occupationsaccordingtotheadvantagesthatwebelievetheywillgiveus,both
monetarily and in terms of the non-monetary delights that they provide. Our
choiceofoccupationsisbasedonourpreferencesfordifferentactivitiesandour
abilitytoperformdifferentkindsofwork.Wesortourselvesamongoccupations
basedonthiscomplex combination of preferences andproductivities.And our
successinvariousoccupationsisbasedinpartonourcharacteristics,including
ourlooks.
One of the leading television shows of the late 1980s and early 1990s was
L.A. Law, a continuing drama centered on a group of attorneys and their
practices and romances. Two of the main characters were played by Harry
Hamlin,showninfigure4.1,andMichaelTucker,showninfigure4.2.Ithink
that most peoplewould regard Hamlinas better-looking than Tucker.
2
One of
the two characters was a litigator, who spent a lot of time in court arguing in
frontofjudgesandjuries.Theotherwasataxattorney,whospentlittletimein
court. If you are not familiar with this show, guess which actor played which
attorney?
Perhaps unsurprisingly, Hamlin was cast as the litigator, while Tucker was
the tax attorney. By making these choices about casting, the series’ executive
producers implicitly recognized that people’s good looks steer them into
occupations where good looks will generate a bigger advantage, and that the
absence of good looks leads them to enter occupations where looks are less
important.
Looking at two pictures of actorsportraying attorneys ina televisionseries
representsmereanecdote;andasadistinguishedeconomistoncetoldme,“The
pluralofanecdoteisdata.”
3
Inthiscasethepreciselyrelevantdataareavailable
from the study of attorneys. In that survey the respondents were asked to list
their legal specialty from among twenty-four choices, which were then
summarized into four main categories.
4
Litigators (like the Hamlin character)
wereratedasthebestlookingbasedonphotographstakenwhentheystartedlaw
school.Attorneysin“RegulationandAdministrative”specialtieswereratedthe
leastgood-looking,whilethosein“CorporateorFinancialLaw”or“Other”were
ratedsomewhereinbetween.TheTuckercharacter’sspecialtywouldhavebeen
classifiedasbeingin“Other”or“RegulationandAdministrative.”
Figure4.1.HarryHamlin,Americanactor,1990s.PhotobyAlanLight.
Figure4.2.MichaelTucker,Americanactor,1990s.PhotobyAlanLight.
Thisdiscussionmakesitsoundlikeonlygood-lookingpeoplewillentersome
occupations,whileonlyplainpeoplewillenterothers.Goingstillfurther,why
doesn’t the very best-looking 1 percent of workers enter the occupation that
rewardsbeauty mostgenerously?Why don’ttheugliest 10percentof workers
windup inthose occupationswherelooksmatterleast?Ifpeople behavedthis
way, the effects of looks on earnings and on other outcomes within each
occupationwouldbeimperceptible,oratmosttiny,sincethedistinctionsamong
thelooksofpeopleineachoccupationwouldbeminute.
Peopledonotchoosetoenteroccupationsbasedsolelyontheirlooksandon
thepotentialpayoffstotheirlooksinvariousoccupations.Beinggood-looking
would help an opera singer; yet not all opera singers are beautiful. Indeed,
arguably the greatest soprano of the twentieth century, Maria Callas, was no
beautyatall.Whateverherlackofgoodlooksmayhavecostinsuccesswasfar
more than compensated by her extraordinary voice and musicality. As a more
recentexample,DustinHoffman’saunttoldhim,“Youcan’tbeanactor;you’re
toougly.”YettwoBestActorOscarshavemadeitclearthatlooksarenotthe
onlythingthatdeterminessuccessinscreenacting.
5
We choose our occupations based on the mix of our skills, interests, and
abilities, of which looks are just one. That choice is partly based on the
importanceattachedtothesedifferentskillsandendowmentsbythemarket,and
beautyisonlyoneofthemanythingsthatarefavoredbythemarket.Anditis
favoreddifferentlyindifferentoccupations.Forthisreasonwewillfindthatthe
looks of workers within a particular occupation are not all nearly the same.
Characteristicsotherthanlooksalsodeterminepeople’schoicesofoccupation.
We will, though, see less variation in looks within an occupation than in the
workforce as a whole. On average, better-looking people will choose
occupationswheretheirlookspayoff,andworse-lookingpeoplewillshyaway
from those occupations. The evidence for attorneys in different specialties
demonstratesthisfact.
Some anecdotal evidence for the notion that beauty can pay off even with
sortingacrossoccupationsisprovidedby a recent example of an Italian priest
who was organizing a web-based beauty pageant for nuns, hardly a calling
wherewewouldthinkthatbeautyisrewardedorevenrecognizedbyworkersor
“consumers.”
6
Nuns could submit photos, and web-users would vote for their
favorites.Theorganizersaid,“Thiscontestwillbeawaytoshowthereisn’tjust
thebeautyweseeontelevision,butalsoamorediscreetcharm.”
HOWBIGAREBEAUTYEFFECTSWHERE
BEAUTYMIGHTMATTER?
A rapidly growing number of researchers have focused on how differences in
looks affect the outcomes that incumbents in various occupations experience.
We have already discussed a study of the effects of beautyon the earnings of
attorneys, so let’s look at what the payoffs to beauty are in a variety of other
occupations. In many cases the payoffs that have been measured are purely
monetary.Inothers, though,theresearch looksathow workers’beautyaffects
theirchanceofsuccess,asindicatedbypromotionsorothermeasuresof“getting
ahead.”
Oneoccupationwherebeautymightmatteralotisprostitution.Forthesame
serviceperformedinthesamekindoflocation,doesabetter-lookingprostitute
receive a higher price? This question has been studied by a number of
economists who have interviewed street prostitutes, obtained information on
their earnings and the kinds of activities performed, and had the prostitutes’
looksratedbyinterviewersorpanelsofraters.
Aregrettablyunpublishedolderstudyisbasedonadetailedsurveyofstreet
prostitutesinLosAngelesthatinterviewedmorethan1,000women.
7
Thelarge
majorityofthemwerenon-whiteorHispanic,withfewcurrentlymarried,most
nevermarried,andonly20percentwithanycollegeeducation.Thewomenwho
wereratedattractiveearnedabout12percentmorethanthe(majorityof)women
whowereratedaslessthanattractivebytheinterviewers.Thisbeautypremium
is based on the price that the prostitute charged, after adjusting for all the
women’s other characteristics, as well as for the duration of their interactions
withtheclientsandthekindsofsexualactivityperformed.
AstudyofprostitutesinseveralMexicanstatescompileddataonthepriceof
thetransactionanda rating of the woman’s beauty (assessed attheendofthe
interview,andmeasuredonthecommon5to1scale).
8
About20percentofthe
workers were rated asattractive (4or 5) by their interviewer.These relatively
attractive prostitutes obtained a price 19 percent higher than their fellow
workers,evenafterthepricewasadjustedforthekindsofservicesperformed,
the other characteristics of the prostitute, and even her clients’ characteristics.
Thisseemslikeahugeeffect,inlightofalltheotherestimatespresentedinthis
and the preceding chapter. But maybe, even after women select into this
occupationpartlybasedontheirlooks,thereisalargeimpactofbeauty.
Oneoftheauthorsofthatstudytook theMexicandata andcombinedthem
withdataonstreetprostitutesinEcuador.Theinterviewsandtheassessmentsof
beautywereobtainedthesamewayasintheMexicansurvey.
9
Whilethereturns
tobeautywerenotaslargeasthosefortheMexicanprostitutes,theEcuadoran
ratersweremuchmoregenerousinassessingbeauty,leavingmuchlessroomfor
variations in looks to affect earnings. Taken together, the two studies
demonstratethat,evenwithinthisoccupationwhereyouwouldthinkthatbeauty
iscrucial,selectionintotheoccupationbasedoncriteriaotherthanlooksallows
differencesinbeautytoaffecttheamountthatpeopleearn.
Street prostitution is a risky business, as atleast the initial contact between
clientand suppliermust be made in public and with great uncertaintyon both
sidesofthemarket.Therisksinvolvedaresubstantial,anditispossiblethatonly
those women who desperately want the income will be attracted to the
occupation.Ifforwhateverreasontheirattitudestowardriskarerelatedtotheir
looks,estimatesoftheimpactoflooksonprostitutes’earningswillbeincorrect.
Asimilar butmuchless riskyoccupationis thatofescort. Inthatbusiness the
assignations are made more formally, more information is available to the
purchaser,andtheremaybefewerriskstotheescort.Earningsperhourarefar
higher than those obtained by street prostitutes, and the workers appear to be
much better educated. With higher-income clients too, one might expect that
workersinthisoccupationwillbeespeciallylikelytobegood-looking—richer
clients will be able to purchase more beauty from the women providing the
service.
Theevidencesuggeststhatthis isexactlywhathappens.These sexworkers
are very young—over half under age twenty-six—and are disproportionately
quite good-looking, at least as based on appraisals by their customers.
10
Yet
evenwithinthisgood-lookinggroup,thebetter-lookingamongthemearnmore
per hour for an identical set of services than do their less good-looking
colleagues.Withamovefromtheaveragetothe84thpercentileoftheirlooks
comes an increase of 11 percent in the price charged (presumably also in the
earnings that the escort retains from her services).
11
Here is an occupation
where, perhaps more than anything except cinema or national television,
customersareconcernedabouttheworkers’looks.Yeteveninthisjobthereis
anextrapayofftoespeciallygood-lookingworkers.
Influence over events, honors, and monetary rewards are the benefits of
success in an occupation—politician—where we would also think looks will
matter. Today’s candidates must appear on television and presumably need to
lookgoodtoattractvoters.Onewonders,forexamples,howGeorgeWashington
would have fared speaking on television with his wooden false teeth; how
AbrahamLincolnwouldhavedone withhis saturninelooks;orhowTheodore
Roosevelt’shigh-pitchedvoicewouldhavebeenreceivedbytelevisionorradio
audiences.Incontemporarypolitics,oneRepublicanpoliticaladvisornoted,“If
Sarah Palin looked like Golda Meir, would we even be talking about her
today?”
12
Clearly, as the photographs of Nikki Haley and Barbara Mikulski
showninchapter2demonstrate,looksaren’teverythinginpolitics.Butdolooks
evenmatteratalltoapolitician’ssuccess?
This question has been examined in a number of studies. For the United
States,someresearchersshowedsubjectsbriefflashesofvideosofgubernatorial
debates.
13
Based only on watching the videos, with the sound turned off, the
subjects were able to predict the outcomes of the elections involving the two
candidates fairly well. When sound was added, their ability to predict actually
fell, suggesting that voters in the elections were at least in part focusing on
differencesinthecandidates’looks.
A more direct approach was taken in a study of elections to office in the
NorthernTerritoryofAustralia.
14
Therethecandidates’photographsaccompany
thepaperballots.Usingbeautyraterswhosedemographicsmirroredthoseofthe
votingpopulation,theauthorsshowedthatbeautyhadastatisticallysignificant
positiveeffectontheshareofvotesobtainedbynon-incumbents.Theeffectwas
also positive among incumbents, but not statistically significant. Once one
accountsforcandidates’partyaffiliations,however,thebeautyeffectessentially
disappears. But skin color, which may be correlated with beauty ratings, and
whichwesawaffectsearningsofAfricanAmericans,thenbecomesanimportant
predictor of electoral success. The bottom linehere is thatbeauty matters,but
thatbeautyratings arecomplexcombinationsofavariety ofcharacteristics,as
wealreadyknew.
Whiletheeffectofbeautydidnotseemlargeintheseterritorialelections,the
same author also analyzed voting for seats in the Australian national
parliament.
15
Here voters are presented with “How-to-Vote” cards by party
workers,showingthenameandalmostalwaysapictureoftheparty’sentryin
theconstituencyelection.Withapanelofevaluatorsofthepictures,theauthors
ofthestudywereabletorelatetheaveragebeautyratingofeachcandidatetohis
orhershareofvotes.Adjustingforthenationalstrengthofthecandidate’sparty
and for the candidate’s incumbency and gender, the authors found that better-
looking candidates, both incumbents and challengers, were more likely to be
elected.Perhapsmostinteresting,itdidn’tmatterhowgood-lookingacandidate
was, but only how much better-or worse-looking than the opponents the
candidate was. Implicitly, voters compared the characteristics of candidates—
bothwhattheystoodfor(onehopes)andtheirlooks.
A similar study was conducted on candidates for the German Bundestag
(nationalparliament)intheelectionof2002.
16
Forcandidatesineachofalarge
numberofparliamentarydistricts,theauthorshadapanelofobserversratethe
photographsthatthecandidateshadsuppliedtothemedia.Giventhesourceof
thephotographs,thesewerepresumablythemostflatteringpossibledepictions,
suggesting that there would be less variation in looks among the candidates’
photos than existed in reality or that would exist among a random sample of
Germans. Nonetheless, even after adjusting for party affiliation, the authors
foundthatcandidateswhoselookswerehigher-ratedobtainedsubstantiallyand
statisticallysignificantlyhighersharesofthevote(andwerethusmorelikelyto
wintheelection).
WhiletheeffectofbeautyintheGermanelectionwassubstantial,inastudy
ofalargenumberofFinnishelectionstheimpactsofdifferencesinbeautywere
extremely large for non-incumbent candidates. Going from the 50th the 84th
percentile of looks (as rated by a very large panel of raters) would increase a
candidate’snumberofvotesrelativetotheaverageinaconstituencybyover15
percent, even after adjustment for age, gender, and assessors’ ratings of the
candidates’competenceandtrustworthiness.InTaiwantheeffectsofdifferences
in candidates’ beauty were similarly large, especially among independent
candidates,whosesuccessdidnotdependonanyhelptheymayhavereceived
frompoliticalpartiesandmayhavebeenmoretiedtotheirlooks.
17
Inallthesestudiesitisclearthatbeautymattersforpoliticians.Politicosare
righttodowhattheycantolookbetter,tohiremediaconsultants,tousethebest
possible photographs, etc. The media even give the better-looking candidate
more publicity, and this pays off in elections.
18
Despite these efforts—despite
what is probablyselection into this occupation disproportionately from among
better-lookingcitizens—westillfindthatthereisenoughvariationinlooks,and
that beauty matters enough to voters, that being better-looking substantially
enhancesacandidate’schancesofwinninganelection.Thefrequentlyobserved
smaller effects of looks onincumbents’electoral success suggest, though, that
bad looks are less of an electoral impediment when voters have gained
confidenceinapolitician.
AnearlystudyexaminedtheearningsofasmallgroupofrecentMBAsover
thefirsttenyearsoftheircareers,relatingtheirearningstotheirbeautyasrated
from pictures taken while they were in business school.
19
Better-looking men
receivedhigherstartingsalariesandexperiencedfasterearningsgrowthoverthe
decade. Among female MBAs, looks were unrelated to starting salaries, but
better-looking women did see their earnings grow more rapidly (suggesting a
risingeffectofbeautywithage).
Prostitutes, attorneys, politicians, and business executives all work in
occupationswherewewouldthinkthatbeautywillmatter.Peopledoselectinto
theseoccupationsbasedonlooks,butthelooksofpeopleintheoccupationare
not all the same—not all attorneys are good-looking. That variation in beauty
withineachoccupationallowsdifferencesinbeautytopayoffinhigherearnings
oragreaterchanceofgettingahead.
HOWBIGAREBEAUTYEFFECTSWHERE
BEAUTYMIGHTNOTMATTER?
Myfavoriteoccupationsareuniversityteacherandeconomist—theoccupations
Iclassifymyselfin.Doesbeautyaffectoutcomesinoccupationslikethis,where
we practitioners pride ourselves on valuing intellect over appearance? Take
universityteachersfirst.Wesawinchapter2thatstudentsratingthelooksofa
groupofprofessorsinwhoseclassestheyhadneverbeenenrolledtendedtorate
them as being pretty bad-looking on average. The question is whether, within
thisless-than-pulchritudinousgroup,thebetter-lookingpeoplearemorelikelyto
getahead.
Wecanmeasuretheimpactofbeautyamongprofessorsinseveralways.The
firstisthesamewaythatwehavemeasureditsimpactsinotheroccupations—
by looking at its effects on earnings. A study of more than four hundred
economicsprofessorsinOntario,Canada,relatedtheirsalariesto ameasureof
their“hotness”:Whetherornotstudentshadassignedthemchilipeppersonthe
websitewww.ratemyprofessors.com.
20
Chilipeppersareassignedwhenstudents
think the professor is unusually good-looking, and in the Ontario study were
“awarded”to about 10 percentofthe professors. Afteradjustingfor numerous
otherfactorsthatmightraiseaprofessor’ssalary, includinghisorherage and
publicationproductivity,theauthorsfoundthat“hot”professorsearnedatleast6
percentmoreperacademicyearthantheirotherwiseidenticallessgood-looking
peers.
Anotherwayis to ask whether students liketheircourses—whether student
evaluations are more positive for better-looking professors. The link between
these evaluations and pay or promotion may not be direct or very strong. But
universityadministratorsdoclaimthattheyrewardprofessorsforgoodteaching,
and,rightlyorwrongly,mostuniversitiesuseteachingevaluationsasthemain
measureofteachingquality.Thatbetterteachingperformancegenerateshigher
pay is a mantra among university administrators—after all, they need to
convincethecustomersthattheiropinionsabouttheservice-providersmatter.
21
In a study of professors at the University of Texas at Austin, whose looks
wereratedbystudentswhohadnevermetthem,Ifoundthattheaveragestudent
evaluation of the instructor’s success in the course differed sharply by the
professors’ looks.
22
Going from the 84th to the 16th percentile of professors’
looksinlower-divisioncoursesdroppedtheprofessor’sratingfrom4.4to3.6on
a5to1scale.Sincetwo-thirdsoftheprofessors’ratingswerebetween3.5and
4.5, this effect of differences in their looks was very large. The impacts were
smaller in upper-level classes, perhaps because those students were more
focused on substantive issues than students in introductory classes. This
distinction seems similar to the difference in beauty effects between electoral
incumbentsandchallengers.
Onemightbeconcernedthatbetter-lookingteachersareassignedtocourses
wherestudentsappreciatebeautymore—wherethestudentevaluationsaremore
likelytobeaffectedbythegoodlooksoftheirinstructor.Perhapsinstructorsin
arthistoryarebetter-lookingthanthoseinelectricalengineering.Inthisstudy,a
largenumberoftheclassesweresectionsofthesamecourse,sothatformany
coursesthesamekindsofstudentsevaluatedprofessorswhoselooksdifferedbut
whotaughtthesamematerial.Whenweaccountfortheparticularcoursebeing
taught, the impacts of looks on evaluations are actuallya bit larger thanthose
shownintable3.1.Thereisnoevidencethatprofessorsareassignedtocourses
orchoosefieldswithinacademebasedontheirlooks.
A similar approach was undertaken using instructional ratings of German
university professors.
23
As in the American study, the ratings of beauty by a
group of students (who were not in the professors’ classes) were statistically
significantlyrelatedtotheevaluationsthattheGermaninstructorsreceivedfrom
the(different)studentsintheirclasses.Whiletheimpactswerenotaslargeasin
the United States, they were still substantial. No doubt the results would be
different in other countries, for other kinds of students, and using different
methods.Buteveninanoccupationlikecollegeteaching,wherewedon’tthink
beauty will be very important, differences in beauty produce impacts on an
outcomethatisarguablylinkedtoeconomicrewards.
Whilewedon’thavestudiesofeconomists’beautyandtheirsalaries,wedo
knowsomethingabouttheimpactoftheirlooksonnon-monetaryoutcomes.Ina
profession that pays well, but that does not offer immensely higher monetary
rewards to the top people, the distinctions offered by various honors become
important.Onesuchmeasureofdistinctionistheesteeminwhichtheyareheld
by their colleagues. In one study I examined how success in competitive
elections to office in the American Economic Association, the leading
professional organization in the field, is affected by the economists’ looks.
24
Eachvoter(memberoftheassociation)receivespicturesofthecandidatesalong
withtheballot,justasdidthevotersinAustralia’sNorthernTerritory,sothatthe
candidates’looksconfrontyouwhenyoucastyourvote.
Clearly,insuchelectionssomeonewillwin.Sotherelevantconsiderationis
not the looks of the candidates alone, but instead, as with the Australian
parliamentarians, how their looks compare to those of other candidates. The
resultsshowthatmovingfromthe84thtothe16thpercentileoflookslowersa
candidate’s chance of winning the election—of obtainingthis honor—from 56
percent to 44 percent. This effect adjusts for measures of the candidates’
scholarly productivity, their gender, and other characteristics. It suggests that
eventhechoicesofeconomists,manyofwhomliketothinkthattheyandtheir
fellowsareamongthemostrationalpeopleintheworld,areaffectedbylooks.
As a university professor and an economist, these studies do not make me
happy.Ona5to1scaleIobtainteachingevaluationsaveraging4.4inmyclass
of introductory economics, a score that is considered very good for a large
coursethatisrequiredformanyfreshmen.Yetifmylookswererated9onthe
10to1scaleusedinthatstudy,theevidencesuggeststhatmyaverageteaching
evaluationwouldbenearly5.WiththathighascoreImightbeearningahigher
salary!Similarly,ifIwerebetter-looking,Iwouldhaveamuchbetterchanceof
receivingoneofthenon-monetaryrewardsthatmyprofessionhastooffer.
Arecentstudyexaminedanoccupationwherewethinkthatlookswouldnot
mattermuchatall—NationalFootballLeaguequarterbacks.
25
Havingapplieda
computer program that measured facial symmetry in the quarterbacks’
photographs, the authors related the symmetry measure to the athletes’ annual
salariesandbonuses,adjustedfortheirproductivity(mainlypassingyardageand
years in the league). Going from the 84th to the 16th percentile of facial
symmetryinthisgroupofathletesreducedearningsbynearly12percent.That
change is not far from the effect of decreasing beauty on men’s earnings
generally in the United States. This seems to be a pretty large effect for an
occupationwhereyouwouldthinkthatonlyonething—pureathleticprowess—
woulddetermineearnings.
In some occupations it might be possible that being bad-looking could
actually give you an advantage, for example, in some criminal specialties. An
ugly robber or thief might be more frightening to his potential victim than a
good-looking one and might obtain the money and goods that he seeks more
quicklyandwithlessneedforviolence.Looksmightbeneutralinothercriminal
specialties.Forexample,sinceburglarsdonotexpecttheirvictimstoseethem,
looksshouldnotmatteratalltoaperson’schoiceofbecomingaburglar.Inyet
othercriminalspecialties,goodlooksshouldbequiteimportant.Agood-looking
confidence man might have an advantage in conning his marks out of their
savings.Thediversityofillegalactivitiesmeansthatthereisnoreasontoexpect
thatcrookswillbeworse-orbetter-lookingthantheaveragecitizenofthesame
age. Just as with attorneys, it depends both on the type of activity and, as is
always true when people are making choices about occupations, on how
beneficialgoodlooksareinalternativeoccupations.
Based on a national survey that included beauty ratings, two economists
examined how a young person’s looks affected the chances that he or she
engaged in criminal activities.
26
They considered the determinants of whether
the young person had been involved in property damage, burglary, robbery,
theft,assault,non-drugcrimes,orsellingdrugs.Lookshadverylittleimpacton
thechancethatayouthhadengagedinmanyofthesecriminalactivities.Butthe
smallpercentageofveryunattractiveyouthsweresignificantlyandsubstantially
morelikelytohavecommittedrobbery,theft,orassaultthanwereotheryouths.
Theseareexactlythecriminalactivitieswhereyouwouldthinkthatbadlooks
mightleadtogreatersuccess.Theirbeautywasratedveryearlyintheirlives,so
it appears that their ugliness led them into those criminal activities where it
might have helped them; and it induced them to shun other, legal activities
whereitwouldhavehurttheirchancesofsuccess.
Even within occupations where you would think beauty doesn’t matter, it
does. Better-looking professors get higher teaching evaluations, better-looking
economistsgetelectedtoofficesintheprofessionalsociety.Althoughithasn’t
beenstudied,Iwouldbetthatbetter-lookingradioannouncersanddiskjockeys
(the“facesforradio”)earnmorethantheirbad-lookingcounterparts.
SORTINGBYBEAUTY
Beautyaffectswhoworksatwhat,andhowmuchtheyearn.Butthereisnothing
unusual in this discussion about how personal characteristics affect people’s
choices of occupations and the returns to their skills and abilities. A similar
discussion would apply if we were to analyze such characteristics as physical
strength or musical ability. The same would be true about the impacts of
workers’preferences,forexamples,suchastheirattitudestowardriskordislike
ofcoldweather.Whatisspecialhereishowpervasivetheroleofbeautyisin
labor markets. There aren’t many occupations where tastes for weather really
matter,forexample,wherethosewhodislikecoldweathermightearnmoreor
less. Similarly, in most occupations one’s musical ability has no impact on
earnings.Beauty,though,canhaveimportanteffectsinmanyoccupations.And
itdoes.Italtersthechoicesthatpeoplemakeaboutwhatoccupationtopursue.
Despitethis,withineachoccupationyoufindsomepeoplewhoaregood-looking
andsomewhoarebad-looking;andwithinmostoccupations,thebetter-looking
earnmore.Notimmenselymore,butsubstantiallyandsignificantlymore.
Theessenceofthischapterisconveyedinthefollowingexchangefromthe
November16,2004,episodeofthetelevisionseriesHouse:
House: Wouldthatupsetyou,really,tothinkthatyou
werehiredbecauseofsomegeneticgiftof
beauty,notsomegeneticgiftofintelligence?
Cameron: IworkedveryhardtogetwhereIam.
House: Butyoudidn’thaveto.Peoplechoosethepaths
thatgrantthemthegreatestrewardsfortheleast
amountofeffort.That’sthelawofnature,and
youdefiedit.That’swhyIhiredyou.Youcould
havemarriedrich,couldhavebeenamodel,you
couldhavejustshownupandpeoplewouldhave
givenyoustuff.Lotsofstuff,butyoudidn’t,you
workedyourstunninglittleassoff.
Dr. Cameron chose to go to medical school because she wanted to—being a
doctor mattered most to her. The evidence here suggests that her choice of
emergencymedicine—withlotsofpatientcontact—isagoodoneforhertotake
advantage of her beauty. Dr. Cameron’s good looks will benefit her in her
medicalcareertoo.
CHAPTER5
BeautyandtheEmployer
THEPUZZLES
Inmany occupationsbetter-lookingworkers earnmorethan others,while bad-
looking workers do worse than average. Across the entire economy, good-
looking workers earn more on average than their otherwise identical but less
well-endowedcolleagues.A crucial puzzle is how employersoftheseworkers
cansurviveinacompetitivemarket,iftheirworkers,whoarenodifferentfrom
othersexceptfortheirlooks,arepaidmore.Howcantheycompeteagainstother
employersinthesameindustrywhoarewillingtosettleforthelessexpensive,
uglierworkers?
Take, for instance, Alan Greenspan, former Chairman of the U.S. Federal
Reserve Board. Before his full-time public service, he headed an economics
consulting company for which he hired mostlyfemale economists. He did not
institutethishiringpolicyoutofanyparticulardesiretosurroundhimselfwith
women,noroutofcharityaimedatwomengenerally.Instead,whenaskedabout
it,hepointedoutthatthewomenwerejustasgoodworkersasmenand,because
they were cheaper to hire due to discrimination in the labor market, he could
makemoremoneyforthecompanybyemployingthem.Hewaswillingtotake
advantage of the discriminatory behavior of other employers toward female
economistsinordertomakehisowncompanymoreprofitable.Buthowcould
those other consulting companies survive when bidding for contracts against
Greenspan’s company, which could offer equally high-quality services at a
lowerpricebecauseitslaborcostswerelower?Movingfromanecdotetodata,
somerecentevidenceshowsthatstart-upcompaniesthatemployedmorewomen
survived longer than others.
1
More generally, how can companies that fail to
employ otherwise identical but lower-paid female, minority, or ugly workers
survive?
Adifferentpuzzleishowthebeautyoftheentrepreneursthemselvesaffects
their companies’ success. How do employers’ looks affect the performance of
thecompaniestheyhead?Thinkingaboutandobtainingevidenceonthispoint
might allow us to understand better the sources of the economic impacts of
beauty.
Idocumentedtheeffectsofdifferencesinbeautyonpaywithalargenumber
ofresearchstudiesconductedbymanyauthors.Evidenceonthepuzzleshereis
muchsparser.Thatmeansthattheconclusionsarenecessarilymorespeculative
andrestonthestrengthoftheargumentsasmuchormorethanonalargebody
ofcarefullyobtainedevidence.
DOGOOD-LOOKINGEMPLOYEESRAISESALES?
Idiscussedthisquestionwithaclassoffreshmenandaskedwhethertheycared
about the looks of employees at the companies they dealt with. One young
womansaidthatshe certainly does care, and that, for example, she would not
buycosmeticsfromasalespersonwhowasnotwellgroomedandatleastdecent-
looking. The brand of cosmetics that she chooses to buy may be the same no
matter who sells it. But presumably the saleswoman’s looks will convey
somethingtomystudentandothersabouttheproductthatwouldmakebuyingit
moreorlessdesirabletoher.
Cosmeticsmanufacturersrecognizethelinkbetweentheirproducts’salesand
beauty and make special efforts to obtain unusually attractive spokeswomen.
Indeed,someof thegreatestbeautiesofthepastfiftyyearshavebeenseenon
television,movieadvertisements,andbillboardsasrepresentativesofcosmetics
lines. The succession of beautiful women includes such stars as Catherine
Deneuve, Isabella Rossellini, Kate Winslet, and Anne Hathaway—all
presumably recruited because the companies believe that customers will find
themattractive,identifywiththemandpurchasetheproductstheyendorse.
Agood-lookingattorneymightbeabletoattractmoreclientsandbillmore
hours,athigherhourlyfees,ifpotentialclientsbelievethatheismorelikelyto
be successful on their behalf. The attorney may be no better at writing briefs,
doinglegalresearch,ordevelopingoralarguments,butclientsmaybelievethat
hewillbemorelikelytoprevailbeforeajudgeorjury,orinnegotiationswith
other attorneys. In a very real sense the legal service is tied to the attorney’s
looks,justasthecosmeticsproductwastiedtotheendorsers’.
If we think of looks as part of a product or service, and if we assume that
potential customers value looks, then it is clear how better-looking employees
can raise a competitive company’s sales. At the same average cost of all the
otherinputsintotheproduct and at the same price charged, customers willbe
morelikelytobuytheproductand/orwillbewillingtobuymoreofit.Morewill
besold; and thecompany willexpandat theexpenseof itscompetitors.If the
company has some control over the prices it charges, the argument is even
stronger:Tyingitsproductorservicetoabetter-lookingproviderwillenableit
to sell at a higher price and/or sell more, even though the product is little
differentfromtheoneofferedbyanothercompany.Butregardlessofthekindof
marketwhereitoperates,acompanythatcantieitsgoodsandservicestobetter-
lookingworkers willbeabletoincreaseitsprice,theamountitsells,or both,
andthusincreasethetotalvalueofitssales.Thebeautyofthesellerbecomesan
integralpartofwhatthecompanyoffers.
All of these examples imply that beauty is somehow productive to the
company—thatitraisessalesbecausecustomersarewillingtopaymoretobuy
products and services provided by beautiful workers. An alternative is that
beauty is unproductive to the company—that it doesn’t affect the company’s
sales,andthatitisinsteadacharacteristicthatbossesarewillingtopayforin
ordertohavethepleasureofinteractingwithgood-lookingemployees.AsJade
Jagger,jewelrydesigneranddaughterofMick,exclaimed,“God,whatgorgeous
staff I have. Ijust can’t understand people whohave ugly people working for
them.”
2
Toexaminewhetherinfactbeautyraisessales,onestudylookedattheeffect
of Dutch advertising executives’ beauty ontheir companies’revenues.
3
At the
time covered by the data (the mid-1980s through mid-1990s), the Dutch
advertising industry included many companies, with most of them, including
nearly all the larger ones, located in the area covering the major cities of
Amsterdam, Rotterdam, Utrecht, and The Hague. While the industry was
competitive,inthesensethatthereweremanyfirms,withnosinglefirmhaving
ashareofthemarketevenapproaching10percent,manyofthecompanieshad
nicheswheretheyhadsomeabilitytodetermineprice.
The companies’ executives (directors in local parlance) run their company,
engageincreativeactivities,andmarkettheirproducts.Theirbeauty,basedon
their photographs, was rated by a panel of four adults on the 5 to 1 scale.
Combiningallcompaniestogether,movingfromthe84thtothe16thpercentile
of average looks of executives across the companies was associated with a
decrease in sales of 7 percent. Clearly, having better-looking executives in a
companyinthisindustrygeneratesfairlysubstantialincreasesinsales.
This study inspired a cartoon in a Dutch newspaper, showing a grossly
deformed woman looking at a pretty executive and thinking, “If that’s how
things go, then even I can do it!”
4
But the evidence would suggest that she
cannot, if “it” is bringing in more business and inducing subordinates to work
harder. She may have the same education and the same tangible skills as the
good-looking incumbent seated at the desk, but her obviously deficient looks
would make her less productive to the company—she would not generate as
muchrevenue.
Onedifficultywiththisstudyisthatthepeoplewhosebeautyislinkedtothe
companies’ sales are not just the companies’ employees—they are also its
managers.Theymayfunctionasentrepreneursinthesefirmsaswellasdrawing
salariesasemployees.Sopartoftheeffectoftheirbeautyisnotonlytoincrease
their company’s revenue directly, butperhaps also to change its directionin a
waythatraisessales.
Nostudiesareavailableofworkerswhofunctiononlyasemployeesofprofit-
makingcompaniesandwhoseworkasanemployeemightraisetheircompany’s
sales. But one study did examine the ability of employees in a non-profit
organizationtogeneraterevenue.
5
The researchexaminedthesuccessofdoor-
to-doorsolicitors,typicallylower-skilledpart-timeworkers,inraisingfundsfor
aparticularcharity.Oneofitsaimswastoestimatetheeffectsofthesolicitors’
looksontheamountsoffundsraised,and forthatpurposetheresearchers had
picturesofeachsolicitorratedbymanyindividualsona10to1scale.
Thedifferences insuccessrates arisingfromdifferences inthe looks ofthe
male solicitors were tiny. But among female solicitors beauty mattered a lot,
withanincreasefromthe16thtothe84thpercentileoffemalesolicitors’looks
nearly doubling the likelihood of receiving a contribution, and increasing the
expectedcontributionbynearlytwo-thirds.Better-lookingfemalesolicitorsgot
morepeopletocontribute,althoughtheadditionalcontributorswerethosewho
hadbeenonthefencebetweengivingnothingandgivingonlyasmallamount.
In an extension of this study, one of the authors used the same data to see
whethercertainaspectsrelatedtolookshavedistinctiveeffectsonthesolicitor’s
success.
6
Holdingconstanttheratingofthesolicitor’slooks,heaskedwhethera
femalesolicitor’shaircoloraffectedhersuccess.Itclearlydid:Blondesolicitors
were substantially more likely than other female solicitors to elicit a
contribution, and the average amount raised per contact was higher too. Their
greatersuccess occurred becauseof their greaterappeal to Caucasiancontacts.
Theseresultsunderscorethecentralroleofinteractionsbetweentheworkerand
thecustomerthatwereillustratedinthediscussionsofattorneys,politicians,and
prostitutes.
Theinferencefromthesestudiesisthathavingbetter-lookingemployeesdoes
increase a company’s sales. Advertising firms’ customers apparently prefer to
deal with better-looking ad executives, allowing the latter to charge more for
theirservices.Ordinaryhome-dwellersprefertocontributetoacharitablecause
whenapproachedbyabetter-lookingfund-raiser.Generalizingfromtwostudies
toanentireeconomyisproblematic;buttheevidencedoessuggestthattheextra
coststhatacompanyincurswhenitpaysforbetter-lookingworkersareatleast
partlyoffsetbythegreatersalesthatthoseworkerscangenerateforit.
HOWDOESBEAUTYAFFECTPROFITS?
Withitsworkers’beautyraisingacompany’srevenueandcosts,thequestionthe
companyfacesiswhethertheincreasedrevenuejustifiestheincreasedcosts.A
company should keep adding workers, presumably in descending order of
beauty,untilthelastworkerhiredgeneratesjustenoughextrasalestooffsetthe
extrapaythathisgoodlooksrequire.Theaverage(basedonlooks)employeein
the firm might add more to sales than to wage costs—we might find that the
average worker’s looks do raise the employer’s profits. But the beauty of the
ugliest worker hired should be a wash—the company should be indifferent
betweenhiringhimandaworse-lookingworker.
This discussion assumes that companies understand the role of beauty in
affectingtheirrevenueandtheircosts.Ofcourse,nobodywouldarguethatevery
employer or even many employers make explicit calculations comparing the
gains resulting from a particular worker’s beauty to the extra labor costs his
beauty may engender. They do not need to. As long as some companies
implicitly account for how beauty affects costs and revenue, they will make
extraprofits.Employersintheirindustrywhofailtomakethecorrectdecisions
abouttheeffectsofbeautyon theirsalesand costswillmakelessprofit.They
will lose out to their competitors, and, in the end, only those companies that
accountfortheroleofbeautywillsurvive.
Does this economic approach really describe the implied benefit-cost
calculationsthatemployersmake?Thereisnowayofknowingwhetheritdoes
foremployersingeneralor,indeed,formostemployersinspecific.Asalways,
all we can do is provide examples for a few companies; and in this case the
evidenceisagainsparse.
Employersdoexplicitlyseemtobelievethattheywillbehelpediftheyhire
better-looking workers. In countries where, unlike in the United States, help-
wantedadvertisementscanspecifypersonalcharacteristics,includingbeauty,we
see employers specifically mentioning beauty in seeking applicants. In China,
for example, a recent study of these advertisements showed a requirement for
looks being mentioned nearly 10 percent of the time, with a much greater
prevalence in lower-skilled jobs.
7
Some ads in Mexico even require that job
applicants submit photographs to demonstrate that they have a “nice
appearance.”
8
Toexaminetheimpactofbeautyonprofits,taketheDutchadvertisingdata.
Movingfromthe16thtothe84thpercentileofexecutives’looksraisedsalesby
about $60,000 in 2009 U.S. dollars. Assume, following the evidence on the
effects of beauty on earnings, that this large a difference in beauty raises
executivepayby15percent.In1994,aDutchworkerearningtheequivalentof
$175,000 would have been among the top 1 percent of earners. That earnings
level is an upper limit to the earnings of the average-paid executive in the
sample, since there are proportionately many fewer very high earners in the
Netherlandsthanin the United States.
9
Themaximumimpact of beauty in the
average firm could have been no larger than $25,000—less than half of the
averageimpactofbeautyonfirms’sales.Inthis,theonlystudyoftheissue,the
effectoflooksoncompanies’salesfarexceedsitsimpactsontheircosts.
Since profit is the excess of revenue over cost, this evidence implies that
good-lookingworkersraisedthefirms’bottomlines.Fine,buthowcanthisbe
true? If I were a good-looking worker, and I realized that the company was
makingprofitsoffmygoodlooks,IwouldfeelthatIwasbeingexploitedand
would insist on being paid what I was worth. If my demands were not met, I
wouldtakemygoodlookselsewheretogetpaidtheamountthatIamaddingto
mycompany’srevenue.Imightnotdothisimmediately,buteventuallyIwould.
EvenifIdidnotleavethecompany,potentialnewgood-lookingworkerswould
realize the value of their looks and insist on being paid what they are worth.
Why doesn’t this appear to happen? Why don’t workers compete away the
profitsthattheirbeautyseemstogenerate?
Onepossibilityisthatmostworkerssimplyarenotawareofthecontribution
of their looks to their company’s revenue, and they allow themselves to be
exploited. This explanation not only assumes some ignorance on the part of
workers, but also that their employers are smart enough to take advantage of
them. Perhaps so, but this is not a very satisfying explanation—claims of
irrationality or poor information are not very appealing and imply that
companiesand/orworkersaretoodumbtobeawareoftheirowninterests.
One explanation that is consistent with companies and workers possessing
good information about the impact of the workers’ beauty is that beauty,
especiallyofaseniorworker,growsintoanassetthatissharedbytheworker
andthecompany.Agood-lookingworkerjoinsacompanyandhelpstobuildup
ateamofotherworkers.Likeallofus,theotherworkersarecharmedbytheir
fellow employee’s good looks and are themselves spurred to greater
productivity. Were the good-looking worker to leave, her team would
disintegrateandloseitsesprit,sothattheremainingworkerswouldbecomeless
productive than before. But if the good-looking worker went elsewhere, she
wouldhavetostartanewinbuildingupagroupofworkerswhoseproductivity
would be enhanced by her looks. According to this explanation, the worker’s
looks essentially represent hers and the company’s beauty capital. It is
somethingwhosebenefits,eventhoughtheyareembodiedinthegood-looking
worker,arepartlyspecifictothecompanywhereshehasbeenworking.
The returns to this beauty capital are shared by the company and the
worker.
10
Shecannotaskfortheentirereturnstothiskindofcapital,because,if
sheleavesthecompany,thevalueofthebeautycapitalthatshetakeswithheris
diminished.Thecompanycouldgraballthereturnsandpayhernothingforthe
extravaluecreated.Butindoingso,theemployerwouldincreasethechancethat
shewouldsimplyquit,killingthebeautifulgoosethathaslaid goldeneggs.A
solutionistosharethereturnstothisasset,whichistheresultoftheworker’s
inherentgoodlooksandthecompany’shavingassembledateamofco-workers
whoseproductivityisenhancedbythosegoodlooks.
Thisexplanationonlyworkstotheextentthatthegood-lookingworkerisina
positiontoinspireherco-workers.Ifsheworksalone,shecouldnotcreatethis
kindofsharedcapital.Thisapproachsuggeststhatopportunitiesforthemutually
advantageoususeofgood-lookingworkersaregreaterinjobswherethegood-
lookingworkerhasmoreco-workersandalsohasmorecontactwiththem.This
maybeonemorereasonwhygoodlookspayoff:Supervisoryjobs,wherethe
workermustexplicitlydealwithotherworkers,paybetter.Theinspirationalrole
of beauty in the workplace is a reason why better-looking workers are more
likelytobepromotedintosupervisorypositions.
Can companies take advantage of differences in their executives’ looks to
increasesalesandraiseprofitsstillfurther?Askyourself:Wouldacompanythat
hadtwoexecutivesrated3onthe5to1scalehavehigherorlowersalesthana
companywithoneexecutiverated5,theotherrated1onthatscale?
WhenIwasworkingonthestudyofDutchadvertisingcompanies’sales,my
Dutch coauthor and I started wondering about this question. I bet him five
guilders(lessthan$3—hardlyaVegas-sizebet)thatgreaterdispersionoflooks
among a company’s executives would be associated with additional sales. My
reasoningwasthat,withonehomelyandonebeautifulexecutive,thecompany
could increase sales byhaving the good-looker outbringing in clients andthe
homelyexecinthebackofficedesigninglayoutsforadvertisements.Withtwo
average-looking executives the company cannot profit from the comparative
advantagespossessedbytheexecutivesalongthedimensionsoftheirappearance
and other skills. I won the bet: Companies whose executives’ looks differed
more from eachother had highersales. It’s not only having good-lookers that
raises sales and profits; it’s having a beneficial mix of executives ranked by
looks and making sure that they specialize in tasks that take advantage of
differencesintheirlooks.
HOWCANCOMPANIESPAYFORBEAUTYAND
SURVIVE?
Theanswertothetitularquestioninthissectioniseasy:Theysurvivebecause
their workers’ good looks enhance their profits. The extra wages paid to the
good-looking workers are more than offset by the extra revenue that the
workers’ looks help to generate.This conclusion is, as noted earlier,based on
onestudy,theonlyoneavailable;butitdoesanswerthequestionaboutsurvival.
Theproblemisthatitanswersittoowell:Ifgood-lookingworkersraiseprofits,
why aren’t firms that employ a disproportionate number of good-looking
workers driving out the other firms in their product markets that choose, for
whateverreason,torelyonuglierworkers?
One answer to this question is to conclude that one study does not a proof
make. We really don’t know very much about whether a worker’s beauty
generates enough extra sales to more than cover the extra wage costs that it
imposesontheemployer.Intheendwedonotyetknowwhethercompaniesthat
employbetter-lookingworkersareexpandingattheircompetitors’expense,are
breakingeven,orarelosingouttocompetitorswhohavechosentheugly-worker
routeinhiring.Therejustisnotenoughresearchtoanswerthequestion.What
wedoknow,though,isthatitisperfectlyreasonabletothinkthatcompaniesthat
employbetter-lookingworkersmaynotonlysurvive—theymayflourishatthe
expenseoftheircompetitors.
DOCOMPANIESWITHBETTER-LOOKINGCEOS
PERFORMBETTER?
In1996,theeditorsofaweekly Swissbusiness newspaper,Cash,havingseen
some of the earlier research on beauty, decided to hold a contest among their
readers. Each reader could cast a vote for the best-looking CEO in
Switzerland.
11
Thisresultedinninehundredvotes,withtheamazingresultthat
theCEOofthecompanythatpublishedthenewspaperwasratedbest-looking!
The newspaper apologized profusely for the seeming phoniness of the contest
results, and it did point out that the second-, third-, and fourth-most favored
CEOs headed three of the biggest companies in the country, including the
international pharmaceutical giant Novartis and the food conglomerate Nestlé.
Theothertopwinnerchangedjobsshortlyafterthecontestandrapidlyroseto
becomeCEOofDeutscheBank,oneoftheworld’slargestbankingcorporations.
Exceptforthetopvote-getter,thewinnersheadedcompaniesthattendedto
belargerthanthoseheadedbytheCEOsofmostofthecompaniesincludedin
the contest. This was hardly a scientific study, but it does suggest a positive
correlationbetweenacompany’ssuccessanditsCEO’slooks.Thismayjustbe
theresultofsorting:Boardsofdirectorsofalreadysuccessfulcorporationsmay
prefertohaveaprettyfacerepresentingthecorporationandmaybewillingto
pay for it. But it could just as likely show a causal relationship—the good-
lookingCEOmayraisetherevenueofthefirmheorsheheads.
ApairofpsychologistsshowedpicturesoftheCEOsofthetop25firmsin
theFortune500, andofCEOsofthefirmsranked476through500,toalarge
group of undergraduate students.
12
The students rated the executives’ facial
features along a number of criteria, including their overall attractiveness.
Appraisalsofthepowerimpliedbythefacesweremorepositiveforexecutives
in the larger companies. Although the faces of the CEOs of the largest and
smallest companies did not differ statistically in theirattractiveness, the larger
companies’CEOswereratedassomewhatbetter-looking.
This evidence provides only very weak support for the anecdotal evidence
from the Swiss survey. Why isn’t the support stronger? First, while there are
substantialagreementsonwhatconstituteshumanbeauty,thoseagreementsare
by no means perfect; and a set of undergraduates is hardly the group whose
views on beauty are likely to match well those of the typical Fortune 500
company’s customers, whose tastes presumably affect corporate boards’
appointmentsofCEOs.AsecondproblemisthesameasthatnotedfortheSwiss
beauty contest: This kind ofstudy saysnothing about causation. Even if there
were a strongpositive relationship between looksand company size, the most
thatwecouldsayisthattherelationshipmightbecausative,oritmightsimply
resultfromthebetter-lookingexecutivesbeingsortedintothelargercompanies.
As much as one would like to claim that beauty leads to CEOs generating
extraprofitsfortheircompanies,theonlyevidenceonthispointissuggestive.
Therealproblemhereisthecommononeinthenowimmenseliteratureonthe
productivityofCEOs.Itisdifficultenoughtodemonstrateastrongcorrelation
between a company’s profits and its CEO’s compensation. Demonstrating a
causalrelationshipfromCEOpaytoacompany’ssalesand/orprofitsismuch,
muchharder.
13
Thatbeingthecase,howmuchmoredifficultisitthentoshow
thataparticularcharacteristicthatCEOsmaypossess—theirlooks—iscausally
linked to their firm’s performance? Even with substantially more than the
currentsparseresearch,wearenotlikelytobeabletounderstandtheeffectsofa
boss’sbeautyonacompany’ssuccesswithasmuchprecisionastheimpactof
workers’beautyontheirearnings.
BEAUTYHELPSCOMPANIES—PROBABLY
The best guess based on research on the relation of employees’ and bosses’
lookstotheircompany’ssuccessisthathavingbetter-lookingworkershelpsthe
companychalkupgreatersales.Itevenseemspossiblethattheimprovementin
sales is so great as to overcome, and possibly even exceed, the extra costs
createdbytheextrapaythatacompanymustofferitsbetter-lookingemployees.
Becauseofthisatleastoffsettingeffectonrevenues,companiescansurviveand
perhaps even make extra profits by employing more costly, better-looking
workers. From the typical company’s narrow point of view its employees’
beautycanbeproductive—itcanraiseprofits.
Whatisthebottom-lineimplicationforcompanies—shouldtheyactivelyseek
outbetter-lookingworkersinthebeliefthattheirextracostismorethanoffset
by the extra revenue that their looks will help generate? More than in most
discussions, the academic caveat—more research is needed—applies here.
Nonetheless,the sparse evidencedoestell employers thattheyshould look for
better-looking workers, since the good-lookers appear to generate more extra
revenuethantheirextrapaycoststheiremployers.Ifenoughemployersfollowed
thissuggestion,though,theworkingsofthemarketwouldsoonmakethisadvice
worthless. Companies would move to the point where the marginally good-
lookingworkerswouldbepaidjustenoughmorethanworse-lookingworkersto
offsetanyadditionstosalesproducedbytheirlooks.Theimplicationisclear:Be
thefirstoneinyourindustrytohirethegood-lookers.Butwatchout:Eventually
your competitors may do so too and compete away the advantages you had
gainedforyourself.
CHAPTER6
LookismorProductive
Beauty,andWhy?
WHATTHEBEAUTYEFFECTMEANS
Beautyraisesearnings,inthepopulationingeneralandamongpractitionersin
particularoccupations.Thereisnoquestionthatitbenefitsthebeautiful;andwe
saw how it increases companies’ sales, and perhaps even their profits. Beauty
providesextramoneyforthosewhopossessitandisproductiveforthosewho
hire them; but is it productive for society? How can we discuss the effects of
beauty in terms that economists, attorneys, and the general public might find
useful? Do they result from discrimination, and if so, who is discriminating?
What does it mean for beauty tobe productive?Underlying these questions is
thecentralone:Whydoesbeautymatterforindividuals,companies,andeventhe
economyasawhole?
Onepossibilityislookism—purediscriminationinfavorofthegood-looking
and against the bad-looking—that should concern every citizen. By this view,
companies benefit by hiring the beautiful because they can cater to people’s
discriminatory preferences, but their behavior harms society. The other
possibility is that it not only benefits companies to hire the beautiful; it is
sociallyproductive.Bythisview,beautyisnodifferentfromanyotherinherent
characteristic, such as intelligence, physical strength, or musical or artistic
ability, that makes workers more appealing to potential employers and that
makes their product inherently better. But before attempting to distinguish the
ultimatecauses of thebeautyeffects, we needtounderstand what ismeantby
the economic categories—discrimination and socially productive. Both have
various meanings in different contexts, but we need to give them precise
meaningsinordertoallowustodifferentiateamongthepossiblesourcesofthe
effectsofbeautyonworkersandcompanies.
HOWCANBEAUTYEFFECTSBE
DISCRIMINATION?
Onedictionarydefinesdiscriminationas,“a.Theact,practice,oraninstanceof
discriminating categorically rather than individually. b. A prejudiced or
prejudicial outlook, action, or treatment.”
1
One crucial term here is
“categorically,”whichinthiscasesuggeststhat people are being classified by
their looks rather than by their other, individual characteristics. The other is
“treatment”—disparatebehaviortowardworkersthatleadstoadisparateimpact
on them, in this case, to outcomes in labor markets that are different and that
depend on workers’ looks. The central paradigm in the discussion of labor-
marketdiscriminationineconomicsstartswithoutlook—preferences,essentially
the second definition. It then moves, to impact, essentially the first definition.
Theideagoesbackto1957tothedoctoraldissertationofGaryBecker,Nobel
laureateineconomicsin1992.
2
Following Becker’s basic theory, economists view discrimination as a
preferenceagainstbuyingfrom,employing,orgenerallydealingwithpeopleina
particulargroup.PreferencesagainstmembersofGroupU(Ugly)differacross
employers(assumefornowthatwearetalkingaboutemployers`choices).Some
employersmightnotcareabouttheiremployees’looks—mightnotdiscriminate.
Afterall,theUworkersproduceasmuchasBworkers;buthowareallofthe
Ugly workers going to find jobs if there are only a few non-discriminatory
employers?Theonlywayisiftheycanmakehiringthemselvesadvantageousto
otheremployers.Andtheonlywaytodothatisbyacceptinglowerwages,by
bribingemployerstoovercometheirprejudicesagainsttheugly.
Howmuchwill it take toconquerotheremployers’ prejudices? With justa
few more U workers than non-discriminatory employers, the wage difference
betweenUandBworkerswillbesmall.EventhelastUworkertogetajobwill
be working for an only slightlybigotedemployer.Butas the sizeof Group U
expands relative to the number of non-prejudiced employers, U workers will
needtoacceptjobsfromanincreasinglyprejudicedgroupofemployersifthey
wanttowork.
Intheend,thepayofUworkerswillbedeterminedbytheprejudiceofthe
employerwhoisthemostprejudicedamongthoseemployerswhoarewillingto
hire U workers. Prejudice among the most bigoted employers of all will not
affect the pay of U workers—the U workers won’t bother approaching those
employers.Instead,itisthepreferencesofemployerswhoarewilling,atsome
reasonableprice,toacceptabribeintheformoflowerlaborcoststoovercome
theirdistasteforhiringUworkerswhichdeterminetheUworkers’payshortfall.
Thepenalty(the wage discrimination) suffered byUworkersis determined
byemployers’preferencesaboutthetypeofworkerstheywishtoemployandby
therelativesizeofGroupU.Howdoesthisrelatetothewagepenaltysuffered
by bad-looking workers and the wage premium received by good-looking
workers? Assume first that all workers are identical along every dimension
except that of looks. Also assume that employers can divide workers into the
threegroups—good-looking,average,andbad-looking—thatmoststudieshave
lookedat.
The outcomes in the labor market are clear: Whatever the good-looking
workersearn,theaverage-lookingworkersmustacceptlowerearningsinorder
to compensateemployersfortheirinferiorlooks;andthebad-lookingworkers
must acceptstillless.Whethergood-lookingworkersreceivepremiumpay,or
theirpayisthebasisagainstwhichtocalculatepaypenaltiesintheothergroups,
isirrelevant.Wecan’ttellifgood-lookingworkersarebeingfavored,orifbad-
looking workers are being penalized. Regardless, we can view the pay
differencesasreflectingdiscrimination.
Talkingaboutthiskindofdiscriminationasifitssourceweretheprejudices
of employers who choose which workers to hire is just an expositional
convenience.Itcouldequallywellsteminsteadfromtheprejudicesofworkers
generally:The average workermightrefuse to work nextto a bad-looking co-
worker and only be willing to work if compensated, in the form of a higher
wage, for looking at an ugly colleague for eight hours per day. The outcome
would be the same as if employers’ prejudices were responsible. Bad-looking
workers would earn less than average-looking workers; and good-looking
workers would command premium pay, as they make the workplace more
appealing to other workers and so enable employers to hire other workers for
lesspay.
Thephenomenoncouldequallywellstemfromconsumers’prejudices.Even
if people do not discriminate in their roles as workers or employers, if they
discriminateasconsumers—iftheyprefertodealwithbetter-lookingprofessors,
salespeople, television-presenters, athletes, or entertainers—better-looking
peoplewhoareotherwiseidenticalwillearnmoreinanyactivityinwhichthey
contactconsumers.Bad-lookingworkerswillshyawayfromthoseoccupations
andmoveintootheroccupationswherelooksdonotmatterasmuch.Thatwill
reduceearningsfor everyone in those other occupations,butthe effect will be
biggest for the bad-looking workers, since they would constitute a
disproportionateshareofworkersinthoseotheroccupations.
This discussion has been based on the most widely accepted theory of
discrimination—that discriminatory outcomes arise from preferences against
individuals who differ from others along the dimensions of certain
characteristics,suchasrace,gender,ethnicity,religion,sexualpreference,or,in
this case, looks. Economists have developed other theories of discrimination.
Whether these additional ideas are useful in discussing the inferior outcomes
experiencedbybad-lookingworkersisworthconsidering,sincetheymightshed
additionallightontheroleoflooksinlabormarkets.
One variant of the basic theory of discrimination ignores preferences and
instead assumes that we categorize other people into groups about which we
havestereotypesthat leadustoexpectdifferentbehavior.Thisidea,knownas
statisticaldiscrimination,and owing originally to the work of Edmund Phelps,
economics Nobel laureate in 2006, and others, suggests that members of the
groupthatisdiscriminatedagainstareassumedtobelessproductiveonaverage
thanotherworkers.
3
Whileafewgroupmemberscanovercomethestereotype
bydemonstratingtheirhighproductivity,mostcannot,andtheyarealllumped
together as being less productive than members of other groups. A few group
members might do well, but most will earn less than other workers because
employers and perhaps others too assume that their membership in the group
signalsthattheyarelessproductivethanotherworkers.
Statisticaldiscriminationisvery appealingasadescriptionofhowweview
groups of people generally; but it is not a satisfactory way of describing the
lower earnings of bad-looking workers. Employers or others may lump good-
looking workers into one group and bad-looking workers into another, and
assume that the latterare on average less productive thanthe former. But this
view seems far-fetched as compared to a simple preference-based approach.
Instead,itseemsmorereasonabletoassumethat,withoutsomecompensationin
theform oflower wagecosts, employerswouldnotwantbad-lookingworkers
around;andcustomerswouldnotbuyfromthematthesamepriceoftheproduct
or service. This view fits the preference-based theory of discrimination more
closelythanatheoryofstatisticaldiscrimination.
A second variant on the basic theory of discrimination is that there is
crowding into some occupations. The notion is that employers get together to
force members of the discriminated group into certain occupations (or
alternatively, keep them out of other occupations). This keeps wages in these
occupations artificially low due to the crowding of workers into them.
4
The
occupations might be such now-antiquated ones as clerk-typist, in the case of
women,orrailroad sleeping-carporter,in thecaseof AfricanAmericans.This
approach requires some kind of collusion among employers to force group
membersintoparticularoccupations.Aswithstatisticaldiscrimination,itmaybe
useful generally; and we know that beauty matters more in some occupations
thanothers.But,sinceitseemsunlikelythatemployersgettogetherandplotto
force ugly workers into certain occupations, it is not as desirable a way of
describing discrimination based on looks as the simpler preferences-based
approach.
HOWCANBEAUTYBESOCIALLYPRODUCTIVE?
Thesparseevidencesuggeststhatbeautyisprivatelyproductive—itraisessales
inthecompaniesthathiregood-lookingworkers.Preferencesforbeautybenefit
the beautiful and help their employers sell more. That is productivity in a
narrow, private sense—it says nothing about whether society is better off
because of people’s preferences for beauty in theireconomic transactions. But
that is the issue—is the benefit of beauty to good-looking people and their
employersofanyvaluetosocietyasawhole?
First consider intelligence. There are numerous kinds of intelligence, be it
skillsatmathematics,abilitytosolvepuzzles,socialskills,orothers.
5
Possessing
anyofthesemightraiseanindividual’sproductivity,nodoubtmoresoinsome
jobs than in others. Your mathematical skills might enable you to calculate
trajectoriesofrocketsmorerapidly,arguemorelogicallyinalegalcase,oreven
provetheoremsinmathematicaleconomics.Yourabilitytosolvepuzzlesmight
makeyouabetterengineer.Yoursocialskillsmightenableyoutoinduceother
peopletoagree to your requests, ortomanage the skills ofotherpeople more
successfullyandthusraiseacompany’ssales.
Each of these forms of intelligence is to a large extent inherent in the
individualwhopossessesit.Eachraisesaperson’sproductivityintheworkplace
—the amount that the person adds to his or her company’s sales. This added
productivity is marketable and induces employers to bid for the person’s
services,sothatthosewhopossesstheskillwillreceivehigherpaythanthose
whodonot.Webelievethattheintelligentarepaidmorebecausetheyproduce
morefortheiremployers.Butwealsobelievethatthisextraproductionbenefits
society,intheformoftechnologicaladvances,moreefficientorganizations,and
evenbettereconomicresearch.
Good-looking people also earn more and also create more sales for their
employers. Does this mean that they are socially productive too? Yes, if you
believe that society benefits because the product sold by the good-looking
salespersonissomehowinherentlybetter.No,ifyouthinkitisthesameproduct
regardlessofwhosellsit.Thecosmeticsexamplewouldarguethatbeautyisnot
productive socially—the quality of the perfume or the makeover is the same
regardlessof thebeauty ofitsseller.Whataboutprostitution,movie-acting,or
some other service? The item being “sold” is inherently different depending
uponwhoissellingit,andbothitsprivateanditssocialvalueareenhancedby
thelooksofthepersonprovidingtheservice.
Beautyisclearlyprivatelyproductive;butthinkingaboutitthisway,insome
cases it might be viewed as socially productive too—as benefiting society as
well as those who are fortunate enough to be born beautiful or the employers
whoobtaintheirservices.Itisreasonabletoarguethatsomeservicesofferedby
the beautiful are inherently different from those offered by the ugly, and that
societyisbetteroffbyhavingthebeautifulprovidetheseservices.
A fair conclusion is that the effect of beauty on earnings, choice of
occupation, and sales or profits is privately productive. The answer to the
question, “Lookism or productive beauty?” is a clear YES! if we are talking
about productivity at the level of a person or company. In many cases our
preferences against the ugly are no different from our socially unproductive
discrimination against minorities. Indeed, in those cases our discriminatory
preferences are counterproductive. There is no gain to society; and by
channelinguglypeopleintocertainroles,societyislessefficienteconomically
thanitwouldbeifpeopleworkedinjobsthatusedtheirskillsmostefficiently,
independentoftheirlooks.Asimplecalculation,analogoustooneseconomists
have made to measure the cost to society of discrimination against African
Americans, suggests that the loss in economic efficiency due to lookism is
equivalenttoone-quarterof1percentoftotalcompensationofemployees,about
$20billionintheUnitedStatesin2009.
6
Notlarge,butnottiny.
Inothercases,ourpreferencesforbeautyarepreferencesforservicesthatare
inherentlybetterthantheywouldbeifprovidedbytheugly.Humanbeautyin
some of its activities is no different from artistic beauty. It would be hard to
argue that Daniel Hamermesh singing La donna è mobile” is as socially
productiveasLucianoPavarottisingingthataria.Musicalabilityisinherentand
shouldbeviewedassociallyproductive.Itisequallyhardtoarguethatsociety
wouldbeaswellofflookingatDanielHamermeshonthebigscreenperforming
asJamesBondasitislookingatDanielCraiginthesamerole,evenifIcould
act as well as Craig. Some of what we might view as lookism is also socially
productive.Thesepotentialpositiveeffectsmeanthatthe$20billioncalculation
isanupperlimittothecosttoAmericansocietyoflookism.
Tosomeextentourpreferencesforbeautyarepurelydiscriminatory—areno
differentfromthedistastesofcitizensinthemajorityforbuyingfrom,working
with,oremployingworkersinsomeminoritygroup.Thiskindofdiscrimination
benefitsthediscriminator,butit hurtssocietyoverall.Tosome extent,though,
and in certaincases, our preferences for beauty representtastes for idealsthat
enhance human well-being generally and that are socially productive. Which
cases are which is hard to say; but most people, if they think about it, can
identifyindividualcases,canviewsociallyproductivebeautythesamewaythat
JusticeStewartviewedpornography—andcan“knowitwhen[they]seeit.”
WHATARETHESOURCESOFBEAUTYEFFECTS?
Regardless of the extent to which our preferences for beauty are socially
productiveornot,possiblysimplerquestionstoanswerare:(1)Whosebehavior
causesthebeautyeffects?Asthediscussionofthestandardeconomictheoryof
discriminationmadeclear,preference-baseddiscriminationcouldarisefromthe
tastesoftheemployersthemselves,fromanindividual’sfellowworkers,orfrom
consumers of the products or services to whose production the worker
contributes.(2)Isthereany directevidence—ontheamountactually produced
insteadofdollarsofsalesrevenue—thatbeautyisevenprivatelyproductive?
Combiningtheeffectsoflooksonsales,profits,andpay,youwouldinferthat
discriminationbyconsumersismostconsistentwiththeevidence.Ifemployers
wereatfault,andconsumersdidn’tcareaboutthelooksofthosesellingtothem,
therecouldbenoeffectonsales.Thesameholdsiffellowemployeeswerethe
discriminators. But if consumers are discriminating, employers will profit by
cateringtotheirpreferences,byhiringthebeautifulandpayingforthescarcity
ofbeauty,therebyincreasingsalesandperhapsevenprofits.
The difficulty with this inference is that it is indirect—one would like
somethingthatidentifiedthesourceofthediscriminationmoredirectly.Ifyou
could set up an experiment that would allow you to distinguish among these
sources of the beauty premium, how would you do it? One possibility is to
imagine a set of unexpected and naturally occurring disfiguring injuries that
occur differentially across members of the labor force. Perhaps a plague
randomly strikes adults, independent of their demographic or economic
characteristicsoranypriorexperiencesthattheymighthavehad,anditrenders
theirfacespermanentlyandseverelyscarred.Thesedisfigurementsmakesome
unfortunate workers worse-looking; and we can assume that some companies
andsomeoccupationshademployedmoreofthedisfiguredworkersthanothers.
Asimpletestwouldcomparewagesbeforeandnottoolongaftertheplaguehas
struck in relation to the degree to which the workers have contact with
customers. If the source of the pay difference is customer discrimination, you
wouldexpecttoseeabiggerdropinwagesamongthosedisfiguredworkerswho
havemorecustomercontact.
Going still further with this same “natural experiment,” how do the before-
afterpaydifferencesvarywiththenumberoffellowemployeeswhoworkwith
thedisfiguredindividuals?If,forexample,youfindthatthesuddenlydisfigured
workers who come into contact with many other employees in their company
sufferlargerwagedeclinesthanthosewhohavefewfellowworkers(or,indeed,
ifthelatterexperiencenochangeinwages),youcanbeprettysurethattheugly
worker’s fellow employees are the source of the beauty effect in the labor
market.
Whatifneithercomparison,amongworkerswhosejobsdifferbytheextent
of customer contact, or among workersdistinguished bythe numberof fellow
employees, shows any difference in the before-after differences in earnings
between disfiguredworkersand those who were more fortunate? Despite their
absence, though, you observe that the typical disfigured worker has suffered a
declineinearningscomparedtothoseworkerswhowerenotdisfigured.Ifthat
werethecase,youwouldhavetoinferthatthesourceofthebeautypremiumis
the employer. You would conclude that employers just prefer to surround
themselveswithbetter-lookingemployees.
No such naturally occurring plague has occurred; and fortunately there has
notevenbeenaman-madedisasterthathasrandomlydisfiguredenoughworkers
to allow researchers to make the kinds of comparisons needed to isolate the
sources of the beauty effect. Minor beautifying efforts, like better clothing,
cosmetics, and beauty treatments, have little effect on how your beauty is
perceived;butperhapsexaminingchangesintheexperienceofpeoplewhohave
undergonemajorfacialplasticsurgerymightallowdeducingthepathsbywhich
beautyaffectsearnings?
There are two problems with considering the effects of plastic surgery on
earnings. First, the number of uninjured workers undergoing major
reconstructivesurgery ontheir facesis minute.Second,itisvery unlikelythat
thosefewwhodoobtainthiskindofsurgeryarearandomsampleofallworkers.
Given that the surgery is elective, most beneficiaries have had above-average
incomesbeforehandandareinjobswhere,sotheybelieve,animprovementin
theirappearancemightmattermost.Thetreatment—majorfacialsurgery—isfar
fromwhatwouldbenecessarytoconsiderthisacontrolledexperiment.
Absentacarefullycontrolledexperiment,oranywayofusinginformationon
major surgery, we cannot look at people before and after their looks have
changed and hope to infer the causes of the beauty effect. This puts us at a
disadvantage compared to a huge and still burgeoning literature in economics
thathasevaluatedsocialandeconomicprogramsbyexaminingoutcomesbefore
and after the program began among those people, geographic areas, or
demographic groups who were or were not treated by the program. We are
thrown back on non-experimentalsituations,where we compare peoplewhose
othercharacteristicsthatcouldaffecttheoutcomeofinterestcanbecontrolledto
asgreatanextentaspossible.Thisapproachisclearlyfarfromideal;butitisthe
bestthattherealworldoffersus,absentunethicalinterventionsthatmight,for
example,allowustodisfiguresomerandomlychosengroupofworkersinorder
theconductthenecessaryresearch.
WHATISTHEDIRECTEVIDENCEONTHE
SOURCES?
Thebeststudytoexaminethisquestiontriedtocircumventtheabsenceofdata
thrownupbyreal-worldexperimentsbycreatingalaboratoryexperiment.
7
The
researchersusedArgentineuniversitystudents,withsomerandomlydesignated
as “employers,” and with others randomly designated as “workers.” Each
worker’sphotograph was ratedon the usual5 to 1scale by alarge number of
highschoolstudents,aswaseachemployer’sphotograph.
Bygivingdifferentgroupsdifferenttreatments,theauthorsdesignedawayto
inferhowmuchofthebeautyeffectwasduetopreference-baseddiscrimination
and how much to payoffs to characteristics that could raise a worker’s
productivity.The“employmentsituation”wasthateachworkerhadtocomplete
asmanymazesaspossibleinashortperiodoftime.Thepayoffwasbasedon
the number completed, on what the worker expected to complete based on a
brief trial maze, and on what the employer expected that the worker would
complete. By using the trial maze the researchers allowed for a correlation of
beauty and self-confidence—based on the worker’s estimate of his or her
eventual “productivity” after the trial—and what the employer was willing to
payforcompletedmazes.Thesevariationsenabledtheresearcherstodistinguish
discriminationfromdifferencesarisingfrompossiblecorrelationsamongverbal
self-confidence,employers’stereotyping,andproductivity.
Themainconclusionofthestudywasthatthemajorityoftheeffectofbeauty
wasnotduetopreference-baseddiscrimination.Instead,muchoftheimpactof
beautywasthroughthechannelofgreaterself-confidenceontheworkers’part
and better verbal skills. The translation of these measures to the real-world
analogoflaborproductivitymaynotbeperfect;butthestudydoessuggestthat
employers’ treatment of bad-looking workers is not entirely unproductive
socially.
In another laboratory study, researchers tried to discover whether more
informationaboutactual“productivity”wassufficienttomodifytherelationship
between the amounts received by people and their beauty.
8
This was not
designedto mimicthe employmentrelationship. Instead,it waspartofawell-
knownlaboratorygame,inwhichmembersofagroupofpeoplearegivensome
moneyandtoldthat,iftheycontribute$1tothecommonpool,membersofthe
groupasawholewillreceivemoneybacktotalingmorethan$1.Tounderstand
thegame,askyourselfhowmuchyouwouldcontributetothepoolifyouwere
in a group with three average-looking strangers; then ask yourself how much
with a group of three good-looking strangers; then with three of your closest
friends.
Again using university students, the authors had other students rate the
participants’looks(fromphotographs),thistimeona9to1scale.Studentswho
wereratedasbetter-lookingelicitedlargercontributionstotheirgroup’sgeneral
pool than did other students. But after their fellow participants were told how
muchthebetter-lookingstudentsthemselveshadcontributedtothegeneralpool,
they then contributed less than did participants in other groups that contained
fewer good-looking participants. There appeared to be preference-based
discrimination in favor of the good-looking students, but that favoritism was
implicitlybasedonexpectationsthatthosestudentswouldbemore“productive”
for the society consisting of participants in this game. Once the good-looking
studentswereshowntobenomoresociallyproductivethanothers,thebeauty
premiumbecameapenalty.
Another study used a different kind of game to examine the same
phenomenon. Each of a group of students was shown photos of a group of
studentsfromanotheruniversityandaskedhowmuchmoneyeachwouldoffer
toeachofthepicturedindividuals.Asecondgroupofstudentswasshownthe
samephotosandaskedhowmuch money they would insist on receiving from
the pictured individuals.
9
Pictures wererated by yet a third group of students,
thistime onan 11to1 scale.Good-looking peoplewere offeredmoremoney;
but when students were responding to photos of good-looking students, they
expected the good-lookers to offer more themselves. This study is consistent
withtheviewthatbeautyisatleastsomewhatsociallyproductive,solongaswe
arewillingtomakethegiantleapfromlabexperimentstotherealworld.
Laboratory experiments allow researchers to isolate factors that would be
difficult to adjust for statistically even with the best available data describing
actuallabormarkets,orthatforpracticalreasonssimplycouldnotbegenerated
intherealworld. They are increasingly popularresearchtoolsfor economists.
But my guess is that you are wondering whether they really tell us anything
about behavior outside the laboratory—and your wonderment is well-founded.
Theanalogybetweenthelaboratoryexperimentandthereal-worldlabormarket
is always imperfect—the games cannot be perfect reflections of employment
relations.Thismakesitdifficult,asthediscussionherehasshown,totranslate
laboratory results to inferences about behavior in real-world labor markets.
Anotherdifficultyisthatthestakesofthesegamesaregenerallymuchsmaller
thanthoseinactualemploymentsituations—inonestudytheaveragepayoffwas
$3.84, infinitesimal compared to the $230,000 difference in lifetime earnings
between the good-looking and the bad-looking in the United States. Also, the
relationships are much shorter-lived. Finally, the participants in these
experimentsarealmostalwaysuniversitystudents,hardlytypicalofreal-world
employersandworkers.
While missing certain aspects of these nicely controlled laboratory
environments,astructuredgameplayedbyrandomlychosencontestantscan,if
properlyanalyzed,providesomeinformationabouthowbeautypaysoffinlabor
markets.Itcan,moreover,avoidsomeofthedifficultiesjustnoted,includingthe
use of students as laboratory subjects. In a study of a Dutch television game
show,Britishresearcherstriedtoinfertherelativeimportanceofpreferencesfor
beauty from the contestants’ behavior, and to test whether there was a causal
relationship between beauty and social productivity.
10
Each gameconsisted of
fivecontestantswhoansweredquestionsposedbythemoderator.Ineachofthe
firstthreerounds,thecontestantwhobuzzedfirstwouldplacepartofhisorher
initial endowment of money and/or prior winnings in play, and receive that
amountifthequestionwasansweredcorrectly,orforfeititifnot.Aftereachof
these rounds the person who did best in the round would choose a fellow
contestant for elimination, with the person eliminated losing all of his or her
winnings.In the final,fourthround, the two remainingcontestants would play
anothergamethatbasedthepayoffsonhowmuchthetwotogether(asamini-
society)hadearneduptothatpoint.
Theauthorshadalargenumberofadultsratethecontestants’beautyona7to
1 scale based on photographs. The ratings were characterized by the same
genderandagedifferencesasusual—moredispersionamongwomen,andlower
average ratings of older players. The research questions were whether the
decisionofthewinnerofaroundtoejectafellowcontestantwasrelatedtothe
contestant’s beauty, and whether the contestants’ beauty was related to their
productivity—totheirabilitytoanswerquestionsandthusincreasethewinnings
ofthegroupofcontestants,the“society.”
Ineachroundtheaveragebeautyofthoseeliminatedwaslessthanthatofthe
averageplayer.Asaresult,theaveragebeautyofthesurvivingplayersroseas
thegamesprogressed.Thesuccessofthebad-lookingcontestantsinanswering
questions,however,wasnolessthanthatoftheothercontestants:Therewasno
apparentrelationbetweenbeautyandsocialproductivity.
The greater success of better-looking contestants on the show was due
entirely to their fellow contestants’ preferences for good looks. Given the
structure of the game,it is difficult toanalogize the result tolabor markets in
order to infer whether it represents employer, employee, or customer
discrimination. But the result strongly indicates the importance of tastes for
beautyabsentanyrelationbetweenbeautyandsocialproductivity.
Even a television game show, one that involves substantial amounts of
money,isveryfarremovedfromactuallabormarkets.Wecanlearnabitmore
aboutthesourcesofthebeautyeffectinactuallabormarketsbyconsultingthe
studies of beauty in specific occupations. Although we did not link them
specificallytosourcesofbeauty,theydo tellussomethingaboutthistopic.In
the study of attorneys, for example, the fact that litigators were better-looking
than transactional attorneys (those less likely to appear in front of a judge or
jury)suggeststheimportanceofcustomers’preferences.
Additional evidence from the study of attorneys makes this point more
strongly. Good-looking attorneys who spent their early careers in the public
sector,andwhothusdidnotneedtoattractclients,weremorelikelythanworse-
lookingpublic-sectorattorneystomovetotheprivatesector,wheretheirlooks
mighthelpthemattractclients.Amongattorneysintheprivatesector,theeffect
ofgoodlookswasgreaterontheearningsofthosewhowereself-employed,who
neededtoobtainclientsanddidnothaveanemployer,thanontheearningsof
attorneyswhowereemployedinlawfirms.Thislastresultinparticularsuggests
that discrimination by employers, or by fellow employees, is a less important
sourceofthebeautyeffectthandiscriminationbycustomers.
The studies of professors also suggest the importance of customer
discrimination. After all, the students who are evaluating professors are
customersinaveryrealsense.Sinceatleastsomesmallamountofpayinmost
universitiesisrelatedtohowwelltheinstructorisappreciatedbystudents,there
is an indirect translation from customers’ (students’) higher instructional
evaluationsofgood-lookingfacultytotheirhigherpay.
Additional,albeitanecdotal,evidenceisprovidedbythecomplaintsofsome
femaletennisplayersinthe2009Wimbledontournament.Duringmanyofthe
tournament’s rounds, Centre Court, the focus of fans’ attention and the most
likely to be shown on television, featured matches between players noted for
their beauty as well as their tennis prowess. The BBC, which broadcast the
tournament, denied being responsible for the assignment of players to Centre
Court, but a spokesperson implicitly acknowledged the role of consumers’
preferences when he noted, “It’s advantageous to us if there are good-looking
womenplayersonCentreCourt.”
11
Thinking about these examples illustrates the difficulty of inferring when
beauty is socially productive. The tennis example seems to be the least likely:
ThequalityoftennisisgenerallynobetterwhenprovidedbyMariaSharipova
thanbyalessgood-looking,equallyablecompetitor,butsponsorsmightbenefit
from showing off Sharipova’s beauty. The professors’ example is tougher:
Students may learn more because the good looks of the professor lead the
studenttoattend classmorefrequentlyand,perhaps,paymoreattentiontothe
substance of the professor’s lecture. The attorneys’ example seems more
difficultstill.Certainly,ifonesidewinsacivilsuitbecauseitsattorney’sbetter
looks influenced the jury, the other side loses. Her beauty is privately but not
socially productive. But, like the beautiful professor, if her looks also get the
jury to pay more attention to her sensible arguments and render a fairer
judgment,herbeautyisalsosociallyproductive.
THEIMPORTANCEOFBEAUTY
Beautymattersineconomictransactionsbecausepeoplecareaboutthelooksof
thosewithwhomtheyinteract.Becausepeopleprovideservicesandsellgoods,
theirlooksbecomepartofthegoodsandservicesthatcustomersbuy.Ifyoubuy
something from a bad-looking person, you are buying a product or service
whosepurchasemakes you lesshappy and lesswillingto pay asmuch.Being
ugly means beingless productive to your employer in many jobs. Your lower
productivityresultsfrompeoplediscriminatingagainstyou—youareharmedby
the prejudices of all of your fellows. Consumers’ preferences for beauty
discriminatorilyappeartomakebad-lookingpeoplelessproductiveintheeyes
of employers. But in some of these cases beauty is socially productive—it
doesn’tjustraisesales,andperhapsprofits;italsomakesanarguablyinherently
betterproductor,morelikely,aninherentlybetterservice.
Sowhocausestheinferiortreatmentofbad-lookingpeopleinlabormarkets,
the discriminatorily lower earnings that they receive, the lowerproductivity in
themindsoftheiremployers,andtheoccasionalfilliptotheinherentqualityof
what we consume? We all do. As suggested by the classic comic strip, Pogo,
“Wehavemettheenemyandheisus.”
PARTIII
BeautyinLove,
Loans,andLaw
CHAPTER7
BeautyinMarketsfor
Friends,Family,andFunds
Whatgoodisbeautyifnobodylikesyou?
—Signcarriedbystreetperson,Austin,Texas,February12,2009
BEYONDTHELABORMARKET
Beauty matters in labor markets—and it surely also matters in an immense
varietyofnon-economicactivities.Ifyouagreetospendtimewithfriends,you
are exchanging something with them—your time—and getting their time in
return, even though no money is exchanged. Time is scarce, and each party
couldspenditwithsomeoneelse—oralone;youhavealternativeusesofyour
time.Yourchoicemeansthatyouaregivinguptheopportunitytobewithother
peopleinfavoroftimespent with these friends. How beauty affects even this
most rudimentary non-monetary exchange is an economic question, since the
sharinginvolvesyourscarcetime.
MuchofwhatIdiscussherehastodowithmatching—howgroupsofpeople
form,howindividualsmatchone-to-onewitheachotherindatingandmarriage,
and how theyobtain monetary preferment when they match withlenders. The
marriage market is especially interesting and important. In most modern
societiesnothingotherthantokenringsareexchanged.Nodowryorbrideprice
is paid. Yet a marriage implicitly involves the exchange of a promise of a
lifetime spent together—doing things together and, most important for our
purposes,lookingateachother andsharingagenepooltopass onto thenext
generation. These latter two considerations involve each spouse’s looks, so in
this most important of transactions, we should expect beauty to play an
importantrole.
HOWISBEAUTYEXCHANGED?
Exchanging beauty for non-economic returns is not that much different from
exchanging beauty for pay at work. But there are a few differences, mostly
because,unlikeajobwhereitisjusttheworker’sbeautythatisbeingexchanged
formoney,hereatleasttwopartiesarebothexchangingtheirbeautywitheach
otherandexchangingbeautyfortheirpartner’sothercharacteristics.
Whatwouldtwo-personpartnershipslooklikeiftheonlytraitthatpeoplehad
was their beauty, everybody appraised human beauty the same way, and
everybody valued beauty? The most beautifulperson would be partnered with
thenextmostbeautiful,thethird-mostwiththefourth-most,allthewaydownto
a partnership between the ugliest and second-most ugly person. We saw that
agreementaboutbeautyisimperfect,sothissetofpairsisanextremecase;but
solongastherearecommonstandardsofbeauty,asweknowthereare,better-
lookingpeoplewilltendtobematchedwithotherbetter-lookingpeople—there
willbegood-lookingcouplesandbad-lookingcouples.
Beautyisn’ttheonlythingpeoplecareabout.Whatifthereisanothertrait,
sayintelligence,thatpeoplevalueintheirpartners.Inthinkingaboutwhomto
partner with, I desire their beauty and their intelligence, and they want mine.
Assume,astheevidenceshowed,thatthereisnocorrelationbetweenbeautyand
intelligence—a woman supermodel is just as likely to be very bright or quite
stupid,andsoisamalesuperstar.Informingpartnerships,solongasbothtraits
arevalued,thosewhoarebeautifulcanusethatdesiredcharacteristictoattract
partners who have both beauty and intelligence to offer. Beautiful people will
attractotherbeautifulpeople;buttheywillalsobeabletotradetheirbeautyfora
partner’sintelligence.Theoutcomewillbethatbeautifulpeoplewillbematched
together; they will also be matched with people who are not so beautiful, but
whoinsteadcanoffertheirintelligenceintheexchange.
Intelligenceisjustoneofmanycharacteristicsasidefrombeautythatpeople
mightdesireinapartner.Othersmightbeheight,goodhealth,education,family
connections, a good name, and, no doubt, many others. The beautiful can
exchangetheirbeautyfortheseotherdesirablecharacteristics;andtheir ability
todosowillleadtogood-lookingpeoplebeingpartneredwithpeoplewhoare
themselves good-looking and who possess many of these other desired
characteristics.Beautywillbeassociatedwithpartner’sbeauty,anditwillalso
be associated with partner’s intelligence, education, family name, and other
characteristics. Most generally, beauty will be associated with any partner’s
characteristicthatbringsmoretothepartnership,includingthepartner’sability
toprovidematerialthings—hisorherabilitytoearnmoney.
HOWDOESBEAUTYAFFECTGROUP
FORMATION?
This discussion has been totally general—it could apply to the formation of
groups of people or to two-person relationships. It could apply to short-term
relationships or to longer-term, even lifetime relationships. The general
principlesofexchangearethesameinallofthesecases,buttherearespecific
differencesthatmakeeachunique.
You start life off engaging with people you didn’t choose, such as your
parentsandotherolderrelatives.Evenherebeautyplaysapart.Mostbabiesare
viewedascute,andtheirperceivedcutenessinducestheirparentsandothersto
bondwiththem—totreatthembetter.Bythetimewestartschool,though,we
mustchoosewhotospendourscarcetimewith.Whomwillweinviteforplay
dates from among the choices in our pre-school class? Who will be our “best
friend”inthirdgrade?Whatsocialgroupwillwesortintoinmiddleschooland
high school? Even this last question misses the essential point: We do not
usuallysortintopreexistinggroups—weformgroupswithothers.Middleschool
or high school groups are not like college sororities or fraternities that one
attempts to join. They are formed anew based on individuals’ preferences for
beingwithoneanother,andforavoidingspendingtimeoutsidethegroup.
Evenafterdecadeshavepassed,mostofusrememberfromourhighschool
yearstheparticulargroupstowhichwedidordidnotbelong.Ifwehaveagood
memory, we can even recall the names of classmates who belonged to the
various groups. In Willowbrook High School in suburban Chicago, class of
1961,thereweretheathletes/cheerleaders(agrouptowhichImostdefinitelydid
not belong), the intellectuals (my group), the “hoody” kids (a 1950s term
denoting D.A. haircuts and denims), and no doubt others. (These terms are
extremelyantiquated,andIleaveittothereadertodiscoverwhataD.A.haircut
looked like and whence the appellation came.) The groups were not rivals—
thesewerenotgangs.But wespenttimemostlywithothersinour group.The
groupscontainedbothboysandgirls,andtypicallyevendatingwaswithinthe
groupandinfacthelpedtodefinethegroup.
Doesbeautyplayaroleintheformationoftheseandothergroups,andhow
doesitaffecttheirformation?Eventhoughbeautyisjustonecharacteristicthat
matters, if people value thelooks of others, they willvalue looks in choosing
membersofagrouptoassociatewith.Abetter-lookinggroupmemberenhances
thestatusofthegroup,creatingpleasureforexistinggroupmemberswhogetthe
chance to associate with her. Perhaps at least as important, a better-looking
groupmembermakestheentiregroupmoreattractivetooutsiders.Shemakesit
easier for the group to attract more, and more desirable, members. It benefits
others, raising the value of group membership for everyone. The effect is the
sameaswhenareligiouscultobtainsanotheradherent,whoseattendancemakes
jointprayermoreenjoyableforbothexistingandprospectivemembers.
1
Social psychologists have created an immense literature examining the
formationof groups, particularlyamongadolescents.Theissueisofparticular
interestinthatagegroup,becausethenyouhavethefreestchoiceaboutgroup
adherence.Earlierinlifeoptionsarelimitedbytheverysmallsocialcircleyou
havecontactwith.Lateronyouareconcernedmorewithone-to-onematching—
datingandmarriage—thanwithbecomingpartofapossiblylargergroup.
The psychologists’ evidence, which typically considers many factors and
occasionally even beauty, is that group members tend to resemble each other
along a variety of dimensions, just as thegeneral discussion predicted.
2
These
dimensions include intelligence, athleticism, economic background (in those
schools that do not obtain a student body from an already homogeneous
population), ethnicity, and religion. The three groups from Willowbrook High
Schoolreflectedexactlythiskindofsorting.
Economists have tried to get at the role of beauty in group formation with
experiments.Usingnon-studentadults,economicexperimentersexaminedhowa
groupofPeruviansbehavedwhenfacedwithincentivestocontributepartofan
initialendowmentgivenbytheresearchertoagroupfund,whichinturncould
paybackmorethancontributedtotheinitialamount.Butthatadditionalamount
waspaidoutonlywhenothergroupmemberscontributed,withthetotalofthe
extra contributions split among the group’s members.
3
In a final round of the
game the participants were allowed to choose members of a group that they
would want to belong to. People who were rated as better-looking by an
independentpanelofraters(whowerenotparticipantsintheexperiment)were
morelikelytobechosentojoinagroup.Beautyprovedtobeimportantingroup
formation, even after the authors adjusted for how much each participant had
contributedinearlierroundsofthegame.
HOWDOESBEAUTYAFFECTDATING?
Mostoftheinterestinnon-marketexchangeofbeautyisinitsroleintwo-person
relationships. Aside from how widespread such relationships are and their
importanceforprocreation,theyhavetheadditionaladvantageofbeingeasyto
analyze—we only need to consider two people’s preferences and abilities, not
three or more people’s behavior. Gender differences are especially interesting
here,withthecrucialpointperhapscapturedinSamCooke’ssong,“Wonderful
World”:
NowIdon’tclaimtobean“A”student
ButI’mtryingtobe,
Somaybebybeingan“A”studentbaby
Icanwinyourloveforme.
This1960 song, whichhas been usedin movies(Witness)and isstillheard in
elevatorstoday,expressesasetofcommonbeliefsaboutthedatingmarket:The
man believes that the woman wants success (being an “A” student), while
nothing is mentioned of her skills other than the man’s implied infatuation,
perhaps with her looks. The central question in this section is how beauty is
exchangedindatingrelationships—whateachpartyislookingfor,andhowthat
differs by gender. That in turn lays the foundation for the more important
questionofthenextsection—howbeautyisexchangedincreatingamarriage.
There is nothing unique to homo sapiens in the potential for exchange of
characteristicsindatingandmating.Similarexchangesoccurwithvariationsin
the animal world too. Assuming thatthe goalis topass one’s genes on to the
nextgeneration,eachpartywouldliketodemonstratereproductivefitnessinthe
formofhealthandstrength.Male dung beetles grow ever larger horns, whose
displayattractsfemalesbecausethemalecanusehishornstodefendthetunnels
where the females will lay their eggs. One mightview the maledung beetle’s
horns as analogous to the songwriter’s desire to become an “A” student.
Presumablythefemaledungbeetlewhoseemshealthiest(prettiest)willattract
themaledungbeetleswiththelargesthorns,maximizingeachparty’schanceof
reproductivesuccess.
4
Thepossibilityof exchange of characteristics, andbeautyinparticular, was
madeespeciallyvividformeinmyintroductoryeconomicsclasswhenIasked
studentsforexamplesofactionsundertakenbyothersfortheirowngainbutthat
affected the student indirectly. One described the following situation. Her
roommate,whoshesaidisverypretty,hadahugeposterofherboyfriendover
herbed,andeverydaymystudenthadtolookatitfromherownbed.“Whydid
this poster impose a negative effect on you?” I asked. She answered, “The
boyfriend is really ugly.” After the uproar in the lecture hall subsided, I then
asked why, if the roommate is so pretty, she dated this bad-looking guy. My
student’sanswerwas,“HegoestoHarvard.”Theremaybeotherreasonsforthe
match;butperhapstheyounggentlemanwasexchanginghisearningspotential
(under the assumption that his acceptance by Harvard signaled his earnings
potential, or perhaps even that a Harvard education might make him more
productive)fortheroommate’sgoodlooks.
Socialpsychologistshavelongbeeninterestedinthedeterminantsofdating
preferencesandmatcheddates,andafewhavefocusedontheroleoflooksin
thisexchange.
5
Economistshaverecentlygottenintothisbusinesstoo,andwe
haveaddedsomenewtwiststotheresearch.Theresearchershaveinsomecases
availedthemselvesoftheimmenseamountsofdataavailablefromonlinedating
sites, going far beyond small samples of student participants. Also, the
preferences are placed into a framework of rationality and are inferred from
actualbehavior,notfromexpressionsofwhatpeoplemightdesireaselicitedin
surveys.
Theroleofscarcityandsomehintsaboutgenderdifferencesintheexchange
ofbeautyareprovidedbyarecentmediacontroversy,popularmusic,andoneof
my favorite jokes. All illustrate how supply and demand interact to affect the
chancesofamatchbeingmadeandthenatureofwhatthepartiesexchange.The
roleofscarcitywhenthereisanexcessofwomenwassuggestedin2008bythe
mayor of a small North Queensland, Australia, town, who commented, “with
fiveblokestoeverygirl,mayIsuggestthatbeauty-disadvantagedwomenshould
proceedtoMountIsa.”
6
Theeffectofashortageofmenissuggested by Jan and Dean’s 1963 song
“SurfCity,”whichtalkedaboutboysgoingtoSurfCitybecausetherewere“two
girlsforeveryboy.”Attheotherendofthelifecycle,awomanstoodupafter
dinner in an old-age facility and announced to thediners (among whom, asat
most such residences, men were very scarce), “Whoever can guess what I’m
holdingbehindmybackcanhavesexwithmetonight.”Onegentlemanyelled
out,“Elephant.”Thewomanreplied,“Closeenough.”
A recent study conducted at the University of North Carolina–Chapel Hill
offersmorethananecdoteonthissubject.
7
UsingthirtycoeducationalSouthern
colleges,whosepercentagesoffemale students in 2006 ranged from 47 to 85,
theauthorhadstudentsatherschoolratethebeautyofnearly1,500Facebook
photographsofwomenona10to1scale.Thehypothesiswasthatcompetition
fordateswouldleadtobetter-lookingwomenattendingschoolswheremenwere
relativelyscarce.Thismightariseifhighschoolgirls,beingawareofconditions
in different schools, sorted themselves in part by the sex ratio (the number of
menperwoman)atprospectivecolleges.Oritmightoccurbecausethecollege
women, finding dates scarce, made special efforts to enhance their physical
attractiveness,andtheseeffortsshowedupintheirFacebookpictures.
Asitturnedout,theschools’sexratiosdidaffecttheaveragelooksofwomen
at different colleges, but not quite as expected. Increases in the percentage of
womenupto60percent(wellabovethenationalaverage)wereaccompaniedby
increases in the average attractiveness of a campus’s coeds. Above that, the
beauty of the women decreased as the campus became even more heavily
female.Sothereissomerecognitionbywomenoftheroleoflooksinthedating
exchange;butitisdifficulttoexplainwhy,whenmenbecomeespeciallyscarce,
the effect disappears. Perhaps with extremely low percentages of men the
womenjustgaveup;orperhapspre-collegesortingdisappearsatsomeverylow
sexratios.
To examine the issue more closely, several economists have analyzed the
resultsofspeed-datingfestivals,inwhichseriesofmenandwomenarematched
briefly and then asked whether they would be interested in pursuing the
relationshipfurther.Onesetofresearcherscreatedtheirownsmall-scalespeed-
datingevents,inwhichseveral(9to21)graduatestudentsspentafewminutes
with each of a number of others of the opposite sex.
8
“Successful” outcomes
occurredwhenparticipantsaskedforcontactinformationonindividualswhom
they had met during the brief speed-dating encounters. Each respondent rated
his/herownbeautybeforetheevent,andeachhadhis/herbeautyratedbyothers
whoparticipatedintheevent.Intelligence,takenasacharacteristicthatmightbe
exchangedforbeauty,wasmeasuredbytheaverageSATscoreofthestudent’s
undergraduateschool.
The authors found gender differences in the effects of attractiveness and
intelligenceonthelikelihoodofaperson’ssuccesswiththeoppositesex.Men
putmoreweightonawoman’sattractiveness,andwomenputmoreweightona
man’s intelligence. These results are consistent with the belief that beauty
mattersmoretomen,andpotentialeconomicsuccessmattersmoretowomen’s
datingchoices. Thegenderdifferences intheresponses, particularlytobeauty,
were not large,though: The responses of women to men’sattractiveness were
over four-fifths as big as men’s responses to women’s attractiveness. Beauty
seemedtomatterforbothgendersinthisstudy.
Amuchbroaderstudywasconductedonthedatingbehaviorofpeoplewho
were involved in an Internet-based dating service.
9
Success was defined as
occurring when one registrant sent an email seeking to contact another.
Attractivenesswasratedbygroupsofundergraduatesbasedonphotographsof
thelargenumberofregistrants.Thebeautymeasuresthuscorrespondcloselyto
best-practicestandardsforratingbeauty.
Bothmenandwomenrespondedmorepositivelytomoreattractivemembers
oftheoppositesex;buttherewasnoevidenceofanydifferenceintheresponse
bygender.Norwerebetter-lookingmenorwomenmorelikelytorespondmore
or less strongly to better looks in the opposite sex. Despite this similarity
between men and women in their responses to looks, the authors did observe
that, as in most of the research, women’s preferences for a man rise as his
education level increases, but that this effect was not so strong in men’s
preferencesforwomen.Relativetotheirvaluationsofbeauty,womenputmore
weightoncharacteristicsthatindicateanabilitytoearnmoremoney.
HOWDOESBEAUTYAFFECTMARRIAGE?
The results from studies of dating are interesting and informative; but the
expressions of preferences about dates, and even the actual choices of dates,
reflect low-cost decisions. A bad date might cost you several hundred dollars
and one unpleasant evening. Marital choices are not low-cost: They are
expressionsofpreferences for amatchthat is expectedto last for manyyears.
Thesematchesareusuallynotmadewithoutverycarefulconsiderationoftheir
long-termcostsandbenefits.Inmostcountriestheyinvolvehugeinvestmentsof
timeandmoneyevenbeforethemarriageoccurs.
Formostpeopletheultimatepurposeofdatingismarriage.Economistsview
datingandmarriageasanalogoustojobsearchandlong-termemployment.Both
dating and job search are ways of gathering information about prospective
matches that, one hopes, will eventually lead to a match that is more or less
permanent. The exchange of information about jobs is two-way: Employers
learnaboutyou.Youlearn what you like about jobs and also learn something
aboutyourreal-worldcapabilities.Similarly,prospectivemates,thepeopleyou
date,discoverwhatyouarelikeinarelationship,andyoudiscoverwhattheyare
like—and more generally what your preferences are about prospective mates.
Theendresultinmostcasesisalong-termmatch,ofaworkerwithanemployer,
orofonespousewithanother.
10
Long-term marriages (and jobs) create surpluses for the partners. In both
casesthe match enablesboth partiestobe betteroffthan ifthematch hadnot
beenmade.Ifthatwerenottrue,thenthematchwoulddisappear.Onepartyor
bothwouldinitiatetheendofthematch—aworkerwouldquitorbelaidoff,and
the couple would divorce. The interesting economic questions in analyzing
marriage are how large a surplus is created, and how the spouses share that
maritalsurplus.
Solongasasurpluscanbecreated,itwillbe.Intermsofthefocusonbeauty,
thissuggeststhatthereisnoreasontoexpectanydifferenceinthelikelihoodof
marriageasindividuals’looksvary.Solongasaprospectivespouse,evenavery
unattractive one, can find someone to whom he or she can offer something
advantageousalongsomeotherdimension(s)—intelligence,height,strength,sex
appeal, family name, or whatever—a match will take place, as some marital
surpluscanbecreated.
Is this correct? Are bad-looking people as likely to be married as good-
lookingpeople?Anoldjokearguesno:
Awomanwalksintoastoreandpurchases1smallboxofdetergent,1bar
ofsoap,3individualservingsofyogurtand2oranges.Thecashiersays,
“Youmustbesingle.”Sheresponds,“YoucantellthatbywhatIbought?”
Thecashiersays,“No,you’reugly.”
Seventy-two percent of the respondents in the two American data sets that
underlay some of the analyses of chapter 3 were married. Among the above-
average-lookingpeople,itwas73percent,andamongthebelow-average,itwas
69 percent. The differences by looks in the percentage married were not
statistically significant. At least within the broad ranges of below-average,
average,andabove-average looks,thisdiscussion describesbehaviorcorrectly.
Bad-looking people are not much less likely than good-looking people to be
married.Thejokeisfunny,butwrong.
Theexchangeofbeautyforaspouse’sothercharacteristicsisshownbydata
onownbeautyandspouse’seducationfromtheAmericansurveyscollectedin
the 1970s and from data on Shanghai, China, from 1995. Except for the
comparison of good-looking to average-looking wives in the United States,
beauty has the expected effect on the education level of the spouse you have
matchedwith.Below-average-lookingindividualsmatchwithspouseswithless
education.IntheAmericandatathisisespeciallytrueforwomeninthebottom
15percentoflooks:Theirhusbandshaveonaverageonelessyearofschooling
than other husbands. A husband’s bad looks are less strongly related to his
wife’seducation.
11
Theeffectsarenotsmall.Thediscussionofbeautyinlabormarketsshowed
thatanextrayearofschoolingisassociatedwithabout10percentextraearnings
among men. As compared to an average-looking woman, a below-average-
looking woman is married to a man who will bring about 11 percent less
earnings into the household.
12
If men on average earn 50 percent more than
women,thismeansthatthis isthesameeffectasherbad lookscausingherto
earnover15percentlessthananaverage-lookingwoman.
Althoughmeasureddifferently,the Chineseresultsareverysimilartothose
fromtheUnitedStates.Fifty-ninepercentofabove-average-lookingwiveshave
husbandswithatleastahighschooldiploma,whileonly50percentofaverage-
or below-average-looking women do. As in the United States, the differences
between their wives’ education of men classified by looks are smaller.Again,
educationseemstobetradedforlooks;anditismen’seducation,inparticular,
whichincreasestheirearningspotential,thatistradedforfemininebeauty.
These calculations help to explain the apparent anomaly that the impact of
badlooksonwomen’searnings appears to be smaller than on men’s. We saw
thatbad-lookingwomenarepaidlessthanotherwomen;andwehaveseenthat
they are not much less likely than their sisters to be married. Their major
additional income disadvantage arises because the husbands they match with
earnsubstantiallylessthanthehusbandsofbetter-lookingwomen.Good-looking
womencantradetheirlooksforahusband’sbetterabilitytoprovide,andbad-
lookingwomencan’t.
Additionalevidenceofgenderdifferencesintherelativeimportanceoflooks
andeducationisshowninastudyofanonlinedating/marriageserviceinKorea.
In addition to all the usual information, the service provided photos that were
usedtomeasuretheparticipants’looks.
13
Thecomparisonsshowedthatwomen
weremuchlesswillingtoreducetheirrequirementsforadditionaleducationina
prospectivematethanweremen.
That the exchange of beauty for desirable characteristics tends to be quite
one-sided is shown explicitly by matrimonial advertisements in Indian
newspapers.
14
Women in a study of ads in one paper described themselves in
three categories of looks. Men seeking brides wanted potential brides with at
least above-average looks in over two-thirds of the ads. Women mentioned
men’slooksonlyrarely.
All of these findings demonstrate clearly what has long been celebrated in
DuBoseHeyward’ssong,“Summertime,”fromPorgyandBess:
Oh,yourdaddy’srich
Andyourmamma’sgoodlookin’
Sohushlittlebaby
Don’tyoucry.
Acceptingthecharacterizationofdating/matchingaswomentradinglooksfor
men’searningspotential,whydoesthisparticularsetofvaluationsarise?What
underlyingconditionsmightexpectustoobservethiskindoftrade?Onecould
simplyassertthatmen prefer looks more than do women, but thatassertionis
bothadhoc and sexist. But aslongas full-time female workersearnless than
full-timemaleworkers,orevenifpeoplemistakenlybelievethisisso,itwould
pay women to trade off their looks for men’s earnings capacity when these
matchesaremade.
Whatifwomenhadthesameearningscapacityasmen,everybodyknewthat
thereisequalityofpotentialearnings,andtherewasnogenderdiscriminationin
labor markets? Would we still observe this trade-off in marital matching? The
answer is yes. Even when workers’ skills and their preferences for beauty are
identicalbygender,itisstillpossibleforasocialnormtopersistthatleadsone
gender(men)totradeofftheirearningspowerfortheothergender’s(women’s)
looks.Asocietycanremaininaworldwheregenderdifferencesinthetrade-off
of beauty for earnings exist long after gender differences in earnings have
disappeared.
15
I have dealt with the trade-offs within marriage that are created by the
spouses’looks.Butwhataboutthelooksthemselves?Thetheorypredictedthat
good-looking husbands will have good-looking wives, and vice-versa. Is this
trueinreality—arespousessortedalongthedimensionofbeauty?
Psychologistshaveexaminedthisissueformanyyears,withresultsthathave
repeatedly demonstrated that better-looking men tend to be married to better-
looking women. Most of these studies have taken a few couples, have had
outsideobserversratethelooksofthespousesbasedonphotographs,andhave
shown that there is a positive relation between the ratings of wives and their
husbands.
16
Otherstudieshaveaskedraterstomatchphotosofmenandwomen
—toguesswhichonesaremarriedtoeachother—withtheresultthat,because
theratersassumedthatgood-lookingpeoplematchtoeachother,theirguesses
werefarmoreaccuratethaniftheyhadpickedrandomly.
17
To examine couples’ looks on a larger sample, take the data on the
Shanghainesehouseholdsfrom1995.ThesearetheonlydataIamawareofona
broad sample of households in which both husbands’ and wives’ looks were
rated. With random matching, we would expect only 12 percent of couples to
containbothagood-lookinghusbandandwife;butinfact25percentofcouples
contained two good-looking spouses. We wouldexpect only45 percentof the
couples to have both partners average or below-average in looks, not the 58
percentthatoccurred.
18
Couplessortevenalongthesingledimensionoflooks,
justasweexpected.
COULDTHEREBEAMARKETFORBEAUTIFUL
CHILDREN?
Beautycanbeexchangedformoneyandothercharacteristicstoday,andtoday’s
exchange can produce long-term benefits, perhaps reaching into future
generations.Indeed,today’sexchangeofbeautycanlinkgenerations.Itisillegal
to sell your children—you cannot produce a child and then shop around for
buyers.Whatif,however,youcouldchooseyourchild’sbeauty,oratleasthave
some influence over it beyond yours and your spouse’s genetic endowments?
ThisisnotanightmareoutofBraveNewWorld.Wearenotyetabletodecant
Alphasupondemand.Itisperfectlylegalandpossible,though,foracouplein
which fertilization cannot occur, but implantation of a fertilized ovum can, to
obtainadonatedovumthatwasfertilizedinvitrobythehusband’ssperm.
Ifyouseekunfertilizedovayoumaytakewhatyoucanget—youmaynotbe
able to choose how good-looking the donor is. Although it apparently never
materialized, an attempt at commercializing the saleof ovato generate better-
lookingchildrenappearedontheInternetintheearly2000s.Theownerofthe
website was trying to create an auction of the ova of a set of models whose
photographsweredisplayed,andadvertised:
Manymenhavesubstantialfinancialresources,yetareunabletofindthe
genetic combinations that would impart beauty to their offspring. . . . If
youcouldincreasethechanceofreproducingbeautifulchildren,andthus
givingthemanadvantageinsociety,wouldyou?Anygiftsuchasbeauty,
intelligence, or social skills, will help your children in their quest for
happinessandsuccess.
19
Theownerrecognizedthatbeautyandmoneycanbeexchangedoutsidelabor
markets, and was attempting to profit from creating a market that would
stimulatethiskindofexchange.
Theideaofthisauctionisappalling,butitdoesallowaninterestingexercise.
What would be the price of an auctioned ovum produced by one of these
women?Howmuchshouldacouplebewillingtopayforoneoftheauctioned
ova?Thewebsitelistedstartingbidsbetween$15,000and$150,000.Dothese
pricesreflectwhatsensiblepeopleshouldbewillingtopayintheopenmarket?
The calculation of an appropriate price in some ways resembles the
calculations in chapter 3 of the lost earnings that resulted from facial
disfigurement,exceptherewearetalkingaboutthegainstobeautyratherthan
thelossesarisingfromimpairedlooks. Presumably the child who results from
the auction of ova will, as the advertisement suggests, have “an advantage in
society.” The child will be able to earn more during adulthood; but since
earnings typically do not materialize until at least nineteen years after
fertilization, the extra benefits ofbeauty occur far intothe future and must be
discountedbacktothepresent.Theoutcomeforthechilddependsonwhatthe
childwouldearnwithoutthefilliptobeautythatisperhapsmadepossiblebythe
purchasedovum.
Thinkingaboutthegeneticsofprocreation,weknowthathalfthegeneswill
comefrom the fatherand willbethe same regardlessof the choiceof the egg
donor. The question is whether a child’s looks can be inferred by the casual
observerasacombinationofthefather’slooksandthatofarandomeggdonor,
or whether they will be expressed in ways not visible from the biological
parents’ physiognomies. This is an impossible question to answer, one that is
linked to the general question of heritability. While many people believe that
parentalexpressionsofsuchtraitsaslongevity,height,andintelligencearefully
heritable,thisisnottrue.
20
Randomnessplaysanimportantroleinallofthese
outcomes. If this is also true for looks, but we assume that looks are fully
heritable,wewillover-estimatethevalueofapurchasedovum.
Let’sassumethatthemodelisintheupper10percentoflooks.Thelargest
possible economic gain, which would occur if looks are fully heritable, if the
childwouldeventuallyobtainagraduatedegree,andifarandomlychosenovum
donor would have been in the bottom 15 percent of looks, is $105,000. Even
this,thebestgainonecouldhopeforfromthisauction,isbelowthetopamount
listed as the starting bid. If you obtain as much pleasure from your children’s
economicwell-beingasyourown,payingmorethan$105,000isjustifiedonlyif
thereisasubstantialnon-economicvalueofproducingunusuallygood-looking
children. No couple should pay a huge amount for an ovum donated by a
gorgeousmodelmerelyforthepossibilityofproducingachildwhosepossible
goodlooksmightoffereconomicadvantageslaterinlife.
The same calculations could be made if we were to imagine a commercial
sperm bank that would charge different prices to couples with an infertile
husbanddependingonthelooksofthespermdonor.Pricesatspermbanksare
currentlyverylow:Oneleadingbankchargesaround$500pervialofsperm.
21
The maximum prices that a buyer should be willing to pay are, as these
calculations show, substantially above that. My guess is that this kind of
differential pricing hasn’t yet appeared in the sperm bank market because the
readysupplyofpotentialdonorskeepspricessolow.
DOESBEAUTYMATTERWHENYOUBORROW?
One of the best Saturday Night Live skits was Eddie Murphy’s “White Like
Eddie.”
22
Thecomedianmasqueradesasawhitemanandgoestoabanktogeta
loan.WhentheAfricanAmericanassistantleaves,Eddieistoldbythebankvice
president that he can have as much money as he wants, can re-pay the loan
wheneverhewants,orsimplynotre-payitatall.Thisskitunderscoresacrucial
and much-debated issue in personal finance—whether and to what extent
ethnic/racialminoritiesarediscriminatedagainstincreditmarkets.
23
Whilethere
is no skit to illustrate this possibility for beauty instead of race, one wonders
whether credit markets treat beauty the same way as Eddie Murphy suggests
theytreatrace.
Why might an applicant’s beauty affect success in obtaining credit? The
possiblereasonsarethesamethatmightaffectsuccessinlabormarkets.Lenders
mighttakebadlooksasasignalthatthepersonisapoorcreditrisk—badlooks
might signal negative characteristics that are good predictors of a person’s
likelihoodofdefaultingonaloan.Inthatsense,pooroutcomesforbad-looking
applicants would indicate statistical discrimination. Another possibility is the
purepreference-baseddiscriminationthatcharacterizescustomers’attitudesand
givesrisetothepenaltiesthatbad-lookingworkersexperienceinlabormarkets.
Alargeonlinelendingmarket,Prosper.com,providesinformationonwhether
a loan was granted and its terms, the interest rate obtained, the person’s
demographic characteristics, and a photograph. Three recentstudies haveused
these data to determine whether looks matter in loan markets.
24
The most
relevantfoundthatabove-average-lookingborrowersweremorelikelytoobtain
loans, even with the same demographic characteristics and credit histories as
worse-looking applicants. They also paid lower ratesof interest on their loans
thanotherborrowers.Thisisanear-perfectreflectionofthe“WhiteLikeEddie”
phenomenon.Butdespitegettingbettertermsontheirloans,thebetter-looking
applicants were more likely to be delinquent on those loans. So beauty was a
very poor predictor of performance, suggesting that lenders were not using
beautyasadevicetoinfersomethingaboutpotentialborrowers,butratherthat
theysimplypreferreddealingwithbetter-lookingborrowers.
Thisdiscussionofcreditmarketsillustratesyetanotherareawhereaperson’s
beautymodifiesaneconomicexchange.Researchinthisareaisjustbeginning,
andtheevidenceisveryfarfromconclusive.Itdoesseem,though,thatlenders
arewillingtoexchangemoregeneroustermsonloansforthepleasureofdealing
withgood-lookingborrowers.Theydothisnotbecausegoodlookspredictthat
theloanwillperformbetter,butbecausetheyareprejudicedagainstbad-looking
applicants.Theyexhibitthe same preference-based discrimination that appears
toexistsociety-wideandthatfindsexpressioninavarietyofothermarkets.
TRADINGBEAUTYINUNEXPECTEDPLACES
Muchofthefocusofeconomistsisjustifiablyonincomeanditsdeterminants,
becausepeoplederivemuchoftheirhappinessfromconsumingwhattheyhave
usedtheirincomestopurchase.Butwealsoderivemuchofourhappinessfrom
thepleasuresthatweobtaininnon-monetaryexchanges.Wegetsomeofthese
pleasuresbecauseofourgoodlooks—orwefailtogetthembecauseourlooks
aresomehowdeficient.Ourlooksbuyusfriendshipandeconomicsupportfrom
ourpeers;and,especiallyforwomen,theybuyeconomicsupportfromaspouse.
The difference between the genders in markets for matching with prospective
marital partners is striking. Men are more concerned with women’s looks,
womenmoreconcernedwithotheraspectsoftheprospectivepartner,including
hisabilitytogenerateanincome.The2009movieTheUglyTruthadvertisedthe
centralrelationshipbyshowingthefemaleleadholdingaheartnexttoherhead
andthemaleleadholdingoneoverhispants.
Ourbehaviorallowsustomonetizeourlooks—totradeourbeautyfornon-
monetary benefits that in turn have some monetary value. It enhances the
economic importance of looks beyond areas that are obviously economic. Put
morebluntly,theepigraphtothischapterhasgotitexactlywrong:Yetonemore
reasonwhybeautypaysisthatitinducesmorepeopletolikeyou.
CHAPTER8
LegalProtectionfortheUgly
FAIRNESSANDPUBLICPOLICY
Fairisnotawordthateconomistsusealot.Wearemoreconcernedwithhow
people’scharacteristicsaffectmarketoutcomes,predictingtheeffectsofchanges
onthoseoutcomes, examiningincentives,andsoon,thanwithaskingwhether
anoutcomemeetssomecriterionoffairness.Buthavingdemonstratedthatthere
isabeautypremium,andanuglinesspenalty,insomanyareasofdailylife,itis
worthaskingthequestion:Isitfairthatsomepeople,whohappentobebornand
grow up bad-looking, are disadvantaged in so many ways compared to others
whoare,forexamples,nomoreintelligent,strong,orphysicallyfit?
Most industrialized societies have instituted policies designed to protect
disadvantaged citizens in a variety of areas. These include labor markets,
housingmarkets,andaccesstopublicfacilities.AtthefederallevelintheUnited
States,protectedgroupsincluderacial,ethnic,andreligiousminorities;women;
older citizens; and disabled citizens. Most other industrialized countries have
similarprotections.InsomecountriesandsomeAmericanstatesandlocalities,
protection is also provided based on sexual orientation. The question here is
whetheritwouldmakesensetooffersimilarhelptowhatonejournalistItalked
with called the “looks-challenged” citizen—perhaps the 10–15 percent of
citizens whose looks are considered by their peers to be below average, or
perhapsonlythe1–2percentwhoareconsideredhomely.
One can easily imagine policies that would offer bad-looking people
protections similar to those now offered to other disadvantaged citizens. Are
theregoodargumentsforprovidingtheseprotections?Dothepotentialbenefits
outweighthepotentialcosts?Thattherearelikelytobebenefitsseemscertain,
sinceproposedpoliciesinanyareaalmostalwaysconfersomebenefitonatleast
somepeople.Whetherothercitizensmightbedisadvantagedbythosepolicies—
whetherthepoliciesgenerateunintendednegativeconsequencesforsocietyasa
whole—is always a more difficult question to answer. But it needs to be
addressedwhenanypolicyproposalispresented.Thatisespeciallytrueinthe
caseofbeauty,giventhenoveltyoftheideaofprotectingthisparticulargroup.
WHATKINDSOFPROTECTIONAREPOSSIBLE?
Before delving into specific existing policies that mightbe used toprotect the
ugly,itisworthdiscussingthemoregeneralpoliciesthathavebeenenactedto
aidcertain“protectedclasses.”IntheUnitedStates,theseclassesofcitizenare
typically helped by two types of policy. The first is legislation—be it federal,
state,orlocal—thatexplicitlymandatesprotectingspecificgroupsofpeoplein
certainspecifiedactivities.Thesecondisthroughgovernmentpurchasing,again
atalllevelsofgovernment,throughwhichprotectedgroupsmustreceivecertain
typesofpreferencesinemploymentbygovernmentcontractors.
Manystates hadlonghad anti-discriminationlaws coveringvarious groups,
particularly minorities, before legislative protection at the federal level began
with the Equal Pay Act (EPA) of 1963. The EPA required employers to offer
femaleandmaleemployeesthesamepayiftheywereperforming“equalwork
onjobstheperformanceofwhichrequiresequalskill,effortandresponsibility,
and which are performed under similar working conditions” within an
establishment. This legislation outlawed genderdiscrimination in employment,
fairlynarrowlydefined,withincompaniesengagedininterstatecommerce.
State laws were to a large extent superseded by the passage of the Civil
Rights Act of 1964, whose Title VII prohibited employment discrimination
basedonthenowwell-knownprotectedcategoriesof“race,color,religion,sex
or national origin.” These protections were to be overseen by the Equal
Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC). Its purview soon came to
include the protection of workers ages forty and up under the Age
Discrimination in Employment Act (ADEA) of 1967. In 1990, Title I of the
Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA) added “qualified individuals with
disabilities”tothelistofprotectedgroups.
TheADAwouldseemtobethemostobviousexistingvehicleatthefederal
levelthroughwhichtooffer generalizedprotectiontobad-lookingworkers. Its
Section 12102 defines disability as “a physical or mental impairment that
substantially limits one or more major life activities,” with the latter term
defined as including, “caring for oneself, performing manual tasks, seeing,
hearing, eating, sleeping, walking, standing, lifting, bending.” None of these
limitations appears to apply to the bad-looking—the language would seem to
excludetheugly.Butthesectiongoesontodefinedisabilitytoincludepeople
“regardedashavingsuchanimpairment,”definedasexisting“iftheindividual
establishesthatheorshehasbeensubjectedtoanactionprohibited...whether
ornottheimpairmentlimitsorisperceivedtolimitamajorlifeactivity.”One
mightarguethatbadlookscouldbeincludedunderthislatterextensionofthe
definitionofdisabilityandthusthattheuglyarealreadyprotectedbytheADA.
Alloftheseprotectionsareaimedatlabormarkets.In1968, TitleVIIIwas
addedtotheCivilRightsActtoofferrentersandbuyersexplicitprotectionsin
housingmarkets.Overtheyearsithasbeenexpandedtodefineasprotectedthe
same characteristics that are covered by the panoply of federal anti-
discrimination laws covering employment. With state and local analogs to the
federallegislation,thereisaready-madevehicleforprotectingtheuglyinother
areas,includinglendingmarkets,wheretheyarealsodisadvantaged.
The other possible general avenue for protecting the ugly is affirmative
action, first introduced by President Kennedy under Executive Order 10925in
1961, and linked to federal contracting by President Johnson in 1965 under
ExecutiveOrder11246.Theideawastousethefederalgovernment’sroleasa
purchaser of goods and services, and as a provider of subsidies, to induce
employerstoadoptandimplementpoliciesthatwouldaidprotectedgroups.In
areas such as hiring, promotion, access to education and others, the program,
monitoredbyanofficeintheU.S.DepartmentofLabor,requiresemployersto
file“affirmativeactionplans.”Thesemustshowpastprogressandpromisesof
additional efforts to meet stated “goals and timetables” for future progress in
enhancingopportunitiesforracialandethnicminoritiesandforwomen.
Nearly fifty years after its inception, affirmative action remains highly
controversial,tothepointthatthereisnotevenmuchagreementonwhetherit
hasbeenbeneficialonnetforthegroupsithasbeenaimedat,muchlessabout
its overall desirability. Affirmative action would hardly seem to be an ideal
vehicletowhichtoattachstilladditionalprotections,butitcouldbeused.One
couldincludethebad-lookingasanotherprotectedclass,requiringanemployer
toofferplansthatwouldindicatehowhomelypeoplewouldbehiredintoentry-
andupper-levelpositions,advanceupjobladders,etc.,inordertoachievegoals
describingtheireventualpositioninthecompany.
Numerous states and localities have enacted protections that extend federal
legislation to some of the relatively few companies that are not covered by
federallawsbecauseoftheirsizeorlineofbusiness.Manyhavecreatedstateor
local affirmative action programs, essentially mandating compliance by those
companiesandorganizationsthatdobusinesswiththestateorlocalgovernment.
These sub-federal extensions become binding, and are most relevant for this
chapter, where they include additional groups that are not subsumed under
federalprotections.
Michigan and San Francisco have laws that expand protection to include
weight and height explicitly. The City of San Francisco Human Rights
Commission, which monitors the treatment of members of an unusually large
varietyofprotectedgroups,describesitstaskas:
Theinvestigation...[and mediationof]complaintsofdiscriminationin
employment by businesses . . . based on a person’s race, color, creed,
religion, national origin, ancestry, age, sex, sexual orientation, gender
identity, domestic partner status, marital status, disability or AIDS/HIV
status,weightandheight.
1
Thelocallegislationdoesnotexplicitlyprotectagainstdiscriminationbasedon
looks, but it would not be a large step to add this additional group to those
alreadycovered.
In a very few jurisdictions, that protection does exist. These include Santa
Cruz, California; Urbana, Illinois; Madison, Wisconsin; and Howard County,
Maryland.
2
Most recently, the District of Columbia has enacted fairly broad
protectionsforemployees,bymakingitillegal“todiscriminate...onthebasis
of outward appearance for purposes of recruitment, hiring, or promotion”
(Section512ofTitle4—HumanRights—oftheDCMunicipalCode).Inanother
section, protection is offered on the basis of personal appearance in rental
housing, mortgage lending, and numerous other aspects of housing markets.
Thesearetheonlyjurisdictionsthatasof2008hadlegislatedexplicitprotection
inemploymentbasedonappearanceindependentofheightorweight.Thestate
of California does, though, prohibit discrimination in housing on the basis of
“personalcharacteristics,suchasaperson’sphysicalappearance...thatarenot
relatedtotheresponsibilitiesofatenant.”
3
Oneofthebroadest-basedlegislativeprotectionsbasedonlookscanbefound
inFrance.Itslaborcodestates:
Concerning recruitment; access to a placement or in-company training
program; pay; training; redeployment within a company; posting;
qualifications;job classification;promotion;transferfrom oneworkplace
to another; and renewal of contract, provides that no person can be
eliminatedduetotheir...physicalappearance.
4
Thisprovisionoffersanextremelybroadprotectiontoemployees,althoughthe
codemakesitclearthattheinitialburdenofproofisbornebytheemployee.
HOWHAVEEXISTINGPOLICIESBEENUSED?
Evenunderfederal,state,orlocallegislationthatdoesnotexplicitlyprotectbad
looksinlabor,housing,orothermarkets,asubstantialnumberoflawsuitshave
beenbroughtseekingcase-lawprotectionforpeoplebasedontheirlooks.
5
Many
ofthemhavelinkedsomeaspectofappearancetoexistingprotectionsbasedon
theirrace,gender,orreligion.Forexample,inHollinsv.Atlantic,188F.3d652
(6th Cir. 1999), anAfrican Americanwoman claimedracialdiscrimination on
groundsthatapolicyconcerninghairstylesapplied onlyto her.Her claimwas
rejected.Twomenarguedthat theiremployer’spreventingthemfrom wearing
earrings constituted sex discrimination (Kleinsorge v. Island Corp., 81 F.E.P.
Cases (BNA) 1601 (E.D. Pa. 2000)). Their claim was denied, with the court
arguing that gender differences in standards of appearance are permissible. In
Swartzentruberv.GuniteCorp.,83F.E.P.Cases(BNA)181(N.D.Ind.2000),
theplaintiffarguedthathisfiringforhavingatattoodepictingaKlansmanwith
aburningcross violated protections of hisreligiousbeliefs. His claim toowas
rejected.
Courtshavebeenunwillingtoincludeappearance,asmanifestedindressor
decoration,asaprotectedexpressionofracial,religious,orgenderidentity.The
treatmentofappearance,asmanifestedinweight,isadifferentstory.
6
Anumber
of successful claims have been brought under EEO (Equal Employment
Opportunity) protections, for example, Frank v. United Airlines, 216 F.3d 845
(9th Cir. 2000), with female flight attendants arguing that weight restrictions
were applied differently by gender. Most weight cases, however, have been
broughtundertheADA,withtheargumenttypicallybeingthatobesity,oreven
overweight,isitselfadisability.AplaintiffwhosimplyasksforADAprotection
for being overweight, without claiming it is a disability, does not generally
obtainrelief(e.g.,Colemanv.GeorgiaPowerCo.,81F.Supp.2d1365(N.D.
Ga.2000)).If,however,aplaintiffcandemonstratemorbidobesity,tothepoint
whereitrestrictsa“majorlifeactivity,”thepersoncanreceiverelief—havethe
disability accommodated by the employer—under the ADA (Cook v. Rhode
Island Department of Mental Health, Retardation, and Hospitals, 10 F.3d 17
(1stCir.1993)).
While successful ADA cases have involved claims that morbid obesity
qualifies as a disability, a number of cases havebeen brought underthe ADA
andotherstatutesthathavearguedforprotectionbasedonclaimsthatbadlooks
aloneconstituteadisability.In2003,theEEOCsuedMcDonald’sonbehalfof
anemployee who hada port winestain coveringmuchof her face.In another
case,amanagerrefusedtofireaKentuckyFriedChickencounterworkerwhom
he had hired and who was missing his front teeth, which the manager’s own
supervisor found potentially offensive to customers. The district and circuit
courts ruled for KFC, arguing that the absence of front teeth hardly limited a
majorlifeactivity.Nonetheless,itseemsafairlysmallstretchtoargue,basedon
alltheevidenceinthisbook,thatreducedearningsarealimitationproducedby
thiskindofdisfigurementandconsistentwiththeADA.
7
Thecaselawinthejurisdictionsthatexplicitlybandiscriminationbasedon
looksisextremelysparse.InacasebroughtundertheDistrictofColumbiacode
in2008(Iveyv.DistrictofColumbia)thatisstillinthecourts,theAppealsCourt
reversed the case’s dismissal by the trial court and allowed some of the
plaintiff’s claims to be re-heard. Ivey, a local bureaucrat, argued that her
supervisor“toldhershewoulddoabetterjobifsheweremoreattractive...and
thathewouldlikeherbetterifshelookedlikeherattractivecoworker.”Thecase
is not over, but it is nearly unique in that the argument is based mostly on
physicalappearance, not genderandnot weight norevenlooks as a disability.
Assuch,itcouldillustratethepathsby whichabroadexpansionof protection
forthebad-lookingmightoccur.
ISITPOSSIBLETOPROTECTTHEUGLY?
Therearetwoquestionsthatneedtobediscussedinordertoaddressthisissue.
Viewing protection for a group of individuals as a benefit that is supplied by
society:(1)Couldweevenagreeonwhichpeoplearesufficientlybad-lookingas
tomeritprotection undersomepolicy designedtoaidthisparticulargroup?In
otherwords,cantherebeagreementamongthosewhomightsupplyprotection
under legislative or other provisions about whoshouldbe protected, given the
inherentsubjectivityofviewsofbeauty?(2)Wouldthosepeoplewhoweagree
shouldbethefocusofprotectioneverbewillingtocomeforwardanddemand
its protection? In other words, would those who might potentially wish to be
helped under laws or administrative provisions be motivated to seek help—to
askforredressfromthecourtsifnecessary?
Thefirstquestionwouldrequiresomelegislature,executiveagency,judge,or
jury to agree on what constitutes denial of a right because people’s looks are
sufficientlybelowtheaveragetohavesingledthemoutfordisparatetreatment.
Observersdonotagreeperfectlyonwhatconstitutesbad(orgood)looks,oron
what is sufficiently far below-average as to constitute ugliness. One attorney
commentingonthisissueclaimed:
Effortstoban discrimination against employeesbasedon their “personal
appearance”areevenmoreproblematic.Whileheightandweightcanbe
measured,aperson’soverallappearancecannot.Thereis,bydefinition,a
profoundlysubjectiveelementtotheinquiry.Whatattributes,forexample,
shouldbeconsideredindeterminingone’spersonalappearance?
8
People’sviewsofbeautyaresubjective;buttheevidencehasmadeitabundantly
clear that people’s views are highly correlated. Somebody who is viewed as
unusuallyuglybyoneobservertendstobeviewedthesamewaybymostother
people.Whilesubjective,perceptionsofbeautyarefarfromrandom.Aperson’s
beautycanbemeasured.
Therewillundoubtedlybedisagreementsbythesuppliersofprotectionabout
exactlywhoistobeprotected,butthosedonotseeminsurmountable.Theissue
is not as simple as determining who might possibly be subject to gender
discrimination—by and large that is a yes-no issue. These disagreements are
qualitativelynodifferent,though,fromdisagreementsovertheextenttowhich
somebodywhohassomeAfricanAmericanancestrymightqualifyforprotection
under various anti-discrimination laws. That particular issue has arisen in a
varietyofcases.WhileIfinditsdiscussionrepugnant,reminiscentoftheracial
lawsinNaziGermany,ithasbeendealtwithandmustbeconsideredifwewish
toprotect thisparticularclass.
9
The dividingline betweenthose whomight be
includedinthiskindofclassandthosewhowouldnotisasarbitraryasitisin
distinguishingonthebasisoflooks.Ithasbeensurmountedinthosecases,and
couldbehandledinlawsuitsbroughtonthebasisofdiscriminationagainstthe
ugly.
Wouldtherebeanydemandforprotection?Wouldpeoplebewillingtoadmit
thattheyarebad-lookingifthereweresomeforumforobtainingcompensation
forthedisadvantagesthattheirlookshavecausedthem?Withouthavingtested
the demand for protection by a newly entitledclass, we cannot becertain that
offeringprotectionwouldelicitthatdemand.Butthehistoryofcasesunderthe
ADAofferssomeguidanceonthisissue.TheADAwasenactedin1990,andthe
EEOC did not start enforcing it until July 1992. By 1997, the EEOC was
receivingover20,000casesperyearundertheADA.
10
Disabilitymaybeamore
clear-cutissuethanbadlooks,buteventhatisnotobvious.Organizationssuch
as the Body Image Task Force have as their stated goal fighting against
prejudicebasedonphysicalappearanceandwould,Ibelieve,behappytohelp
organize plaintiffs to take advantage if legislative protection of the ugly were
instituted.
11
Ihaveshownthatbadlookscangenerateanearningsdisadvantageofperhaps
$140,000 over a lifetime compared to the earnings of an average-looking
worker. Add to this amount reasonable punitive damages, and there is a clear
monetaryincentiveforanindividualtosuehisorhercurrentemployer,oreven
a prospective employer in the caseof hiring discrimination. With an incentive
amounting to more than three years of earnings, I doubt that people will be
unwillingtoacknowledgetheirbadlooks.
Legalactiontakesmoney—thecostoffilingandpursuingalegalcasebased
onlookswouldprobablyfarexceedthelikelyrecoveryfromalawsuitbrought
byasingleindividual.Justasinthecaseofsuitsclaimingdiscriminationbased
ongender,race,orethnicity,though,onecanimaginethattriallawyerswillseek
to form classes of individuals and pursue class-action lawsuits. Obtaining
certification of a class spreads the cost of bringing the lawsuit over enough
plaintiffstomaketherecoverysufficienttoattractclassmembers—andtomake
itpotentiallyworthwhileforplaintiffs’attorneystopursuelegalactionontheir
behalf. Class certification is often quitedifficult, sothat ofall the pitfalls that
mightstandinthewayofthisextensionofprotectiontobad-lookingindividuals,
this might be the most severe. But with a large enough class, and with the
potentialforlargerecoveriesforeachperson,theselawsuitswillbefiled.
In 2005, a class of ethnic/racial minorities and women who argued that
promotionswereoffereddisproportionatelytowhitemensuedAbercrombieand
Fitch. The retailer agreed to a settlement of $40 million with members of the
class. Since then individual employees have alleged that the company rates
potential sales workers on their looks and offers existing workers more
opportunities if managers rate them higher on a scale of “hotness.”
12
The
aggrievedindividualsacknowledgethattheyhavenocurrentlegalrecourse.But
youmightinferfromtheircurrentclaimsthat,iftheydid,theywouldhaveno
qualmsabouttakingadvantageofit.
Whenpeoplearewillingtosupplyagoodorservice,andothersdemandit,if
governments don’t intervene to prohibit the exchange, some price will be
established,eitherinavisiblemarketorimplicitly,andexchangewilltakeplace.
Asyet there isno generalizedformalprotection forbad-lookingindividuals in
laborandothermarkets.Governmentsimplicitlylimitlawsuitsbasedonclaims
oflooksdiscrimination.Thepotentialsupplyofanddemandforlegalprotection
is there, but exchange is not allowed. But what if it were—if legal protection
were explicitly granted to below-average-looking individuals? The returns to
protection, indicated by the probability of those cases succeeding and the
amounts recovered in successful cases, would be demonstrated over time
through the case law and would determine the number of cases that people
wouldfile.Amarketofsortsforlooks-basedlawsuitsiswaitingtobeborn.
WHATJUSTIFIESPROTECTINGTHEUGLY?
Imaginethefollowingbook:Itstartsoffbyshowing thata particulargroup of
people has a characteristic that remains essentially unchanged over their
lifetimes unless they incur huge expenditures to alter it artificially. That
characteristicmakesitsmemberslesslikelythanothercitizenstobeworkingfor
payandearningmoney.Whentheydoworkforpay,membersofthegroupearn
less than other workers, even after adjusting for the amount and kind of
education that they have obtained and for numerous other earnings-enhancing
characteristics.Whentheymarry,theeducationandthustheearningsabilityof
their spouses is less than that of others’ spouses. Companies that employ
members of this group do not generate as much sales revenue as others. The
group’s members typically date and marry other group members. Finally,
members of the group occasionally sue and recover for deficiencies in their
earnings.
Ihave essentiallydescribedthisbook, withthe groupbeing below-average-
lookingindividuals.Yetif Ihad substitutedAfrican Americans,the discussion
would, with minor changes, have been very much the same. Changing race is
verydifficult. Theemploymentrate ofAfricanAmericans—the fractionof the
populationworkingforpay—islessthanthatofnon-Hispanicwhites,andthatis
especiallytrueamongmen.Sixty-sixpercentofnon-Hispanicwhitemaleswere
employedin2008,butonly57percentofAfricanAmericanadultmaleswere.
Amongwomen,thediscrepancyisinthesamedirectionbutismuchsmaller,54
percentto53percent.
13
GiventhelevelofeducationofAfricanAmericanmen,
theirearningsareabout20percentlowerthanthoseofnon-Hispanicwhitemen,
with the difference among women being nearly 10 percent.
14
Indeed, African
American men’s earnings disadvantage, adjusted for the earnings-enhancing
characteristics that they bring to labor markets, is similar to the disadvantage
experienced by below-average compared to above-average-looking male
workers generally. While not much attention has been paid to the issue, the
researchthathaslookedatitsuggeststhatanAfricanAmericanaddslesstohis
or her company’s revenue than does a non-Hispanic white.
15
Since their
educational attainment is lower, and they generally marry other African
Americans, the educational attainment of their spouses is less than that of the
spouseofatypicalnon-Hispanicwhite.
16
In short, every specific research result about beauty could, with some
alterations,applytoAfricanAmericans.Indiscussingapparentlydiscriminatory
outcomesthatharmAfricanAmericans,Ibelievethesameproblemexistsabout
theultimatesourceoftheirdisadvantage:Employersappeartodiscriminate,but
dotheiractionssimplyresultfromtheirpreferencesagainstAfricanAmericans,
orisitthattheyaretheproximateagentsofharmbecausetheircustomersprefer
not to deal with African Americans? No doubt some of the apparently
discriminatory outcomes experienced by African Americans result from
employers’exercisingtheirownpreferences;andcertainlymuchofthethrustof
public policy has targeted employers. But much also results from customers’
refusal to deal with African Americans without the equivalent of a monetary
bribe.
17
The situationofAfricanAmericansisobviouslymuchdifferenthistorically
fromthatofbad-lookingpeople.Butthecurrentsimilaritiesinthesituationsof
the two groups may provide as much logical justification for protecting ugly
workersthroughpublicpolicyasforprotectingAfricanAmericans.Inbothcases
—among African Americans and among bad-looking workers—the negative
outcomesthatoccur in many markets aretheresult of the preferences thatthe
majority has imposed on those markets. If we protect one group whose
disadvantages arise from those preferences, why not protect the other? On
economicgroundstheargumentsforprotectionseemthesameforboth.
With the exception of the discussion of dating and marriage, the same
argumentscouldbemadeifweweretoreplacebad-lookingcitizens,orAfrican
Americans,withwomen.Giventheirlevelofeducation(onaverageidenticalto
men’s in the United States), their earnings are lower, with the earnings
disadvantage being about 15 percent after numerous adjustments for other
determinantsofearnings.
18
Companies thatemployotherwiseidenticalwomen
havelowersales,andsoon.
19
Whilethereobviouslyisnoinherentprejudiceby
customers against women generally, the most useful theory of discrimination
thatunderliesstudiesofthedisadvantagesthatwomenfaceinvariousmarketsis
based on societal views about women’s roles. One can readily interpret those
views as reflecting consumers’ preferences—the same as the sources of the
apparentdiscriminationagainsttheugly.
WHATJUSTIFIESNOTPROTECTINGTHEUGLY?
The arguments in favor of protection seem very powerful. A leading legal
scholarhasarguedpassionatelyonfairnessgroundsthatlegalprotectionsshould
beextendedtobad-lookingpeopleandthatthoseprotectionsshouldbeenforced
vigorously.
20
Why not? After all, absent any logical basis for distinguishing
amonggroupstobeprotected,whyshouldmembersofonegroupbenefitfrom
government aid while others whose situations seem similar do not? The only
possibleargumentsagainstprotectionmustbebasedonthepotentialharmdone
to other groups by adding protections for the group proposed here—the bad-
looking. Otherwise, protecting the bad-looking would seem likely to benefit
societyoverall.
Onemightarguethattheaveragecitizen—arepresentativeofthemajority—
is harmedwhenanadditionalgroupofdisadvantagedcitizens is protected. To
the extent that the labor of the two groups is substitutable in employment,
additional protections for the ugly would reduce wage rates and/or lower
employmentopportunitiesforbetter-lookingworkers,particularlythosewhojust
missqualifyingforprotection—thenear-ugly,inthiscase.Evenifprotectionof
theuglydoesn’taffectothers’employmentopportunities,suchprotectionwould
still require the majority to pay taxes to finance the bureaucracy that would
enforceanyregulations.Whilecorrect,thisobjectioncouldberaisedagainstthe
protections afforded to any minority group. Indeed, because the disadvantages
experiencedbyprotectedgroupsareproducedbythepreferencesofthemajority
behavingasconsumers,membersofthemajorityarepreciselythosewhoshould
be made to bear the costs of protecting the minorities whom they have
disadvantaged.
If the costs of protection are only to be borne by the majority whose
preferencesgeneratethedisadvantagesfortheugly,whatcouldbetheargument
againstgrantingpreferencesforbad-lookingworkersinthelabor,housing,and
othermarkets?Onepossibilityis that lookism is so socially productive that to
enforce legal protections against it would reduce its social productivity. It is
socially productive; but I doubt that the social productivity of preferences for
goodlooks issufficienttoovercometheireconomiccosts.And,even ifit did,
thefairnessissuearguablywouldtrumpanyconcernsaboutsocialproductivity.
Thereisanotherargument,alsobasedonfairness,thatseemsmuchstronger.
Consideringasinterestedgroupsonlymajoritycitizensandbad-lookingcitizens
leaves out all the other non-majority groups that are currently offered legal
protection. The crucial economic issue here is the extent to which offering
protection for bad-looking workers might reduce the labor-market and other
opportunities of minority and other citizens whom we might choose to aid
throughlegislationandregulation.
Thereisnoevidenceonthedegreetowhichemployersareabletosubstitute
bad-looking for minority workers, and thus on the extent of job or earnings
losses that minority and other protected workers might experience if special
preferencesweregrantedtouglyworkers.Afewstudies,though,haveexamined
whetherworkersinonedisadvantagedgroup—forexample,low-skilledAfrican
Americans—tend to be substituted for or against by workers in other
disadvantaged groups—for example, low-skilled Hispanics.
21
The evidence is
not dispositive, but it does suggest that employers tend to treat as substitutes
workers in different low-skilled and disadvantaged groups, including some of
thosewhichareprotectedbyU.S.policy.
Putinstarkterms,aidingworkersinonedisadvantagedgrouptendstoreduce
wagesandtakejobsawayfromthoseinotherdisadvantagedgroups.Whatifthe
same phenomenon characterizes how employers treat bad-looking workers
compared to other disadvantaged workers? We would then have to infer that
offering protection to bad-looking workers would harm workers who we have
already determined deserve protection, and who already receive it through
legislationandregulations.
What if this economic argument is incorrect, so that helping bad-looking
workers does not cause economic harm to other disadvantaged workers? We
wouldstillhavetomakethepoliticaldecisiontospendscarcepoliticalresources
—legislativeactionandregulatoryandadministrativeeffortandmoney—tothe
benefitofonegroupinsteadofanother.Unlessyoubelievethatpoliticalwilland
administrativebudgetsareunlimited,whichhardlyseemslikely,aidingthebad-
looking means offering less aid to other groups which we currently protect or
mightwishtoprotectinthefuture. Publicfundsandenergyarenotunlimited.
Evenifdifferentdeservinggroupsarenoteconomicsubstitutes,theyarelikely
tobepoliticalsubstitutes—aidingonewillreducetheamountofeffortdevoted
toaidinganother.Andthatsubstitutionwillproduceeconomicharmtomembers
ofotherdisadvantagedgroups,astheamountofaidofferedtothemisreduced
bycompetitionfromtheaidtothebad-looking.
WHATISTHEAPPROPRIATEPOLICY?
The causes of mistreatment of the bad-looking, and their results—inferior
outcomesinalargevarietyofareas—seemlittledifferenteitherqualitativelyor
quantitatively from the mistreatment of other groups. Those include other
minorities,betheyracial,religious,orethnic,andevenagendermajority.Inall
instancesonecanarguethatthedisadvantagedgroupisharmedbythemajority
of citizens, or the most powerful citizens, who, for whatever reason, would
prefertodealwithpeoplewhoaremorelikethemselvesthandealwiththosein
thedisadvantagedgroup.
In the end, the decision about whether to aid bad-looking citizens in labor
markets,housingmarkets,andelsewheremustbe political.Ithastoweighthe
relativemeritsofdifferentgroupsthatmightbecompetingforhelp.Eachgroup
arguablyhasthesamekindofeconomicclaimonthesympathiesofthemajority,
asthedisadvantagesofeachhavebeengeneratedbytheirinabilitytoalterthe
characteristicsthatthepreferencesofthemajoritytreatasinferior.Sincesome
substitution,perhaps economic but surelypolitical,exists betweenbad-looking
andotherdisadvantagedgroups,eachofushastomakeavaluejudgmentabout
how deserving different groups are. Those views need to be translated into
policy—ornot—throughthepoliticalprocess.
Judgments about this issue depend on how large a weight you put on the
demonstrablegaininfairnessthatwouldcomefromprotectingthebad-looking
comparedtothepotentialimpactsonother,currentlyprotectedgroups.Onthese
considerations,thecentralityofraceinAmericanhistoryandthepoliticsofthe
past sixty years suggest that we need to pay special attention to any potential
reduction in protections for African Americans when we contemplate offering
additionalprotectiontobad-lookingAmericans.
Regardingotherprotectedgroups,theconcernsarelessclear.Likethebad-
looking, women and some ethnic minorities have an essentially immutable
characteristic with which they were born. While religion is not immutable,
Americanattitudes toward religiousfreedomsuggest that theeaseof changing
your religion should not detract from arguments for its protection. Also,
ethnicity,religion,andgenderhave been protected by federal law for nearly a
halfcentury.Ifwebelievethatthereiseithereconomicorpoliticalsubstitution
ofprotectionforonegroupagainstprotectionforanother,concernsaboutthese
groupsshouldmakeusthinkevenharderaboutextendingprotectiontotheugly.
Ourwillingnesstoprotectdisabledworkers,embodiedintheAmericanswith
Disabilities Act, is the most recent extension of the protections offered at the
federallevel. Protectioncouldbe extendedtoinclude badlooksas adisability
withaslightlybroaderinterpretationoftheADA,onethatgoesbeyondabasis
inlimitationsondailyactivities.Thismightbemoreacceptableifonlythevery
worst-looking people, people whoare generally agreed to be“1’s”—including
those with explicit facial disfigurements, either congenital or acquired—were
protected.Whetherprotectingeventhisnarrowlydefinedgroupisdesirableisa
less difficult question, but still one that requires thinking about the costs to
groupsthatarecurrentlyprotected.
Thedifficultiesinconsideringthisextensionareillustratedinstarktermsby
thefollowingexample.Compareaperson,nowreleasedfromprison,wholost
bothlegsinanautomobileaccidentthatwascausedbyhisdrunkendrivingand
that killed another driver, and another person who has been unusually bad-
lookingsincebirth.UndercurrentinterpretationsoftheADA,thedisableddrunk
drivermustbe offeredaccommodationinemploymentandotherareas,butthe
bad-lookingpersonwillreceivenosuchprotection.Thiscomparisonleavesone
wondering what the appropriate policy might be. I would argue in favor of
protectingtheuglypersonratherthanthedrunkdriver;butIwouldalsorealize
thattodosowouldmeancreatingasetofrulesthatmightreduceprotectionfor
disabledindividualsgenerally.
Extending protection to the bad-looking in hiring and promotions in labor
markets,andinaccesstorentalsandtomortgagesinhousingmarkets,maybe
worth consideration. Bad-looking people should command the sympathy of
othersalongasensibleRawlsiancriterion—essentially,therebutforthegraceof
GodgoI,andthatpossible“I”deservesprotection.Yettheuglyareonlyoneof
many groups of individuals who are deserving of protection. The scarcity of
politicalenergyforofferingprotection,andthedistinctpossibilitythatprotected
groupsaresubstitutesinemployment,shouldbeconsideredseriouslybeforewe
addthebad-lookingtothelist.
PROTECTINGTHEUGLYINTHENEARFUTURE
I would not be surprised if bad-looking Americans are eventually included
among those citizens protected by anti-discrimination and related legislation.
Thisextensionwouldbeespeciallylikelyifthedefinitionofbadlookswerekept
very narrow. This might come in the form of an expansion from the small
numberofjurisdictionsthathaveenactedlegislationtoprotecttheuglytomany
more local and even state protections, and perhaps even to federal legislation.
Morelikely,itcouldcomethroughan expansionof protectionsunderthecase
law, particularly under the ADA. But given how willing America has been to
expandprotectiontoadditionalgroupssincethefirstbroad-basedlegislationwas
enacted,predicting the inclusionofthe bad-looking underlegalprotection is a
reasonablebet.
PARTIV
TheFutureofLooks
CHAPTER9
Prospectsforthe
Looks-Challenged
THEBEAUTYCONUNDRUM
Beautypervadesspecificaspectsofeconomicbehavior.Butdoesitaffecthow
wefeelaboutourlivesgenerally?Willtheimpactsofbeautycontinueoverthe
nearandeventhemoredistantfuturethatshouldconcernallofus?Atleastas
important,shouldbeautycontinuetomatter:Doesanyevolutionarybasisforour
continued preoccupation with people’s looks remain? What could we as a
societydotolessenthenegativeimpactsofbadlooksonpeople’slives?Ifwe
do nothing and if the impacts of beauty do not disappear, what can looks-
challengedindividualsdotohelpthemselves?
AREBEAUTIFULPEOPLEHAPPIER?
Uglypeopleearnlessthanaverage-lookingpeople;andaverage-lookingpeople
earnlessthanthebeautiful.Uglypeoplefindentryintocertainoccupationsmore
difficult;andiftheychoosethoseoccupations,theirearningsarepenalized.Bad
looksevenaffectourchoicesaboutwhetherornottoworkforpay.Beingbad-
lookingmeansyouenterthedatingandmarriagegamewitha“weakerhand”—
lesstotradeforthecharacteristicsthatyouseekinapartner.Youhavelessofa
chancetoobtainloansforhousingandotherdurables.
So what? These are specific considerations. They involve how well people
fareinparticularaspectsoftheirlives,includingtheirworklives,theirlivesas
consumers, and their family lives. What if, taking all these specifics together,
beautifulpeoplearenohappierthanaverage-lookingorevenuglypeople?One
could even imagine a “Richard Cory” phenomenon where, despite all these
superficialadvantages,beautifulpeopleareactuallyunhappierthanothers.
1
Thisisjustnotso;quitethecontrary.Beautifulpeoplearealsohappierthan
their less good-looking counterparts. Two of the surveys used in this book
contain information on both beauty and happiness—people’s responses to
questionslike,“Howsatisfiedareyouwithlifeasawhole?”Fifty-fivepercent
ofthepeopleinthetopone-thirdoflooksstatedthattheywereverysatisfiedor
satisfiedwiththeirlives;53percentofpeopleinthemiddlehalfoflookssaidthe
samething;butonly45percentoftheworst-lookingone-sixthofthepopulation
saidtheyweresatisfied.
2
Badlooksandunhappinesswithlifegotogether;and
thatisespeciallytrueforpeoplewhomostotherswouldviewashomely.Taken
together,thenegativeeffectsofbadlooksonapanoplyofspecificeconomicand
social outcomes reduce people’s overall happiness. As Dorothy Parker said,
“Beautyisonlyskindeep,butuglygoescleantothebone.”
Thatunhappinessandbadlooksarerelatedisprobablynotsurprising.What
might be surprising is that the relationship is just as strong for men as for
women.
3
Thediscrimination against ugliness andthefavoritism toward beauty
thatcharacterizemodernsocietiesarenotatallagenderissue;theyareanissue
facingbothmenandwomen.
WHATWILLBEBEAUTIFUL?WHATSHOULDBE?
Perhaps the importance of differences in human beauty that produce all these
negativeimpactswilldeclineinthefuture.Afterall,fewerandfewerpeopleare
disfigured.And,whileourbeautyisdifficulttochange,withincreasingincomes
and improved surgical and other technologies, maybe people’s looks will
improveonaverage.Ifso,perhapswewillpaylessattentiontowhatwillhave
becomelessobviousdifferencesinpeople’slooks.
Oneauthornoted,“There’snoreasonforustothinkthatbeautifulpeopleare
good and ugly people evil, yet we do.”
4
Although we still view beauty as a
signalofdesirabilityinapotentialmate,worker,orborrower,itscontinueduse
for these purposes does not seem justified. In rich societies today, beauty and
health—reproductive fitness—are not generally correlated, although there may
exist a minuscule minority of individuals whose bad healthis signaledby bad
looks.Theevolutionarybasisfortheroleofbeautyinvariousmarketsnolonger
effectivelyexists.
5
A recent study offers a glimpse of change.
6
Women in a wide range of
countries were shown pictures of men’s faces, all of which matched the
symmetrystandardsofbeauty,butwhichdifferedintheirdegreeofmasculinity
(jawline,nosesize,andotheraspects).Thestudyshowedthatwherepeopleare
generallyhealthier,womenpaylessattentionto thedegree ofmasculinityina
man’sface.Itsuggestedthataswegetricher,ourcriteriaabouthumanbeauty
mightchange.Butwilltheychangetothepointthatwedon’tcareaboutlooks
anymore?
Perhaps;butevenifdistinctionsamongpeople’sbeautybecomefiner,itmay
beyourbeautyrelativetoothers’thatdeterminesyourpayoffs.Givenpeople’s
remarkable willingness and ability to make narrow distinctions among
themselves,it isquite possible,with anincreaseinaveragebeauty andgreater
homogeneityinlooks,thatthepenaltyforbeingjustslightlyworse-lookingthan
otherpeoplemightincreaseovertime.
Wecannotknowwhatfuturestandardsmightbe,butpeoplehaveimplicitly
speculatedonthem.Oneexampleiscontainedinthescience-fictionseriesFlash
Gordon,originallyacomic-bookseriesinthe1930s.Flash“lived”inthethirty-
third century CE, and, along with his love interest, Dale Arden, has been
depicted often over the past three-quarters of a century. As depicted in the
originalcomicbooksfromthe1930s,Flashwasblond,squared-jawed,andmid-
American. In the 2007 television series the actor who played Flash was again
blond, square-jawed, and mid-American. The forward-looking depictions have
been remarkably constant over these seventy-five years. In both cases the
individuals qualify as being above-average in looks. Now their looks may be
determined by the artists’ or producers’ desire to appeal to the standards of
beautyheldbypotentialcontemporary(withtheartist,notwithFlashandDale!)
readersorviewers.Buttosomeextenttheycanbeviewedaspredictionsabout
what might be beautiful in the future. Taken as such, and to the extent that
forecastingbeautystandardsispossible,theysuggestthatwebelievethatwhat
constituteshumanbeautyisunlikelytochangeanytimesoon.
Taking all these considerations together, I doubt that our perceptions of
human beauty will diminish in importance in our lifetimes. Industrialized
societiesarestuckinalow-levelequilibrium.Ourbehaviorisarelicofasetof
responsesthatnowlackabiologicalbasis.Inotherareasofeconomiclife,there
arenumerousexamplesoflow-levelequilibriathatwereestablishedasaresult
of some past characteristics and that remain in existence long after underlying
conditionshavechanged.
7
Sotoowithbeauty:thebeautifulwillbeadvantaged,
theuglywillbedisadvantaged,formanyyearstocome.
WHATCANSOCIETYDO?
Evenifsomeformsofprotectionforsomebad-lookingworkerseventuallycome
about,eitherthroughnewlegislationornewcaselaw,mostbad-lookingworkers
willnotfindprotection.Perhapsonlytheveryworst-looking,thosewithsevere
disfigurements,mightbehelped.Ifthathappened,peoplemightfeelthatenough
had been done and that the relevant problems had been solved. Yet the
disadvantagesofbadlooksnotonlyimpingeontheworst-looking1or2percent
of the population, but also on the one-sixth to one-eighth whose looks are
viewedasbelow-average.Theharmthatmostbad-lookingpeoplesufferwillnot
beremovedbylegislationorlawsuitsthatprotectatinyminority.Withoutlegal
protection, what would eliminate the discrimination that the rest of society
imposesonitsbad-lookingmembersinsomanyareasoflife?
One solution is to try to keep unemploymentas low as possible.We know
that employers cannot afford to indulge consumers’ preferences for workers’
beautyatatimewhenlaborisgenerallyscarce.Asidefrombeingdesirableon
macroeconomicgrounds, a policy ofthelowest possible unemploymentwould
create the additional benefit of reducing the earnings disadvantage of bad-
lookingworkers;anditmightevenspillovertotheirtreatmentinotherareas.
Discussionsoflow-levelequilibriainothercontexts—addictiontocigarettes
isagoodexample—suggestthatmaintainingapolicythattemporarilymovesa
system far away from an undesirable equilibrium can alter the nature of the
system.
8
Even if underlying conditions revert to the status quo ex ante, the
systemmaynotreverttothedetrimentaloutcomeifthechangedconditionshave
beenmaintainedlongenough.Lowunemploymentandtheresultingreductionin
the disadvantages in employment opportunities experienced by bad-looking
workersmight,iftheyprevailedlongenough,accustomconsumerstodealwith
bad-looking people in different contexts and reduce underlying prejudices
againstthem.Obviously,lowunemploymentandtightlabormarketsareunlikely
to persist indefinitely; but they are generally socially desirable, and their
potential beneficial impacts on bad-looking citizens offer one more basis for
them.
WHATCANYOUDOIFYOU’REBAD-LOOKING?
Persistent low unemployment that induces employers and customers to deal
equally with people regardless of their looks is not likely to be sufficient to
remove or even greatly reduce the disadvantages that bad-looking citizens
experience in so many endeavors. It is also not likely that legislation or
administrativeactionswillbebroadenoughtohelpmostbad-lookingcitizens.A
social solution, be it imposed orevolutionary, isunlikely tosolve mostof the
problemsofthelooks-challenged.
Intheend,abad-lookingpersonwillcontinuetofacethequestionofhowto
adjust to societal discrimination in work, dating, and marriage, choice of
housing, and other areas. The burden will, as it always has been, be on bad-
looking people to make the most of their advantages and to minimize the
impacts of the disadvantages caused by their looks. Substituting “less
intelligent”or“uncoordinated”forbad-looking,thisisthesameprescriptionthat
you would offer people who experience disadvantages arising from their
diminishedintellectualabilityorlackofathleticism.
In my media appearances discussing beauty I often get questions like, “If
somebodyisbad-looking,isthereanyhopefortheminthelabormarket?”The
answer is no and yes. No, in the sense that the research that I have presented
makes it clear that bad-looking people generally do worse in a wide range of
areasof dailylife.Ihavepresented evidenceon manyofthese; andI haveno
doubt that there are others that I have not discussed where the same kinds of
disadvantageswillbedemonstratedbyfutureresearch.
Theanswerwouldbeyes,though,inthesensethatlooksareonlyoneofthe
many appealing characteristics that people possess. As the title of an advice
articleinamagazineformiddle-agedwomensuggests,“MaketheMostofYour
Looks.”
9
IfIambad-looking,Iwillavoidoccupations(movieactor?)wheremy
badlookswillpenalizemegreatly.Instead,Iwillchooseanoccupationwhere
the skills that I possess in abundance have a chance to bring me the biggest
rewards,bothmonetaryandnon-monetary,andwheretherewardsforthegood
looksthatIlackarelessimportant.Soyes,plainpeoplearepenalized;butthey
can and should structure their careers to avoid the worst effects of those
penalties. Remember, too, that although differences in beauty have large
impacts, they account for only small parts of the differences in outcomes that
peopleexperienceatwork.
Similarly, in dating and marriage looks do matter initially. As the Beatles
sang,“Wouldyoubelieveinaloveatfirstsight?YesI’mcertainthatithappens
all the time” (“With a Little Help from My Friends”). But most bad-looking
peoplehaveothercharacteristicsthatcangivethemaromanticadvantagethat,
with careful nurturing, can help remove the initial disadvantages that their
physiognomiesinflictonthem.Onecouldmakethesameargumentsaboutcredit
and other markets. In the end, bad looks hurt us and will continue to hurt us.
Looks are fate; but so are many other things. But bad looks are not a crucial
disadvantage, not something that our own actions cannot at least partly
overcome, and not something whose burden should be so overwhelming as to
crushourspirit.
NOTES
CHAPTERONE:THEECONOMICSOFBEAUTY
1
The dataonthetimeinputs are from the American Time Use Survey,2003,categoryt6_10201. There
were5,240marriedmeninthesample,5,763marriedwomen,and1,087singlewomenageseventyorover.
2
FromtheConsumerExpenditureSurvey,asreportedinhttp://www.bls.gov/cex/csxstnd.htm#2008,table
3.
3
Calculatedbytheauthorfromthe1991–92Zeitbudgeterhebung.Thecategoryiszh031,waschenoder
anziehen.”
4
InternationalHerald-Tribune,August13,2008.
5
Nancy Etcoff, Survival of the Prettiest: The Science of Beauty (New York: Doubleday, 1999); Naomi
Wolf, The Beauty Myth: How Images of Beauty Are Used Against Women (New York: Anchor Books,
1992).
6
Vogue,September2009;Men’sHealth,December2008.
7
TimurKuranandEdwardMcCaffery,“ExpandingDiscriminationResearch:BeyondEthnicityandtothe
Web,”SocialScienceQuarterly85(September2004),pp.713–30.
8
 Daniel Hamermesh, “An Economic Theory of Suicide,” Journal of Political Economy 82
(January/February 1974), pp. 83–98; Mark Duggan and Steven Levitt, “Winning Isn’t Everything:
Corruption in Sumo Wrestling,” American Economic Review 92 (December 2002), pp. 1594–1605; Jeff
Biddle and Daniel Hamermesh, “Sleep and the Allocation of Time,” Journal of Political Economy 98
(October 1990), pp. 922–43; Lena Edlund and Evelyn Korn, “A Theory of Prostitution,” Journal of
PoliticalEconomy110(February2002),pp.181–214.
9
Oneofthebestnon-economicanalysesofbeautyanditsroleinhumanbehaviorisbymycolleagueDavid
Buss,TheEvolutionofDesire:StrategiesofHumanMating(NewYork:BasicBooks,1994).
CHAPTERTWO:INTHEEYEOFTHEBEHOLDER
1
http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/.
2
OwntranslationofBernhardSchlink,SelbsBetrug(Zürich:Diogenes,1994),p.9.
3
TheNewYorker,August30,2010,p.36.
4
http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/africa/3429903.stm.
5
In2008,itsGDPpercapitarankedit143rdoutof180countriesstudiedbytheInternationalMonetary
Fund:http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_countries_by_GDP_(PPP)_per_capita.
6
Genesis,29:17.
7
AngusCampbell,PhilipConverse,andWillardRodgers,QualityofAmericanLife,1971.Availablefrom
Inter-universityConsortiumforPoliticalandSocialResearch,StudyNo.3508.RobertQuinnandGraham
Staines,QualityofEmploymentSurvey,1977.AvailablefromICPSR,StudyNo.7689.
8
Daniel Hamermesh and Amy Parker, “Beauty in the Classroom: Instructors’ Pulchritude and Putative
PedagogicalProductivity,”EconomicsofEducationReview24(August2005),pp.369–76.
9
Daniel Hamermesh, “Changing Looks and Changing Discrimination: The Beauty of Economists,”
EconomicsLetters 93(2006), pp.405–12. Ina two-wayanalysis ofvariance ofthe standardizedaverage
looks ratings and the economists’ identification numbers, less than one-third of the variance was within
individuals.
10
Formal statistical testing of the independence of the ratings within each pair sharply rejects the
hypothesisthattheratingsarerandom.Thechi-squarestatisticsareallhighlysignificantlydifferentfrom
zero.
11
Fromatwo-wayanalysisofvarianceofthe5-pointlooksratingsandtheinterviewernumbers.
12
Allofthedifferencesbyagearesignificantstatistically.
13
NancyEtcoff,SurvivalofthePrettiest,1999.
14
ElaineHatfieldandSusanSprecher,Mirror,Mirror...(Albany:StateUniversityofNewYorkPress,
1986),p.283.
15
Judith Langlois, Jean Ritter, Lori Roggman, and Lesley Vaughn, “Facial Diversity and Infant
Preferences for Attractive Faces,” Developmental Psychology 27 (January 1991), pp. 79–84; Judith
LangloisandLoriRoggman,“AttractiveFacesAreOnlyAverage,”PsychologicalScience1(March1990),
pp.115–21.
16
AmericanSocietyofPlasticSurgeons,2008Reportofthe2007StatisticsoftheNationalClearinghouse
ofPlasticSurgeryStatistics.ArlingtonHeights,IL:ASPS,2008.
17
www.cosmeticsurgerybible.com/2008/news/uk-tops-table-for-european-cosmetic-surgery-spending.
18
Soohyung Lee and Keunkwan Ryu, “Returns to Plastic Surgery in Marriage and Labor Markets,”
unpublishedpaper,UniversityofMaryland–CollegePark,2009.
19
Therelativelysmalleffectsarebasedoncalculationsthataccountfordifferencesinthewomen’sfamily
incomes and ability to spend. To the extent that the data allow, problems of endogeneity in the
determinationofspendingonbeautyhavebeenaccountedfor.
20
For China, see http://www.chinadaily.com.cn/english/doc/2004-07/05/content_345598.htm. Stories
about the United States abound, for example, http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/30112465/ and More, April
2009,p.78.
CHAPTERTHREE:BEAUTYANDTHEWORKER
1
The 10 percent figure comes from a multivariate regression estimated over a large random sample of
Americans in 2007 (from the Current Population Survey, Merged Outgoing Rotation Groups). The true
figureisprobablymuchhigherforthegainsfromfinishinghighschool,orfromfinishingcollege.
2
Author’scalculationsfromCurrentPopulationSurvey(ibid.).
3
In2009,menaccountedfor52.5percentofemployees.Usingthatfigure,thesecalculationsarebasedon
weightedaveragesofthebeautyeffectslistedintable3.1.
4
Jeff Biddle and Daniel Hamermesh, “Beauty, Productivity and Discrimination: Lawyers’ Looks and
Lucre,”JournalofLaborEconomics16(January1998),pp.172–201.
5
Andrew Leigh and Jeff Borland, “Unpacking the Beauty Premium: Is It Looks or Ego?” unpublished
paper, Australian National University, 2007; Daniel Hamermesh and Jeff Biddle, “Beauty in the Labor
Market,”AmericanEconomicReview84(December1994),pp.1174–94;DanielHamermesh,XinMeng,
and Junsen Zhang, “Dress for Success—Does Primping Pay?” Labour Economics 9 (October 2002), pp.
361–73;SoohyungLeeandKeunkwanRyu,“ReturnstoPlasticSurgeryinMarriageandLaborMarkets,”
unpublished paper, University of Maryland–College Park, 2009; Barry Harper, “Beauty, Stature and the
LaborMarket:ABritishCohortStudy,”OxfordBulletinofEconomicsandStatistics62(December2000),
pp.771–800.
6
JasonFletcher,“Beautyvs.Brains:EarlyLaborMarketOutcomesofHighSchoolGraduates,”Economics
Letters105(December2009),pp.321–25.
7
At the very least, there are more claims of discrimination by workers when the unemployment rate is
higher:JohnDonohueandPeterSiegelman,“LawandMacroeconomics:EmploymentDiscriminationover
theBusinessCycle,”UniversityofSouthernCaliforniaLawReview66(March1993),pp.709–45.
8
PhilipRobins,MichaelFrench,andJennyHomer,“Non-CognitiveTraitsandLaborMarketEarningsof
YoungAdults,”unpublishedpaper,UniversityofMiami,2009.
9
Fletcher,“Beautyvs.Brains.”
10
SusanAverettandSandersKorenman,“TheEconomicRealityoftheBeautyMyth,”JournalofHuman
Resources 31 (Spring 1996), pp. 304–30. John Cawley, “The Impact of Obesity on Wages,” Journal of
HumanResources39(Spring2004),pp.451–74;ChristianGregoryandChristopherRuhm,“WhereDoes
theWagePenaltyBite?”inEconomicAspectsofObesity,ed.MichaelGrossmanandNaciMocan(Chicago:
UniversityofChicagoPress,2011).GiorgioBrunelloandBéatriced’Hombres,“DoesBodyWeightAffect
Wages:EvidencefromEurope,”EconomicsandHumanBiology5(March2007),pp.1–19.
11
Nicola Persico, Andrew Postlewaite, and Dan Silverman, “The Effect of Adolescent Experience on
Labor Market Outcomes: The Case of Height,” Journal of Political Economy 112 (October 2004), pp.
1019–53.WenshuGaoandRussellSmyth,“Health,HumanCapital,HeightandWagesinChina,”Journal
ofDevelopmentStudies46(2010),466–84.
12
Dan-Olof Rooth, “Obesity, Attractiveness, and Differential Treatment in Hiring,” Journal of Human
Resources44(Fall2009),pp.710–35.
13
WallStreetJournal,Friday-Saturday,November26–27,1993,page1,quotingindirectlyNaomiWolf,
authorofTheBeautyMyth.
14
Thequote,asitappearsinvariousplaces,is“EsistleichtereinAtomzuspalten,alseinVorurteil.”
15
Compare,forexample,thesurveysofempiricalevidencebyJohnPencavel,andbyJamesHeckmanand
MarkKillings-worth,inOrleyAshenfelterandRichardLayard,eds.,HandbookofLaborEconomics,Vol.1
(Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1986); and the survey by Richard Blundell and Thomas MaCurdy in
Ashenfelter and David Card, eds., Handbook of Labor Economics, Vol. 3A (Amsterdam: North-Holland,
1999).
16
ArthurGoldsmith,DarrickHamilton,andWilliamDarity,“FromDarktoLight:SkinColorandWages
amongAfrican-Americans,”JournalofHumanResources42(Fall2007),pp.701–38.
CHAPTERFOUR:BEAUTYINSPECIFIC
OCCUPATIONS
1
In the case of opera, the career of the soprano Florence Foster Jenkins early in the twentieth century
providestheexceptionthatprovestherule.
2
ThetabloidsofthetimereferredtoHamlinandoneotherattorneyontheshowas“L.A.Lawhunks.”
3
ThelateZviGrilichesofHarvardUniversity,personalconversationsometimeinthe1980s.
4
Jeff Biddle and Daniel Hamermesh, “Beauty, Productivity and Discrimination: Lawyers’ Looks and
Lucre,” Journal of Labor Economics 16 (January 1998), pp. 172–201. The twenty-four underlying
categorieswerecombinedintofourgroupsbyanexperiencedattorney—mywife.
5
AbigailPogrebin,StarsofDavid(NewYork:BroadwayBooks,2005),p.10.
6
http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/europe/7581039.stm.
7
Lee Lillard, “The Market for Sex: Street Prostitution in Los Angeles,” unpublished paper, RAND
Corporation,1995.
8
Paul Gertler, Manisha Shah, and Stefano Bertozzi, “Risky Business: The Market for Unprotected
CommercialSex,”JournalofPoliticalEconomy113(June2005),pp.518–50.
9
RajArunachalamandManishaShah,“TheProstitute’sAllure:TheReturntoBeautyinCommercialSex
Work,”unpublishedpaper,UniversityofMichigan,2009.
10
www.theeroticreview.com offers detailed information for members on the characteristics of a huge
numberofescorts,alongwithpriceschargedforvariousservices.
11
Lena Edlund, Joseph Engelberg, and Christopher Parsons, “The Wages of Sin,” unpublished paper,
UniversityofNorthCarolina–ChapelHill,2009.
12
MikeMurphy,quotedbyMaureenDowd,NewYorkTimes,July29,2009.
13
Daniel Benjamin and Jesse Shapiro, “Thin-Slice Forecasts of Gubernatorial Elections,” Review of
EconomicsandStatistics91(August2009),pp.523–36.
14
Andrew Leigh and Tirta Susilo, “Is Voting Skin-deep? Estimating the Effect of Candidate Ballot
PhotographsonElectionOutcomes,”JournalofEconomicPsychology30(February2009),pp.61–70.
15
AmyKingandAndrewLeigh,“BeautifulPoliticians,”Kyklos62(November2009),pp.579–93.
16
MarkusKleinandUlrichRosar,“PhysischeAttraktivitätundWahlerfolg:EineEmpirischeAnalyseam
Beispiel der Wahlkreiskandidaten bei der Bundestagswahl 2002,” Politische Vierteljahresheft 46 (2005),
pp.266–90.
17
NiclasBerggren,Henrik Jordahl,andPanu Poutvaara,“TheLooksofaWinner:BeautyandElectoral
Success,”JournalofPublicEconomics94(February2010),pp.8–15;Cheng-DaLiandMing-ChingLuoh,
“BeautyPremiumsinPolitics—TheCaseofthe2004LegislatorElectionsinTaiwan,”TaiwanEconomic
Review36(March2008),pp.67–113.
18
Marcus Maurer and Harald Schoen, “Der Medial Attraktivitätsbonus: Wie die Physische Attraktivität
vonWahlkreiskandidatendieMedienberichterstattunginWahlkämpfenBeinflusst,”KölnerZeitschriftfür
SoziologieundSozialpsychologie62(June2010),pp.277–95.
19
IreneFrieze, Josephine Olson,andJune Russell, “AttractivenessandIncome for Men andWomenin
Management,”JournalofAppliedSocialPsychology21(July1991),pp.1039–57.
20
Anindya Sen, Marcel Voia, and Frances Woolley, “The Effect of Hotness on Pay and Productivity,”
unpublishedpaper,CarletonUniversity,October2010.
21
Statisticalevidence infavorof thenotionthat teachingqualityaffects salaryisoffered byWilliamJ.
Moore,RobertNewman,andGeoffreyTurnbull,“DoAcademicSalariesDeclinewithSeniority?”Journal
of LaborEconomics16 (April 1998), pp. 352–66, whodemonstratethe link between receipt ofteaching
awards and salary. The evidence on the impact of teaching evaluations is less direct, but my personal
experiencesinevaluatingyoungfacultyfortenureandteachingawardssuggestthatevaluationsreceivea
lot,perhapseventoomuchattentionintheseprocesses.
22
DanielHamermeshand Amy Parker,“Beautyin the Classroom: Instructors’Pulchritude and Putative
PedagogicalProductivity,”EconomicsofEducationReview24(August2005),pp.369–76.
23
BerndSüssmuth,“BeautyintheClassroom:AreGermanStudentsLessBlinded?”AppliedEconomics
38(February2006),pp.231–38.
24
Daniel Hamermesh, “Changing Looks and Changing Discrimination: The Beauty of Economists,”
EconomicsLetters93(December2006),pp.405–12.
25
DavidBerri,RobSimmons, Jennifer van Gilder, andLisleO’Neill,“What Does It Mean to Findthe
FaceoftheFranchise?”unpublishedpaper,SouthernUtahUniversity,2009.
26
Naci Mocan and Erdal Tekin, “Ugly Criminals,” Review of Economics and Statistics 92 (February
2010),pp.15–30.
CHAPTERFIVE:BEAUTYANDTHEEMPLOYER
1
Andrea Weber and Christine Zuhlehner, “Female Hires and the Success of Start-up Firms,” American
EconomicAssociation,PapersandProceedings100(May2010),pp.358–61.
2
Quoted in an interview reported at http://www.telegraph.co.uk/fashion/3302299/You-can-always-get-
what-you-want.html.
3
GerardPfann, Jeff Biddle,CiskaBosman, and DanielHamermesh, “Business SuccessandBusinesses’
BeautyCapital,”EconomicsLetters67(May2000),pp.201–7.
4
DeTijd,July28,2000,p.32.
5
CraigLandry,AndreasLange,JohnList,MichaelPrice,andNicholasRupp,“TowardanUnderstanding
of the Economics of Charity: Evidence from a Field Experiment,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 121
(May2006),pp.747–82.
6
MichaelPrice,“Fund-RaisingSuccessandaSolicitor’sBeautyCapital:DoBlondesRaiseMoreFunds?”
EconomicsLetters100(September2008),pp.351–54.
7
Peter Kuhn and Kailing Shen, “Employers’ Preferences for Gender, Age, Height and Beauty: Direct
Evidence,”unpublishedpaper,UniversityofCalifornia–SantaBarbara,2009.
8
ReportedinAustinAmerican-Statesman,July19,2004,p.A1.AstoryinaChinesenewspaperin2005(in
Mandarin)evenreportedthatonegovernmentagencypostedahelp-wantedadvertisementsuggestingthat
onlywomenwithlargebreastsneedapply.
9
This difference has been shown for various years for many northern European countries by numerous
authors, with one of the clearest demonstrations being by Dan Devroye and Richard Freeman, “Does
Inequality in Skills Explain Inequality in Earnings Across Advanced Countries?” National Bureau of
EconomicResearch,WorkingPaperNo.8140,February2001.
10
See,forexample,GeorgeBorjas,LaborEconomics,4thedition(New York:McGraw-Hill,2008),pp.
277–79,foradiscussionoftheideaoffirm-specifichumancapital,aconceptthatgoesbacktotheearly
1960s.
11
Cash8,no.34(August23,1996),p.1.
12
NicholasRuleand Nalini Ambady, “The FaceofSuccess: Inferences from ChiefExecutiveOfficers’
AppearancePredictCompanyProfits,”PsychologicalScience19(2008),pp.109–11.
13
Fortherelationshipbetweenpayandcompanyprofits,seeKevinJ.Murphy,“ExecutiveCompensation,”
inHandbookof LaborEconomics,vol.3B,ed.OrleyAshenfelterandDavidCard(Amsterdam:Elsevier,
1999),pp.2485–2563.
CHAPTERSIX:LOOKISMORPRODUCTIVE
BEAUTY,ANDWHY?
1
Merriam-WebsterOnlineDictionary,http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary.
2
GaryBecker,TheEconomicsofDiscrimination(Chicago:UniversityofChicagoPress,1957).
3
Edmund Phelps, “The Statistical Theory of Racism and Sexism,” American Economic Review 62
(September 1972), pp. 659–61; Dennis Aigner and Glen Cain, “Statistical Theories of Discrimination in
LaborMarkets,”IndustrialandLaborRelationsReview30(January1977),pp.175–87.RolandFryerand
MatthewJackson,“ACategoricalModelofCognitionandBiasedDecisionMaking,”BerkeleyElectronic
JournalContributionstoTheoreticalEconomics8(2008),goastepbeyondthistoanalyzetheeconomics
oftheformationofgroupsthatunderliethestatisticaltheories.
4
Barbara Bergmann, “The Effect on White Incomes of Discrimination in Employment,” Journal of
PoliticalEconomy79(March–April1971),pp.294–313.
5
Amongthemanydiscussionsofthisapproach,HowardGardner,FramesofMind:TheTheoryofMultiple
Intelligences(NewYork:BasicBooks,1983),isperhapsthemostwellknown.
6
This is a standard Harberger-triangle calculation. Take the extent of wage discrimination against the
worst-looking workers as 10 percent as compared to all other workers, and figure their fraction in the
workforceis10 percent.Both ofthesefigures accordwiththe evidencein chapters2and 3,asdoes the
assumptionthattheuglyareonaverageasskilledastherestofthelaborforce.Then,evenifthedemand
elasticityforthelaborofthisgroupofworkersisashighastwo(seeDanielHamermesh,LaborDemand,
Princeton,NJ:PrincetonUniversityPress,1993),thecosttosocietyofmisallocatingtheirlaborwouldbe
about0.25percent (.1 ×.1 × .5×.5) of totalcompensation. In 2009,compensationof employeesinthe
United States was about $8 trillion, so that the loss to society of this kind of socially unproductive
discriminationis$20billion.
7
Markus Möbius and TanyaRosenblat,“WhyBeautyMatters,” American Economic Review 96 (March
2006),pp.222–35.
8
James Andreoni and Ragan Petrie, “Beauty, Gender and Stereotypes: Evidence from Laboratory
Experiments,”JournalofEconomicPsychology29(2008),pp.73–93.
9
Sara Solnick and Maurice Schweitzer, “The Influence of Physical Attractiveness and Gender on
Ultimatum Game Decisions,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 79 (September
1999),pp.199–215.
10
Michèle Belot, V. Bhaskar, and Jeroen van de Ven, “Beauty and the Sources of Discrimination,”
unpublishedpaper,UniversityCollege–London,2008.ThegameshowwasentitledShafted,andtheauthors
usedallepisodesfrom2002.
11
“Wimbledon Puts Tennis Babes Front and ‘Centre’,
http://www.foxnews.com/story/0,2933,529865,00.html.
CHAPTERSEVEN:BEAUTYINMARKETSFOR
FRIENDS,FAMILY,ANDFUNDS
1
SeeLaurenceIannaconne,“SacrificeandStigma:ReducingFree-RidinginCults,CommunesandOther
Collectives,”JournalofPoliticalEconomy100(April1992),pp.271–91.
2
SeeAlanFeingold,“MatchingforAttractivenessin RomanticPartnersandSame-sexFriends:A Meta-
Analysis and Theoretical Critique,” Psychological Bulletin 104 (September 1988), pp. 226–35, for a
summaryofalargenumberofstudiesofthisissue.
3
Marco Castillo, Ragan Petrie, and Maximo Torero, “Beautiful or White? Discrimination in Group
Formation,”unpublishedpaper,GeorgeMasonUniversity,2010.
4
NewYorkTimes,March24,2009,p.D1.
5
Feingold,“MatchingforAttractiveness.”
6
http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/world/asia-pacific/7567239.stm is among the many websites discussing this
statement.
7
Susan Fisk, “Competition and Social Exchange: Female Attractiveness as an Object of Exchange in
DatingMarkets,”unpublishedpaper,DepartmentofSociology,StanfordUniversity,2008.
8
RaymondFisman,SheenaIyengar,EmirKamenica,andItamarSimonson,“GenderDifferencesinMate
Selection:EvidencefromaSpeedDatingExperiment,”QuarterlyJournalofEconomics121(May2006),
pp.673–97.
9
Günter Hitsch, Ali Hortaçsu, and Dan Ariely, “Matching and Sorting in Online Dating,” American
EconomicReview100(2010),pp.130–63.Hitsch,Hortaçsu,andAriely,“WhatMakesYouClick?”Mate
PreferencesandMatching:OutcomesinOnlineDating,”unpublishedpaper,UniversityofChicago,2006.
10
Forexample,themedianworkerages25–34in2008hadbeenatthejobfor2.7years,whilethemedian
workerages55–64hadbeenwiththesameemployerfor9.9years.U.S.DepartmentofLabor,Bureauof
LaborStatistics,EmployeeTenurein2008.
11
Theseestimatesarebasedonregressionsthataccountforspouses’ages,differencesintheirhealth,and
othercharacteristics.
12
Calculatedas10percentperyeartimes1.1(12.4–11.3)years.
13
SoohyungLee,“MarriageandOnlineMate-SearchServices:EvidencefromSouthKorea,”unpublished
paper,UniversityofMaryland,2009.
14
AbhijitBanerjee,EsterDuflo, Maitreesh Ghatak, and Jeanne Lafortune,“Marryfor What? Caste and
Mate Selection in Modern India,” National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper No. 14958,
2009.
15
David Bjerk, “Beauty vs. Earnings: Gender Differences in Earnings and Priorities over Spousal
CharacteristicsinaMatchModel,”JournalofEconomicBehaviorandOrganization69(March2009),pp.
248–59.
16
SeeFeingold,“MatchingforAttractiveness,”whichsummarizesstudiesofspouses’looks.DavidBuss,
TheEvolutionofDesire:StrategiesofHumanMating(NewYork:BasicBooks,1994),discussesthismore
generally.
17
Liliana Alvarez and Klaus Jaffe, “Narcissism in Mate Selection: Humans Mate Assortatively, as
Revealed by Facial Resemblance, Following an Algorithm of ‘Self Seeking Like,’ ” Evolutionary
Psychology2(2004),pp.177–94.
18
Atestoftheentiredistributionshowsthatitishighlynon-random,withaX
2
(4)=413.8,wherethe99
percentcriticalvalueis13.28.
19
http://www.ronsangels.com/index2.html.
20
Onlongevity, see DanielHamermeshand Frances Hamermesh,“Does Perception ofLifeExpectancy
ReflectHealthKnowledge,”AmericanJournalofPublicHealth73(August1983),pp.911–14.Thestudy
oftheintergenerationalrelationofheightsisthemotivationforregressionanalysis,asStephenStigler,The
HistoryofStatistics:TheMeasurementofUncertaintyBefore1900(Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversity
Press, 1986), so beautifully discusses. Although there are many other works, I find Leon Kamin, The
ScienceandPoliticsof IQ(NewYork:HalstedPress,1974),tobeaparticularlyuseful discussionofthe
issuesintheheritabilityofintelligence.
21
http://www.breitbart.com/article.php?id=CNG.33f98480
869b474b6d10cafcf0b1de64.7c1&show_article=1.
22
http://snltranscripts.jt.org/84/84iwhitelikeeddie.phtml.
23
AliciaMunnell,GeoffreyTootle,LynnBrowne,andJamesMcEneany,“MortgageLendinginBoston:
InterpretingHMDAData,”AmericanEconomicReview86(March1996),pp.25–53.
24
Enrichetta Ravina, “Love and Loans: The Effect of Beauty and Personal Characteristics in Credit
Markets,” unpublished paper, New York University, March 2008; Jefferson Duarte, Stephan Siegel, and
LanceYoung,“Trust andCredit,”unpublished paper,RiceUniversity, November2008.Devin Popeand
Justin Sydnor, “What’sinaPicture?Evidence of Discrimination from Prosper.com,” unpublishedpaper,
WhartonSchool,UniversityofPennsylvania,2008.
CHAPTEREIGHT:LEGALPROTECTIONFORTHE
UGLY
1
http://www.sfgov.org/site/sfhumanrights_index.asp?id=4583.
2
SeeDeborahRhode,TheBeautyBias:TheInjusticeofAppearanceinLifeandLaw(NewYork:Oxford
UniversityPress,2010),chapter6,foralongerdiscussionoftheseprovisions.
3
Discussion of the California Fair Employment and Housing Act, California Department of Consumer
Affairs,isat(http://www.dca.ca.gov/publications/landlordbook/discrimination.shtml).
4
http://wallis.kezenfogva.iif.hu/eu_konyvtar/projektek/
vocational_rehabilitiation/france/fra_rap/leg.htm.
5
Foradiscussionofthecaseshere,aswellasmanyothers,seeJenniferFowler-Hermes,“Beautyandthe
Beast in the Work-place: Appearance-based Discrimination under EEO Laws,” Florida Bar Journal 75
(April2001).
6
ThecasesdiscussedhereandthelegalissuesgenerallyarepresentedbyElizabethTheran,“LegalTheory
on Weight Discrimination,” in Weight Bias: Nature, Consequences and Remedies, ed. Kelly Brownell,
RebeccaPuhl,LeslieRudd,andMarleneSchwartz(NewYork:GuilfordPress,2005),pp.195–211.
7
JamesMcDonald,“CivilRightsfortheAesthetically-Challenged,”EmployeeRelationsLawJournal29
(Autumn2003),pp.118–29,discussesthedevelopmentoflawinthisarea.
8
Timothy Van Dyck, Edwards, Engell, Palmer & Dodge, July 17, 2008,
http://www.employmentlawalliance.com/en/node/2393.
9
The case of the Malone twins, Boston firefighters whose claim to be African American on their job
applicationswaseventuallychallenged,isthemostwell-knownexampleofthedifficultiesinclassification
and with self-classification (New York Times, October 9, 1988;
http://www.nytimes.com/1988/10/09/us/boston-case-raises-questions-on-misuse-of-affirmative-action.html?
pagewanted=all). Other cases have arisen. In Washington State, when individuals who had listed
themselves as being members of various protected racial/ethnic groups were asked to provide some
supporting evidence, 3 percent switched their self-description to Caucasian
(http://aad.english.ucsb.edu/docs/proof.html).
10
http://www.eeoc.gov/stats/charges.html.
11
See,forexample,http://www.radiancemagazine.com/kids_project/body_image.html.
12
Foradiscussionoftheseevents,seehttp://www.dallasnews.com/sharedcontent/dws/fea/lifetravel/
stories/082708dnmetabercrombie.4027698.html.
13
CalculationsarebytheauthorfromtheCurrentPopulationSurvey,MergedOutgoingRotationGroups,
2008.
14
Ibid.Calculationsusingdatafor2008basedontheusualearningsofmenwiththesameeducation,age,
hoursofwork,location,andmaritalstatus.
15
Judith Hellerstein, David Neumark, and Kenneth Troske, “Wages, Productivity, and Worker
Characteristics:EvidencefromPlant-LevelProductionFunctionsandWageEquations,”JournalofLabor
Economics 17 (July 1999), pp. 409–46; and John Haltiwanger, Julia Lane, and James Spletzer, “Wages,
Productivity,andtheDynamicInteractionofBusinessesandWorkers,”LabourEconomics14(June2007),
pp.575–602.
16
Foradiscussionoftheverylow,butrisingintermarriageratesintheUnitedStates,seeRolandFryer,
“GuessWho’sBeenComingtoDinner?TrendsinInterracialMarriageoverthe20thCentury,”Journalof
Economic Perspectives 21 (Spring 2007), pp. 71–90. In 2008, 21 percent of African Americans had not
completed high school, while only 12 percent of non-Hispanic whites had that little education. Only 17
percentofAfricanAmericanshadatleastgraduatedfromcollegeoruniversity,while29percentofnon-
Hispanicwhiteshaddoneso.Computedusingthesamemethodsanddataasprovidedinnote13.
17
SeeClarkNardinelliandCurtisSimon,“CustomerRacialDiscriminationintheMarketforMemorabilia:
TheCaseofBaseball,”QuarterlyJournalofEconomics105(August1990),pp.575–95;OrleyAshenfelter
and Timothy Hannan, “Sex Discrimination and Product Market Competition: The Case of the Banking
Industry,”QuarterlyJournalofEconomics101(February1986),pp.149–73.
18
Computedusingthesamemethodsanddataasprovidedinnote13.
19
See Hellerstein et al., “Wages, Productivity, and Worker Characteristics,” and Haltiwanger et al.,
“Wages,Productivity,andtheDynamicInteractionofBusinessesandWorkers.”
20
Rhode,TheBeautyBias.
21
An early study of this issue is George Borjas, “The Substitutability of Black, Hispanic and White
Labor,” Economic Inquiry 21 (January 1983), pp. 93–106. See also most of the studies in Daniel
Hamermesh and Frank Bean, eds., Help or Hindrance: The Economic Implications of Immigration for
African-Americans(NewYork:RussellSageFoundation,1998),particularlythosebyGeorgeJohnsonand
byBorjas.
CHAPTERNINE:PROSPECTSFORTHELOOKS-
CHALLENGED
1
...heflutteredpulseswhenhesaid,
“Good-morning,”andheglitteredwhenhewalked
...
AndRichardCory,onecalmsummernight,
Wenthomeandputabulletinhishead.
EdwinArlingtonRobinson
2
Calculationsfrom the1971and 1978 QualityofAmerican Lifesurveys.The only scholarlystudythat
seems to have examined this issue using a nationally representative sample employed the 1978 data to
summarize a happiness measure in each of the five categories of beauty: Debra Umberson and Michael
Hughes, “The ImpactofPhysical Attractiveness on Achievement and PsychologicalWell-Being,”Social
PsychologyQuarterly50(September1987),pp.227–36.SeealsoDanielHamermeshandJasonAbrevaya,
“‘BeautyIsthePromiseofHappiness’?”,IZADiscussionPaperNo.5600,2011.
3
Calculationsfromthesamesourcesasinnote2.
4
AnthonySynott,sociologist,quotedinInternationalHerald-Tribune,November4,2008.
5
S. Michael Kalick, Leslie Zebrowitz, Judity Langlois, and Robert Johnson, “Does Human Facial
AttractivenessHonestlyAdvertiseHealth?”PsychologicalScience9(January1998),pp.8–13.
6
Lisa DeBruine, Benedict Jones, John Crawford, Lisa Welling, and Anthony Little, “The Health of a
NationPredictsTheirMatePreferences:Cross-culturalVariationinWomen’sPreferencesforMasculinized
MaleFaces,”ProceedingsoftheRoyalSociety,PartB,277(August2010),pp.2405–10.
7
The idea goes back at least to Richard Nelson, “A Theory of the Low-Level Equilibrium Trap in
Underdeveloped Economies,” American Economic Review 46 (December 1956), pp. 894–908. John
Dagsvik and Boyan Jovanovic, “Was the Great Depression a Low-Level Equilibrium?” European
EconomicReview38(December1994),pp.1711–29,discussitinthecontextofmacroeconomics.
8
Gary Becker and Kevin Murphy, “A Theory of Rational Addiction,” Journal of Political Economy96
(August1988),pp.675–700,istheleadstudyexpoundingthisidea.TheapplicationtocigarettesisbyGary
Becker,MichaelGrossman,andKevinMurphy,“AnEmpiricalAnalysisofCigaretteAddiction,”American
EconomicReview84(June1994),pp.396–418.
9
More,October2008,p.143.
INDEX
AbercrombieandFitch,159
actors,13–15,32,67–71,110,176,179
advertising,88–93,96,139,142–43,146,191n8
aesthetics,12
affirmativeaction,151–52,199n9
AfricanAmericans,144
affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
educationand,200n16
employmentand,58–59,76,108,110
legalissuesand,154,157,161–62,165
Malonetwinsand,199n9
standardsofbeautyand,29–30
age:AgeDiscriminationinEmploymentAct(ADEA)and,150
AmericanswithDisabilitiesAct(ADA)and,150–51,155,158,167–69
attorneysand,60–63
datingand,133
earningsand,44,52,56,59–63,75–79,83,118,190n21
employmentand,44,52,56,59–63,75–79,83,118,190n21
groupformationand,129
legalprotectionand,148,150,153
prostitutesand,75
standardsofbeautyand,11,22–23,27–34
vanityand,3–4
AgeDiscriminationinEmploymentAct(ADEA),150
AmericanEconomicAssociation,81–82
AmericanswithDisabilitiesAct(ADA),150–51,155,158,167–69
analysisofvariance(ANOVA),183nn9,11
Arden,Dale,176
artisticability,103,110,176
AsianAmericans,15–16,29
assistedlivingfacilities,4
athletics,66,82–83,120,127–30,179
attorneys,188n4
administrative,71
ageeffectsand,60–63
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkerand,63–64
corporate,71
employmentand,48–52,60–64,67–68,71–72,78–79,83,88,91,102,119–20
financial,71
L.A.Lawand,68–71
LawSchoolAptitudeTest(LSAT)and,52
legalissuesand,157,159(seealsolegalissues)litigators,68
lookismand,102,119–21
productivebeautyand,102,119–20
regulation,71
tax,68
Australia,15,49,76,82,133
bad-lookingpeople,5,35
affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
AgeDiscriminationinEmploymentAct(ADEA)and,150
agreementonrightsof,156–60
AmericanswithDisabilitiesAct(ADA)and,150–51,155,158,167–69
appropriatepolicyfor,166–68
BodyImageTaskForceand,158
CivilRightsActand,150–51
datingand,132
earningsand,155,158–64,173–74
employmentand,39,41,46–47,51–52,56–57,64,67,71,83–89,97,102–10,113–21
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC)and,150,155,158
ExecutiveOrder10925and,151
ExecutiveOrder11246and,151
fairnessand,148–49
futureissuesfor,158–59,173–80
happinessand,173–77
homelinessand,22,27,29,31,35,46–48,96,149,152,174
legalprotectionfor,148–69
legislationfor,149–52
aslooks-challenged,149,173–80
marriageand,137–39
nerdsand,19,52
prejudiceand,15,103–6,121,146,158,162,178
productivebeautyand,102–10,113–21
prospectsfor,173–80
protectedclassesand,149–52
publicpolicyand,148–49
strategiesfor,178–80
taxburdenand,163–64
useofexistingpoliciesand,154–56
Baldwin,Alec,xi
Beatles,180
beauty:asaggregateofpersonalqualities,11
bimboeffectand,48
clothingand,3–4,12,20,33–35,54,113,154
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkerand,61–64
cosmeticsand,3,33–35,88,109,113
coworkerinspirationand,95–97
culturaldifferencesand,4,16,21–27,30–31
definitionsof,11–18
earningsand,18,29,40–55,58–67,71–79(seealsoearnings)economicsof,3–10(seealsoeconomics)
exchangeof,126–27
facial,12–15,19–20,31,33,35,53–54,61–62,66–67,82–84,98–99,112–14,142,155,167,175–76
fleetingnatureof,35
futureissuesfor,173–80
groomingand,153–58
groupformationand,125–26,128–30,146
hairand,3,12,33–34,91,128–29,154,176
happinessand,173–75
heightand,12,53–54,127,137,143,152–53,157
help-wantedadvertisementsand,93,191n8
hotnessand,79–80,159
increasing,32–35
internal,12
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,141–44
measurementof,19–24(seealsoscaleofbeauty)
modernobsessionwith,3
personalityand,51–52
plasticsurgeryand,32–35,113–14
premiumfor,7,18,39–52,55,59,67,73,89,105,112–13,116,148
asproduct,88–89
profiteffectsfrom,92–97,100–1
scarcityof,6,8–9,24,28,50,133–34
scholarlypaperson,x
skinand,12,58,76,174
sociallyproductive,103,108–11
sortingby,84–85
specificoccupationsand,66–85
symmetryand,31–33,82–83,175
timespentprimpingand,3–4
weightand,12–13,16,21,53–54,152–57
youthand,31,33,35,83–84(seealsoage)beautyeffect:ageand,59–61
clothingand,54
constancyof,51
datingand,129–35
discriminationand,103–8(seealsodiscrimination)
meaningof,102–3
raceand,58–59
salesand,87–92,100–1
sizeofimpactof,72–84
smallereffectsamongwomenand,55–58
sourcesof,111–21
beautypageants,72
Becker,Gary,ix,103
behavior,4–6,147,182n9
consumerpreferenceand,106,112,120–21,163–64,177–78
datingand,126–35,139
economic,7–8,173(seealsoeconomics)employmentand,42,51,66,87
futureoflooksand,173,177
groupformationand,125–26,128–30,146
happinessand,34,41,82,121,142,146,158,173–75,201n2
marriageand,137
personalityand,51–52
productivebeautyand,102–3,106,111,117–18
psychologistsand,9–10,31,33,51,98,129–32,140
romantic,28,68,180
self-confidenceand,51,115
standardsofbeautyand,13,18,21,36
sympathetic,12,166,168
Bible,18
Biddle,Jeff,x
bimboeffect,48
biology,5,143,177
blondes,91,176
BodyImageTaskForce,158
bodypaints,4
Bond,James,110
books,5
Bosman,Ciska,x
Botox,32
Boyle,Susan,5
boys,3–5,129,132–33
BraveNewWorld(Huxley),141
breasts,191n8
brideprice,125
California,152–53
Callas,Maria,71
Canada,25–27,49,51,57,79
Cash(newspaper),98
CEOs,98–100
cheerleaders,128
children,56,61–62
boys,3–5,129,132–33
girls,3–5,16,19,64,129,133
infants,4,128,184n15
intelligenceand,142–43
marketforbeautiful,141–44
ovaauctionsand,141–43
spermdonorsand,141,144
teenagersand,3,64
China,5
breastsizeand,191n8
employmentand,49,53,93,191n8
marriageand,137–38
Shanghaistudiesand,23,27–28,30,34,49,137–38,141
standardsofbeautyand,23,30,34
chi-squarestatistics,183n10
cigarettes,178
CivilRightsAct,150–51
Clooney,George,13,15
clothes,3–4
employmentand,54,113
legalissuesand,154
standardsofbeautyand,12,20,33–35
successand,33
ColemanV.GeorgiaPowerCo.,155
competition:datingand,133
employmentand,40–41,50,77,81,86–89,93–94,97,101,120
legalissuesand,165–66
Cooke,Sam,131
Cookv.RhodeIslandDepartmentofMentalHealth,Retardation,andHospitals,155
Cory,Richard,174
cosmetics,3,33–35,88,109,113
cosmeticsurgery.Seeplasticsurgery
cost-benefitanalysis,93
Craig,Daniel,110
crewcuts,3
criminals,83–84
culturaldifferences,4
earningsand,49
help-wantedadvertisementsand,93,191n8
standardsofbeautyand,16,21–27,30–31
customers,80
beautyeffectonsalesand,87–92,100–1
CEOappointmentsand,99
legalissuesand,155,162
loansand,145
preferencesof,106,112,120–21,163–64,177–78
productivebeautyand,107,113
workers’looksand,41–42,58–60,75
D.A.haircuts,128–29
dating,125
ageand,133
bad-lookingpeopleand,132
beautyeffectson,129–35
behaviorand,131–35
competitionand,133
earningsand,132,139–40
easeofanalyzing,130–31
economicsof,135
excessoffemalesand,133
exchangeofbeautyand,126–27
futureoflooksand,174,179–80
genderdifferencesin,130–35,139,146
asinformation-gathering,136
intelligenceand,127,134
Koreaand,139
legalissuesand,162
marriageand,135–36,139(seealsomarriage)matcheddatesand,132
menand,133–35
online,132,139
photographsand,133,135
preferenceand,130–32,135
purposeof,136
reproductivefitnessand,131
scarcityofbeautyand,132–33
sexratiosand,133–34
shortageofmalesand,133
skillsand,131
speed,134–35
successand,131,134–35
womenand,133–35
Deneuve,Catherine,88
discrimination:AgeDiscriminationinEmploymentAct(ADEA)and,150
AmericanswithDisabilitiesAct(ADA)and,150–51,155,158,167–69
beautypremiumand,39–52,55,59,67,73,105,112–13,116,148
BodyImageTaskForceand,158
CivilRightsActand,150–51
consumer,106,112,120–21,163–64,177–78
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC)and,150,155,158
EqualEmploymentOpportunity(EEO)and,155
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
ethnicityand,5,39,44,63,106,130,144,148,152,159,166–67
ExecutiveOrder10925and,151
ExecutiveOrder11246and,151
futureissuesand,174–79
gameshowcontestantsand,118–19
Greenspanand,86–87
height,152–53
intermarriageand,200n16
labor-marketand,55,86–87,102–12,115–16,119–20
legalprotectionfrom,148–69
loansand,144–46
lookismand,103–8,114–21
lower-paidwomenand,86–87
Malonetwinsand,199n9
marriageand,140
preferenceand,10,41–42(seealsopreference)prejudiceand,15,103–6,121,146,158,162,178
productivebeautyand,102–12,115–16,119–20
raceand,144–45(seealsorace)
sexismand,140
stereotypesand,30,106–7
treatmentofappearanceand,153–58
wage,105(seealsoearnings)
weight,152–53,198n6
disfigurement,35
compensationfor,61–64
earningsand,142,158
futurepoliciesand,175,177
legalissuesand,155,167
lookismand,112–14
DistrictofColumbia,153
divorce,136
dolls,3
door-to-doorsales,67,91
dowry,125
Dr.Faustus(Marlowe),19
Dr.Seuss,6
earnings,29
ageand,44,52,56,59–63,75–79,83,118,190n21
bad-lookingpeopleand,155,158–64,173–74
beautypremiumand,7,18,39–52,55,59,67,73,89,105,112–13,116,148
clothesand,54,113
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkerand,61–64
competitionand,40–41,50,77,81,86–89,93–94,97,101,120
culturaldifferencesand,49
datingand,132,139–40
disfigurementand,61–64,158
educationand,46,199n14
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC)and,150
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
executivesand,7,62,68,78,89–99
futurepoliciesand,173–74,178
legalissuesand,155,158–64
lower-paidwomenand,86–87
marriageand,18,44,138–43
obesityand,53
offsettinghigher-paidgood-lookingemployeesand,88,91–97,105,109
otherfactorson,44,51–55
personalityand,51–52
productivebeautyand,100,102,105–7,110,113,117–21
raceand,39–40,44,58–59
self-esteemand,51
skillsand,40,60,71,84,90–93,96,108–10,115,131,140,150,165,179,192n9,193n6
smallerbeautyeffectsamongwomenand,55–58
specificoccupationsand,66–67,71–79,82–85
unionsand,44,46
economics,6–7
AmericanEconomicsAssociationand,81–82
beautyeffectonprofitsand,92–97
beautypremiumand,18,39–52,55,59,67,73,89,105,112–13,116,148
bottom-lineand,100–1
clothingand,3–4,33–35,113
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkerand,61–64
consumerpreferenceand,106,112,120–21,163–64,177–78
customersand,41–42,58–60,75(seealsocustomers)datingand,135
earningsand,18,29,40–55(seealsoearnings)fairnessand,148–49
asfun,ix
Greenspanand,86–87
higherpricesand,18,73,89
highersalesfromgood-lookingemployeesand,87–92
loansand,14–46
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,141–44
marriageand,136
offsettinghigher-paidgood-lookingemployeesand,88,91–97,105,109
ovaauctionsand,141–43
plasticsurgeryand,32–35
productivebeautyand,102–21
salesand,7,42,67,87–102,106–12,121,159–60,162
scarcityofbeautyand,6,8–9,24,28,50,133–34
skillsand,40,60,71,84,90–93,96,108–10,115,131,140,150,165,179,192n9,193n6
specificoccupationsand,81–82
spermdonorsand,141,144
taxesand,163
unemploymentand,50,67,177–78,186n7
Ecuador,74
education:;AfricanAmericansand,200n16
bimboeffectand,48
employmentand,43,46,63,73,90,199n14
enjoymentofcoursesand,80
legalissuesand,151,160–62
marriageand,137–38
MBAsand,78
professorsand,24,26,29,67,79–84,106,120–21
SATscoresand,134
socialissuesand,127,132–39
successand,131
Egypt,4
elections,76–78,81–82
employers:advertisingand,88–93,96,191n8
beautyeffectonprofitsand,92–97
better-lookingCEOsand,98–100
bottom-lineand,100–1
cost-benefitanalysisand,93
coworkerinspirationand,95–97
Dutchadvertisingstudyand,89–90,93–94
Fortune500companiesand,98–99
lookismand,102–21
marketsurvivalpuzzlesand,86–87,97
offsettinghigher-paidgood-lookingemployeesand,88,91–97,105,109
productivityand,89–90,95,99–100,102–3,107–11,115–21
salesand,87–101
sociallyproductivebeautyand,108–9
employment:affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
ageand,44,52,56,59–63,75–79,83,118,190n21
antiquatedoccupationsand,107–8
applicantphotographsand,48,54,71,75–78,82,90,93
bad-lookingpeopleand,39,41,46–47,51–52,56–57,64,67,71,83–89,97,102–10,113–21
beautypremiumand,18,39–52,55,59,67,73,89,105,112–13,116,148
behaviorand,42,51,66,87
bimboeffectand,48
choosinganoccupationand,66–72
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkersand,61–64
customersand,41–42,58–60,75,80,88–91,99,107,112–13,119–21,145,155,162,178
earningsand,18,29,40–55(seealsoearnings)educationand,43,46,63,73,90,199n14
employersand,86–101
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC)and,150,155,158
EqualEmploymentOpportunity(EEO)and,155
ExecutiveOrder10925and,151
ExecutiveOrder11246and,151
executivesand,7,62,68,78,89–99
incumbentsand,72,76–80,90
intelligenceand,52–53,79,85,102,108–9
jobinterviewsand,48,53–54,59,73–74
laborunionsand,44,46
legalissuesand,150–65,168
marriageand,44,73,85
menand,39,43–47,49,50,53,55–58,64,78,86,185n3,199n14
Mormonsand,57
personalityand,51–52
productivebeautyand,40,56,60,68,79–82,89–90,95,99–121
raceand,58–59
salesand,7,42,67,87–102,106–12,121,159–60,162
self-esteemand,51
sizeofbeautyeffectsand,72–84
skillsand,40,60,71,84,90–93,96,108–10,115,131,140,150,165,179,192n9,193n6
specificoccupationsand,66–85
successand,48,60,67–68,71–81,84,87–88,91,98,100
unemploymentand,50,67,177–78,186n7
UnitedStatesand,39–42,46–53,61,65,76,81,83,93–94,110,117
U.S.DepartmentofLaborand,151–52
womenand,39,43–50,53–58,64,73–75,78,86–88,184n19
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC),150,155,158
EqualEmploymentOpportunity(EEO),155
EqualPayAct(EPA),150
ethics,114,148–49
ethnicity,5,63,106
affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
appropriatepolicyfor,166
earningsand,39–40,44
KuKluxKlanand,154
legalissuesand,148,152,159,166–67
loansand,144
lookismand,130
evolution,31,173,175,179
ExecutiveOrder10925,151
ExecutiveOrder11246,151
executives,7,62,68,78,89–99
eyeofthebeholder.Seestandardsofbeauty
eyes,12
Facebook,49,133
Face-Off(film),32
faces,202n6
bodyweight/heightand,53–54
CEOsand,98–100
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkerand,61–64
disfigured,61–64,112,155
focuson,11–15,19–20,31–32
genderand,55,175–76
mirrorsand,3
physiognomyand,12–13,20–21,54,67,143,180
plasticsurgeryon,113–14
forradio,66–67
standards ofbeautyand,12–15, 19–20, 31, 33, 35, 53–54, 61–62, 66–67,82–83,84,98–99, 112–14,
142,155,167,175–76
symmetric,32,175–76
Western,15
fairness,148–49
family,4,44,56,127,137,174,184n19
fatfarms,16
5to1scale,19–25,43,50,73,80,82,90,96,115
FlashGordon(comic-bookseries),176
Fortune500companies,98–99
France,4,32,153–54
Frankv.UnitedAirlines,155
friends,4,132
groupformationand,125–26,128–30,146
lookismand,116
gender,5,175
appropriatepolicyfor,166
datingand,126–35,139
employmentand,55–58,63,77,82,106,118
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
husbandsand,3–4,8,18,138–41,144
legalissuesand,146,150,153–59,166–67
standardsofbeautyand,11,22,27–32,36
studentratiosand,133–34
wivesand,3–4,8,18,137–41.Seealsomen;womenGermany,4,32,77,81,158
girls,3–5,16,19,64,129,133
Gordon,George(LordByron),xii
Greenspan,Alan,86–87
grooming:clothingand,3–4,12,20,33–35,54,113
employersand,88
hairand,3,12,33–34,91,128–29,154,176
legalissuesand,153–58
groupformation,125–26,128–30,146
hair,3,12,33–34,91,128–29,154,176
Haley,Nikki,16,75
Hamermesh,Daniel,ix-xii,110
Hamermesh,FrancesW.,xi–xii
Hamermesh,Madeline,xi
Hamlin,Harry,68,69f
happiness,146
beautifulchildrenand,142
employmentand,41,82,121
futureprospectsand,173–75,201n2
legalissuesand,158
standardsofbeautyand,34
Harberger-trianglecalculation,193n6
Harvard,132
Hathaway,Anne,88
health,34,44,127,131,175–76,196n11
height,12,53–54,127,137,143,152–53,157
Heyward,DuBose,139
Hispanics,73,165,200n16
Hoffman,Dustin,71
Hollinsv.Atlantic,154
Hollywood,13,32,68–71,110
homeliness,22,27,29,31,35,46–48,96,149,152,174
hoodykids,128–29
hotness,79–80,159
House(TVshow),85
HowardCounty,Maryland,153
“How-to-Vote”cards,76–78
husbands,3–4,8,18,138–41,144
incumbents,72,76–80,90
infants,4,128,184n15
intelligence,179
attorneysand,52
bimboeffectand,48
datingand,127,134
educationand,137–38(seealsoeducation)
employmentand,52–53,79,85,102,108–9
groupformationand,128,130
LawSchoolAptitudeTest(LSAT)and,52
legalissuesand,148
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,142–43
marriageand,137
SATscoresand,134
intermarriage,200n16
internalbeauty,12
Internet,49,135,142
interviews:job,48,53–54,59,73–74
photographsand,20–21
scaleofbeautyand,20–30,34,183n11
invitrofertilization,141
Italians,32,72
Iveyv.DistrictofColumbia,156
Jacob(Biblicalpatriarch),18
Jagger,Jade,89
Jagger,Mick,89
JanandDean,133
jewelry,4,89
Johnson,LyndonB.,151
judgment.Seephysiognomy
JunsenZhang,x
Kennedy,JohnF.,151
KentuckyFriedChicken(KFC),155
Korea,33,49,139,196n13
KuKluxKlan,154
labormarket.Seeemployment
LakeWobegoneffect,23
L.A.Law(TVshow),68–71
Langlois,Judith,xi,31
LawSchoolAptitudeTest(LSAT),52
legalissues,177
affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
ageand,148,150,153
AgeDiscriminationinEmploymentAct(ADEA)and,150
agreementonrightsofuglyand,156–60
AmericanswithDisabilitiesAct(ADA)and,150–51,155,158,167–69
appropriatepolicyand,166–68
BodyImageTaskForceand,158
CivilRightsActand,150–51
Colemanv.GeorgiaPowerCo.,155
compensatingbeauty-damagedworkerand,61–64
competitionand,165–66
Cookv.RhodeIslandDepartmentofMentalHealth,Retardation,andHospitals,155
datingand,162
disfigurementand,61–64,155,167
employmentand,150–65,168
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC)and,150,155,158
EqualEmploymentOpportunity(EEO)and,155
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
ethnicityand,148,152,159,166–67
ExecutiveOrder10925and,151
ExecutiveOrder11246and,151
fairnessand,148–49
Frankv.UnitedAirlines,155
futurepoliciesand,158–59
genderidentityand,146,150,153–59,166–67
governmentlegislationand,149–60,166–69
heightdiscriminationand,152–53
Hollinsv.Atlantic,154
intelligenceand,148
Iveyv.DistrictofColumbia,156
Malonetwinsand,199n9
marriageand,160–62
menand,154,159,161
minoritiesand,148
protectedclassesand,149–52
protectionforbad-lookingpeopleand,148–69
publicpolicyand,148–49
raceand,150,153–54,159,161,166
religionand,148,150,153–54,167
Swartzentrubev.GuniteCorp.,154
taxburdenand,163–64
treatmentofappearanceand,153–58
UnitedStatesand,148–49,162
useofexistingpoliciesand,154–56
weightdiscriminationand,152–53,155–57
Levitt,Steve,ix
Lincoln,Abraham,87
loans,144–46
lookism:defined,102–3
discriminationand,103–8,114–21
legalissuesand,164
meaningofbeautyeffectand,102–3
productivebeautyand,102–21
socialproductivityand,103,108–11
societalcostsof,109–11
sourcesofbeautyeffectsand,111–21
McDonald’s,155
Madison,Wisconsin,153
magazines,5,33,49,179
Malonetwins,199n9
manicures,3,33
Marlowe,19
marriage,131
bad-lookingpeopleand,137
beautyeffectson,135–41
behaviorand,137
bridepriceand,125
Chinaand,138
divorceand,136
dowryand,125
earningsand,18,44,126,129,138–40
economicsof,136
educationand,137–38
employmentand,44,73,85
exchangeofbeautyand,126–27
futureoflooksand,174,179–80
intelligenceand,137
intermarriageand,200n16
Koreaand,139
legalissuesand,160–62
long-term,136
asmarket,8–9
matchedbeautyand,140–41
menand,138–40,146
preferenceand,135–36,140
ringexchangeand,125
standardsofbeautyand,18
UnitedStatesand,137–38
womenand,138–40,146
Mauritania,16
media,5,9,33,49,62,77–78,132,179
Meir,Golda,75
men,5
actorsand,13–15,32,67,68–71,176,179
blond,176
datingand,126–35,139
door-to-doorsalesand,91
employmentand,39,43–47,49–50,53,55–58,64,78,86,185n3,199n14
facialbeautyand,55,175–76,202n6
futureoflooksand,174–75
legalissuesand,154,159,161
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,142
marriageand,138–40,146
sexiest,13–15
shortageof,133
spermdonorsand,141,144
standardsofbeautyand,13–15,18,22–30
superstarsand,127
Mexico,73–74,93
Michigan,152
Mikulski,Barbara,16,17f,75
Moore,Melinda,xi
Mormons,57–58
mouth,12
multivariateregression,185n1,196n11,197n20
Murphy,Eddie,144–45
musicalability,71,84,103,110
NationalBureauofEconomicResearchLaborStudies,xi
NationalFootballLeague,82–83
Nazis,158
nerds,19,52
nuns,72
nursinghomes,4
obesity,53,155
occupationalchoices,66–72,84
Oettinger,Gerald,xi
Olympics,5
onlinedating,132,139
operasingers,66,71,187n1
ovaauctions,141–43
Palin,Sarah,75
Parker,Amy,x
Parker,Dorothy,174
Pavarotti,Luciano,110
pedicures,3
personality,51–52
Pfann,Gerard,x–xi
Phelps,Edmund,106–7
photographs:datingand,133,135
employmentand,48,54,71,75–78,82,90,93
help-wantedadvertisementsand,93
“How-to-Vote”cardsand,76–78
lookismstudiesand,116–17
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,142
marriageand,140
obtainingloansand,145
productivebeautyand,115–18
scaleofbeautyand,20–26,29
physiognomy,54,67,180
biasand,24,27
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,141–44
photographsand,20–21
standardsofbeautyand,12–13,20–21
plasticsurgery,32–36,113–14
Pogo(comicstrip),121
politicians,75
electionsand,76–78,81–82
“How-to-Vote”cardsand,76–78
standardsofbeautyand,15–17
PorgyandBess(opera),139
preference:10,145–46
consumer,106,112,120–21,163–64,177–78
datingand,130–32,135
earningsand,41–42(seealsoearnings)
groupformationand,128–29
legalissuesand,150,161–66
marriageand,135–36,140
occupationalchoicesand,68,84
productivebeautyand,102–12,115–21
sexual,5,106,149,153
smallerbeautyeffectsofwomenand,57–58
primping,3–4
productivebeauty:attorneysand,102,119–20
behaviorand,102–3,106,111,117–18
discriminationand,102–12,115–21
Dutchadvertisingstudyand,89–90
employmentand,40,56,60,68,79–82,89–90,95,99–100,102–3,107–11,115–21
lookismand,102–21
meaningofbeautyeffectand,102–3
photographsand,115–18
social,103,108–11
societalcostsof,109–11
sourcesofbeautyeffectsand,111–21
successand,109,119
uglinessand,104–5,108,110,113,121
womenand,107–8,118,120
professors,24,26,29,67,79–84,106,120–21
profits.Seesales
prostitutes,9,67,73–75,78,91,109
protectedclasses,149–52
psychology,9–10
datingand,130–32
employersand,98
groupformationand,125–26,128–30,146
matchedbeautyinmarriagepartnersand,140–41
standardsofbeautyand,12,31,33
workerbeautyand,51
QualityofAmericanLifesurveys,201n2
race:affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
AfricanAmericans,29–30,58–59,76,108,110,144,154,157,161–62,165,199n9,200n16
appropriatepolicyfor,166
changing,161
Chinese,5,23,30,34,49,53,93,137–38,191n8
CivilRightsActand,150–51
earningsand,39–40,44,58–59
educationand,200n16
Hispanics,73,165,200n16
intermarriageand,200n16
KuKluxKlanand,154
legalissuesand,150,153–54,159,161,166
loansand,144–45
Nazisand,158
prostitutestudiesand,73–75
standardsofbeautyand,28–32
Rachel(Biblicalcharacter),18
radiobroadcasting,66–67,84
religion,72
appropriatepolicyfor,166
discriminationand,106,148,153–54
easeofchanging,166
groupformationand,129–30
legalissuesand,148,150,153–54,166–67
Mormonsand,57
Renoir,13
reproduction,131
ovaauctionsand,141–43
spermdonorsand,141,144
invitrofertilizationand,141
successin,131,142,175
romance,28,68,180
Roosevelt,Theodore,75
Rossellini,Isabella,xi,88
Sacks,Oliver,12
sales:beautyeffecton,87–92,100–1
consumerpreferenceand,106,112,120–21,163–64,177–78
cosmeticsand,88
employersand,87–101
haircolorand,91
raisingofbygood-lookingemployees,87–92
salespeople,67,88,91,106,109
salons,4
samples,x
analysisofvariance(ANOVA)and,183nn9,11
Argentinestudyand,114–15
biasand,24,27
Canadianstudyand,25–27
comparisonofdeterminantsand,46
consistencyand,25–26
datingand,132
Dutchadvertisingstudyand,89–90
employmentenvironmentand,43–44,52,58,77,94,113–14
Harberger-trianglecalculationand,193n6
lookismstudiesand,114–21
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,141
multivariateregressionand,185n1,196n11,197n20
prostitutestudiesand,73–75
QualityofAmericanLifesurveysand,201n2
random,5,27–28,42–43,52,56,58,77,112–14,117,141,157,183n10,185n1,196n18
Shanghaistudiesand,23,27–28,30,34,49,137–38,141
speed-datingand,134–35
standardsofbeautyand,24,28–29
statisticsand,24,27,45,47,76–77,81,99,106–8,117,137,145,183nn10,12
telephonesurveysand,5.Seealsointerviews
SanFrancisco,152–53
SantaCruz,153
SATscores,134
SaturdayNightLive(TVshow),144
scaleofbeauty,xi
culturaldifferencesand,23–24
datingand,133–34
5to1scale,19–25,43,50,73,80,82,90,96,115
hotnessand,79–80,159
intellectualizingand,22
interviewsand,20–30,34,183n11
LakeWobegoneffectand,23
legalissuesand,159
lookismand,115–18
meaningofscoresand,20–24
photographsand,20–26,29
10to1scale,19,24,26,82,91,133
uglinessand,23–24,193n6
scarcebeauty,6,8–9,24,28,50,133–34
self-confidence,51,115
sex:datingand,133
genderand,5,11,22,27–32,55–58,63,77(seealsogender)legalprotectionsand,150,153–54
marriageand,137
prostitutesand,9,67,73–75,78,91,109
reproductivefitnessand,131,142,175
standardsofbeautyand,13,22,30
sexism,140
sexratios,133–34
sexualpreference,5,106,149,153
Sharipova,Maria,120
skills:employmentand,40,60,71,84,90–93,96,108–10,115,131,140,150,165,179,192n9,193n6
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
help-wantedadvertisementsand,93,191n8
social,108,131,142
skin,12,58,76,174
Sneetches(Dr.Seuss),6
socialissues:affirmativeactionand,151–52,199n9
AgeDiscriminationinEmploymentAct(ADEA)and,150
CivilRightsActand,150–51
culturaldifferencesand,4,16,21–27,30–31,49
datingand,126(seealsodating)
discriminationand,5(seealsodiscrimination)
educationand,43,46,63,73,90,127,132–39,151,160–62,199n14,200n16
EqualEmploymentOpportunityCommission(EEOC)and,150,155,158
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
ExecutiveOrder10925and,151
ExecutiveOrder11246and,151
fairnessand,148–49
groupformationand,125–26,128–30,146
legalprotectionfortheuglyand,148–69
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,141–44
marriageand,126(seealsomarriage)
politiciansand,15–17,75,78
positivestrategiesfor,177–80
religionand,106,130,150,153–54,167
sociallyproductivebeauty,103,108–11
socialnetworks,49,133
socialskills,108,142
specificoccupations:actors,13–15,32,67–71,176,179
athletes,82–83
attorneys,48–52,60–64,67–68,71–72,78–79,83,88,91,102,119–20,159,188n4
choosing,66–72,84
criminals,83–84
economists,81–82
operasingers,66,71,187n1
politicians,15,17,67,75–78
preferenceand,68,84
professors,24,26,29,67,79–84,106,120–21
prostitutes,9,67,73–75,78,91,109
radiobroadcasters,66–67,84
requirementsand,67–68
salespeople,67,88,91,106,109
sizeofbeautyeffectsand,72–84
skillsand,71,84
sortingbybeautyand,84–85
speed-dating,134–35
spermdonors,141,144
spokespersons,88,120
standardsofbeauty,10
ageand,11,22–23,27–34
agreementon,11–13,15,18–21,24–28,31–32,35–36,99,126,156–57
behaviorand,13,18,21,36
bodyweight/heightand,53–54
culturaldifferencesand,4,16,21,23,26–27,30–31
definitionsofbeautyand,11–17
executivesand,7,62,68,78,89–99
facesand,12–15,19–20,31,33,35,53–54,61–62,66–67,82–84,98–99,112–14,142,155,167,175
76
futurechangesin,173–80
genderand,28–32,36
importanceof,18–19
increasingbeautyand,32–35
marriageand,18
measurementfor,19(seealsoscaleofbeauty)
menand,13–15,18,22–30
raceand,28–32
uglinessand,23–24,28,31–32,36
UnitedStatesand,15–16,23,27,30,32
universal,15–16,21,27
womenand,13–15,18,22–25,28–30,34,36
start-upcompanies,87
statistics:ageand,183n12
analysisofvariance(ANOVA)and,183nn9,11
chi-square,183n10
Harberger-trianglecalculationand,193n6
employmentand,45,47,76–77,81,99,106–8,117
loansand,145
marriageand,137
multivariateregressionand,185n1,196n11,197n20
standardsofbeautyand,24,27
stereotypes,30,106–7
strength,84,103,131,137
success:beautifulchildrenand,142
datingand,131,134–35
dressingfor,33
educationand,131
employmentand,48,60,67–68,71–81,84,87–88,91,98,100
legalissuesand,155,160
obtainingcreditand,145
productivebeautyand,109,119
reproductive,131,142,175
standardsofbeautyand,13,31,33
“Summertime”(operaaria),139
supermodels,127
superstars,127
“SurfCity”(JanandDean),133
Swartzentruberv.GuniteCorp.,154
Switzerland,98
symmetry,31–33,82–83,175
sympathy,12,166,168
Taiwan,77–78
taxes,163–64
teenagers,3,64
telephonesurveys,5
10to1scale,19,24,26,82,91,133
time:employmentand,6–7,40,56,60,67–68,89,125
groupformationand,128–29
primping,3–4
marriageand,136
matingand,31
spentonbeauty,3–4,7,9,181n1
standardsofbeautyand,13,25,31
transplants,3
Travolta,John,32
Trejo,Steve,xi
Tucker,Michael,68,70f
ugliness,126,146
datingand,132
employmentand,41,52,57,67,71,83,87,89,97,104–5,108,110,113,121
houseworkand,57
legalprotectionfor,148–69
marriageand,137
productivebeautyand,104–5,108,110,113,121
scalefor,23–24,193n6
standardsfor,23–24,28,31–32,36.Seealsobad-lookingpeopleuglyducklings,31
UglyTruth,The(film),146
unemployment,50,67,177–78,186n7
unions,44,46
UnitedKingdom,49,52–53,118
UnitedStates,3–5,176,200
AmericanswithDisabilitiesAct(ADA)and,150–51,155,158,167–69
employmentand,39–61,64–65,76,81,83,93–94,110–11,117
legalissuesand,148–50,154,162,166–69
marriageand,137–38
standardsofbeautyand,15–16,23,27,30,32
UniversityofMichigan,21–22
UniversityofNorthCarolina,133
UniversityofTexasatAustin,xi,31,80
Urbana,Illinois,153
U.S.DepartmentofLabor,151–52
U.S.FederalReserve,86
Valentino,Rudolf,13,14f
vanity,3
Washington,George,75
weight:BodyImageTaskForceand,158
Colemanv.GeorgiaPowerCo.and,155
Cookv.RhodeIslandDepartmentofMentalHealth,Retardation,andHospitalsand,155
employmentand,53–54
fatfarmsand,16
Frankv.UnitedAirlinesand,155
legalissuesand,152–57,198n6
obesityand,53,155
standardsofbeautyand,12–13,16,21
“WhiteLikeEddie”(Murphy),144–45
WillowbrookHighSchool,128–30
Wimbledon,120
Winslet,Kate,88
Witness(film),131
wives,3–4,8,18,137–41
women,3–4
actressesand,32
bimboeffectand,48
blond,91,176
datingand,126–35,139
donatedovumand,141–43
door-to-doorsalesand,91
employmentand,39,43–50,53–58,64,73–75,78,86–88,184n19
EqualPayAct(EPA)and,150
excessof,133
facialbeautyand,55
futureoflooksand,174–76,179
Greenspanand,86–87
largebreastsand,191n8
legalissuesand,148,152,159,161–63,167
lower-paid,86–87
magazinesfor,5,33,49,179
marketforbeautifulchildrenand,142
marriageand,138–40,146
asmorebeautiful,28–30
Mormonsand,57
productivebeautyand,107–8,118,120
smallerbeautyeffectsamong,55–58
standardsofbeautyand,13–15,18,22–25,28–30,34,36
start-upcompaniesand,87
supermodelsand,127
“WonderfulWorld”(Cooke),131
wrinkles,32
XinMeng,x
youth,31,33,35,83–84