Taking Credit
William J. Graham
William H. Cooper
Received: 17 August 2011 / Accepted: 10 July 2012
Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012
Abstract Taking credit is the process through which
organizational members claim responsibility for work
activities. We begin by describing a publically disputed
case of credit taking and then draw on psychological, sit-
uational, and personality constructs to provide a model that
may explain when and why organizational members are
likely to take credit. We identify testable propositions
about the credit-taking process, discuss ethical aspects of
credit taking and suggest areas for research on credit taking
in organizations.
Keywords Credit Business ethics
Organizational justice Psychological ownership
Fraud triangle Narcissism
Good people do good work without meddling in the
distribution of rewards (Confucius, n.d., verse 4.14)
There are two classes of people, those who do and
those who take credit. My advice is to be a member
of the first class; there is much less competition.
(Variously attributed to Mahatma Gandhi, Indira
Gandhi, Dwight Morrow, and Mark Twain)
It is amazing what you can accomplish if you do not
care who gets the credit. (Harry Truman)
The person who appropriates credit redistributes it as
he chooses, bound essentially and only by a sensi-
tivity to public perceptions of his fairness. (Jackall
1988, p. 21)
Credit can be a valuable commodity in organizations.
Credits—defined as having one’s efforts recognized by
others—can be exchanged for small privileges (e.g., a day
off), banked (e.g., used to enhance a reputation), pointed
to for tactical reasons (e.g., during a performance review),
accumulated for major rewards (e.g., a promotion),
redeemed (e.g., asking for a favor), and traded (e.g., for a
leadership opportunity); credit can also be dissipated (e.g.,
eroded by time and memory) and lost (e.g., by making a
major blunder). Because credits are valuable they can also
be challenged by aggrieved colleagues who feel the credit
belongs to them, either in whole or in part. These credits
might be based on perceived contributions to any part of a
work activity (project, idea, collaboration, assignment):
having the idea, proposing it to someone who matters,
refining, and crystallizing the idea, providing support,
assigning appropriate resources, and structures for the
project, implementing the idea, assuming the risks associ-
ated with implementation, doing the hard work required to
finish the project, and framing the outcome so that it is seen
as worthwhile, both for the organization and for the framer.
The process of making a bid for credit can take many
forms, ranging from the most active (e.g., putting one’s
name on a document, arranging for a colleague to give you
credit in a public setting) and explicit (e.g., written or
verbal assertions) to the most passive (e.g., failing to cor-
rect the record when someone gives credit to a non-con-
tributor) and implicit (structuring a situation so that the
inference is drawn of one’s personal responsibility for an
effort). The process of bidding for and getting credit can be
W. J. Graham
Royal Military College, Kingston, ON, Canada
W. H. Cooper (&)
Queen’s School of Business, Kingston, ON, Canada
123
J Bus Ethics
DOI 10.1007/s10551-012-1406-3
simple and quick, as when someone says ‘‘When I did this’
and the audience agrees: the outcome is credit. But when
the claim is implicit it can take some time for an audience
to recognize that credit has been claimed and that credit has
been given though silence. Attentive audiences may readily
detect explicit claims but be less likely to notice more
implicit claims.
We argue that taking credit for a work activity is an
inherently ethical act that can have personal, organiza-
tional, and societal consequences. If the credit is justified
and defensible—the credit matches the contribution to the
work activity and is worthy of approbation by civil soci-
ety—then the credit taker is acting ethically. But when
unjustified credit is taken—the credit taken exceeds the
contribution to the work activity—then someone who is
entitled to that credit is diminished, devalued, and denied
that to which he or she is entitled. The individual who is
wrongfully denied credit may experience that denial as an
injustice, a theft, or at least as an undermining of their
workplace identity. We note that the ethical aspects of a
claim may not be salient for all: those who are bounded
ethically (i.e., who intend to be ethical but are psycho-
logically and cognitively limited in their ability to appre-
ciate the ethics of the act; see De Cremer et al. 2010)orfor
those for whom the ethical aspects of the decision have
faded (i.e., have receded in consciousness; see Tenbrunsel
and Messick 2004).
The ethics of credit taking in organizations can also
have a societal component: doing something that violates
widely accepted civil standards is indefensible, even if
it is seen as justified within the organization. The dis-
tinction between justified and defensible distinguishes
between what is deserved within an organization (the
credit matches the effort) and what is acceptable in
civil society (the effort warrants approbation). We use
‘defensible’ to refer to the extent to which actions meet
the standards of civil society. ‘Justified’ here means that
what is claimed (credit) matches what has been done
(contribution to a work effort). This use of justification is
fundamental to many theories, from equity theory (the
equality of inputs and rewards; Adams 1965) and Marx’s
(1847) theory of value to Kant’s (1785) categorical
imperative and virtue ethics (Taylor 2002). Each of these
would recognize that acts such as taking credit for work
done by a subordinate (Donaldson 1996; McDonald and
Zepp 1988; Metha and Kau 1984) is unjustified because
it violates principles of equity, ownership, the ethical
rule, and character habits that are to be encouraged.
Later, we draw on just such an example of a speechwriter
who took sole credit for work done by a team of
speechwriters. We contrast this with one of the other
team members who takes justified credit for writing some
of the speeches.
Thus, taking credit for work efforts can range from
justified and defensible (taking appropriate credit for deeds
done within the organization that are socially approved of
outside the organization), justified and indefensible (taking
appropriate credit for actions that are condemned by civil
society), unjustified and defensible (taking more credit than
is due for deeds that are socially approved of), and unjus-
tified and indefensible (taking more credit than is due for
deeds that are condemned by civil society). The last raises
ethical issues both inside and outside the organization.
Some Expected Consequences of Taking Credit
We expect that taking credit has positive and negative
emotional, behavioral, and organizational consequences
within organizations. The likely positive emotional con-
sequences of taking justified credit include feelings of
empowerment and agency, particularly for those who have
a history of passivity in work settings. The positive
behavioral consequences of justified credit taking may
include an employee’s increased willingness to collaborate
and volunteer for future projects. For organizations, the fair
distribution of credit can provide a foundation for a healthy
organizational culture, enhanced employee perceptions of
justice and a strengthened sense of teamwork. Among the
likely negative emotional consequences of unjustified
credit taking are the bitterness felt by those whose contri-
butions are devalued, victims’ sense of betrayal by col-
leagues and a debilitating sense of cynicism. The negative
behavioral effects of unjustified credit taking may include a
reduced willingness to collaborate in the future, retribution
to settle a score, increased turnover and the lowered
commitment that comes from being undermined by col-
leagues and supervisors (cf. Duffy et al. 2002; Pozner
2007). For organizations, the unfair distribution of credit
can weaken norms of reciprocity and equity, reduce
transparency and destroy trust (Brown and Robinson 2011;
Fortin and Fellenz 2008; McFarlin and Sweeney 1992).
We use two constructs—social undermining (Duffy
et al. 2002) and psychological safety (Edmondson 1999)—
to highlight some of these consequences. Duffy et al.
(2002, p. 332) define social undermining as ‘behavior
intended to hinder, over time, the ability to establish and
maintain positive interpersonal relationships, work related
success, and favorable reputation.’ The unjustified taking
of credit is one way in which social undermining can
happen in the workplace, particularly when it is successful
(i.e., when taking unjustified credit results in receiving
credit), as when corporate psychopaths bully by taking
credit for another’s work (Babiak and Hare 2006). The
unjustified taking of credit, when viewed as a type of social
undermining, may result in distributive, procedural, and
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
interactional injustice. The appropriate distribution of
credit may accomplish the opposite: taking justified credit
is likely to allow individuals to establish and maintain
positive interpersonal relationships, experience work-rela-
ted success, and develop a favorable reputation.
Edmondson (1999) introduced the construct of team
psychological safety and has shown that it facilitates team
learning. She defines team psychological safety as ‘a
shared belief that the team is safe for interpersonal risk
taking’ (p. 354). She characterizes the type of climate in
safe teams as one dominated by trust and mutual respect.
Taking unjustified credit can undermine team psychologi-
cal safety, reduce trust and poison an organization’s culture
by undermining norms of reciprocity and equity. Expected
consequences include decreased cooperation and organi-
zational citizenship behavior and increased turnover.
Although external stakeholders have not shown much
interest in how internal disputes about credit are resolved
(Jackson 2001), focusing instead on acts that breach trust
between organizations and those with whom organizations
are interdependent, insiders do care about unjustified credit
taking. Wronged parties complain to business advice col-
umnists (see, e.g., Pinker 2005) and cartoonists poke fun at
opportunistic credit takers (‘‘I made a few tweaks to your
idea. Now if it fails it was your idea and if it works I can
claim the credit’’; Adams 2011) and manager’s report that
they experience unjustified credit taking as stressful (van
Zyl and Lazenby 2002). Others have noted that claiming
unjustified credit is a source of eroded trust (Simon and
Eby 2003) and a form of bullying (Babiak and Hare 2006;
Clive 2011) that compromises business ethics and creates
threats to the integrity of organizational reward systems
(cf. Jackall 1988, p. 21).
While scholars have identified the taking of unjustified
credit as an unethical organizational behavior, and some
research has suggested ways to think about the process of
claiming credit (see, e.g., Bazerman 2006 on self-serving
biases; Bazerman’s work with colleagues on bounded
rationality (Banaji et al. 2003; Bazerman 2006) with col-
leagues on bounded ethicality; Jackall 1988 on the role of
power), we believe this is the first systematic attempt to
understand the conditions that lead to and enable credit
taking. Following De Cremer et al.’s (2010, p. 2) sugges-
tion that ‘we need to understand the psychological
underpinnings of behavior relevant to ethics in greater
detail,’ we examine the concept of credit and when and
why credit is taken. Our purpose is to call attention to a
construct of potential interest to the field and some of the
ways in which it can be researched. We take the standpoint
of the credit taker in the interest of providing a focused and
systematic way of thinking about when and why individ-
uals take credit. We acknowledge the role of the audience
but focus on the roles of contribution, psychology,
situations and personality in the decision being made by
potential credit takers. We begin by providing a prototype
that we use to anchor our analysis of credit taking, after
which we define ‘credit’ and ‘taking credit’ and propose
a model that may help explain the phenomenon.
A Prototype
Most of the phenomena discussed in this article appear in a
public dispute over claims for speechwriting credit in the
George W. Bush White House. Former speechwriter Scully
(2007) provides a rich account of the rewards and costs that
become apparent when a speechwriter over-reaches and
violates the self-effacing norms of the profession. From
1999 to 2004, Scully, Michael Gerson, and John McCon-
nell served as senior speechwriters for President Bush.
Scully says (and subsequently confirmed by Frum 2007)
that the major speeches, including those from shortly after
9/11, were jointly written by all three on McConnell’s
computer. But with time, Michael Gerson presented the
story as if he did all the writing. Gerson’s account became
particularly well known as he emerged as a media star.
Scully, commenting on a prepublication draft of a book
about those White House years written by Gerson (2007)—
made available to Scully by Gerson’s publisher—publicly
disputed Gerson’s claims to single authorship: ‘without
fear of contradiction—because it’s all in the presidential
records—I can report here that Michael Gerson never
wrote a single speech by himself for President Bush. From
beginning to end, every notable speech, and a huge pro-
portion of the rest, was written by a team of speechwriters,
working in the same office and on the same computer. Few
lines of note were written by Mike, and none at all that
come to mind from the post-9/11 addresses—not even ‘axis
of evil’’ (Scully 2007
, p. 79).
Given the public nature of the claims and the availability
of digital records, one might expect that this would be
enough to constrain claims, but ‘the only time Mike
appeared disturbed by the approach of public attention was
during the preparation of the New York Times Magazine
account of the making of the joint-session speech, when the
magazine’s fact-checkers started calling to confirm such
details as who wrote what. Fact-checkers of tomorrow will
find somewhere in the presidential archives a frantic e-mail
from Mike in which a colleague was ordered not to take
any further calls from Times fact-checks’ (Scully 2007,
p. 84).
Whatever the facts, this dispute offers a clear illustration
of the costs and rewards of taking unjustified credit.
‘Maybe you have brushed up against such people in your
own workplace. If so, you know that it is a peculiar vice,
this kind of credit hounding. One is left almost disoriented
Taking Credit
123
by the gall of it. It was amazing that a friend could carry on
like this in full view and still act as if nothing were out of
order. The sheer pettiness of such conduct served to repel
corrective action, because who wants to be drawn into little
games of guile and manipulation’ (Scully 2007, p. 85)?
Scully notes that there ‘are rewards for such behavior, and
in Mike’s case the Washington establishment has raised
him up as one of its own—a status complete with a col-
umnist’s perch at The Washington Post. There is a down-
side, too, measured in the lost esteem of friends and in the
tainting of real gifts and achievement’ (Scully 2007,
p. 79). Further, ‘when we are given credit for things we
didn’t do, or feel tempted to grab at underserved acclaim,
we show what we are made of’’ (Scully 2007, p. 87). Scully
concludes his account by saying that ‘a modest round of
merited applause is worth far more than a standing ovation
undeserved’ (Scully 2007, p. 88).
At the other end of the spectrum is the anomalous case
of who solved the Poincare Conjecture, a legendary prob-
lem in topology (Gessen 2009; Nasar and Gruber 2006). In
2002, Grigory Perelman, a Russian mathematician, posted
a compressed solution to the problem on the Internet. The
compressed posting allowed another mathematician, John
Yau, to elaborate the solution; Yau claimed that the gaps in
Perelman’s solution were important to fill before the con-
jecture could be considered solved. The record shows that
Yau did contribute to the solution and hence felt a sense of
psychological ownership that underpins his claim. The
anomaly is that Perelman has since declined to defend a
claim for credit and has refused two highly prestigious
international awards for his work—the Fields Medal in
2006 and the Clay Millennium Prize in 2010.
Credits, Audiences, and Ethics
‘Credit’ and ‘taking credit’ are terms used in ordinary
language. They can be ambiguous and create misunder-
standings because they are non-technical terms. To reduce
misunderstandings, we begin by defining our constructs.
Further, the dependence on audiences needs to be
acknowledged, as does the relationship between taking
credit and business ethics.
Credits
‘Credit’ has been part of the field’s lexicon at least since
its use by the social psychologist Hollander (1958). He
defined credit as ‘an accumulation of positively-disposed
impressions residing in the perceptions of relevant others’
(p. 120). According to Hollander, candidates for emergent
leadership positions are more likely to be recognized as
legitimate leaders if they have built credits by
demonstrating competence and conforming to group norms
(the latter now re-conceptualized as showing fidelity to the
group; see Stone and Cooper 2009). In the interests of
conceptual clarity and consistency, we follow Hollander by
defining ‘‘credit’’ as recognition for contributions to a work
effort that is acknowledged by others.
An individual who takes credit is making a conscious
bid for an audience’s recognition that he or she has made a
positive contribution to a work effort.
1
To receive credit
means that others have acknowledged that the credit is
deserved. We refer to these others as ‘the audience.’ No
credit exists until the audience recognizes the claim as
deserved. Burt (2004, p. 388) presents an equivalent view
about ideas: ‘An idea is as valuable as an audience is
willing to credit it with being.’ Thus, an individual whose
bid for credit is successful (i.e., has been acknowledged by
an audience) is said to have received credit for his or her
work effort.
Audiences
The process of taking credit is interactive with an audience.
Audiences vary in their awareness of efforts and in their
sensitivity to the ways in which bids are made, just as
claimants vary in their awareness of audiences. A claimant
who makes a bid has the onus of demonstrating to a target
audience that his or her effort is worthwhile.
2
Some
claimants may give little thought to the audience’s reaction
because he or she may have a strong sense of psychological
ownership of a work activity and feel firmly connected to
an effort (Pierce et al. 2001). In this case, the claimant may
not consider the audience’s reactions when making a bid,
perhaps taking his or her credit-worthiness for granted.
Conversely, someone who wishes to take credit when their
contribution is not well known (or when the contribution
has been nil-to-marginal) might be particularly concerned
1
While there may be cases where credit is awarded prior to a
conscious bid being made (e.g., not noticing that someone has
credited the individual with a contribution, perhaps during a meeting
the individual did not attend) these are not cases of taking credit until
the claimant becomes aware that credit has been awarded. If the
individual receiving the credit then acknowledges it, then we would
regard the individual as having taken credit. The claiming here is
passive (although letting the audience’s perceptions stand is a
conscious act). This means that no credit is taken when credit is
awarded and the individual remains unaware that credit has been
awarded. We expect these situations are uncommon; as a result, we
focus on the more common (and the more ethically interesting) cases
where an individual exaggerates their contribution or just makes it up.
In these cases we regard the credit taking as conscious (and, in some
instances, calculative).
2
While the individual’s contribution must be seen as favorable, the
outcome need not be: an unsuccessful effort might be recognized as
credit-worthy in a losing cause. For consistency we use ‘work effort’
and ‘contribution’ throughout, rather than ‘outcome.’
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
with the audience’s evaluation of the bid. In these latter
cases, the claimant may devote efforts to stage managing.
This dependence on an audience complicates the process
of getting credit. Much of the complexity arises from four
factors: the success of the bid is uncertain, the process may
be managed, audiences may award credit on grounds other
than contribution, and there may be multiple audiences.
First, making a bid for credit carries risk because a bid may
fail, perhaps because the audience has not noticed the
contribution. Even well-motivated audiences that intend to
be rational may have limited knowledge of the events,
constrained attention and truncated processing ability (i.e.,
audiences operate under conditions of bounded rationality;
Simon 1957). As a consequence, some efforts that deserve
credit are not noticed and the claimant does not get the
credit deserved. At a minimum this can leave an individual
feeling underappreciated. Other bids may fail because an
attentive audience feels the effort is insufficient to warrant
credit or does not think the effort is meritorious. In either
case the bid fails. Discrepancies between an individual’s
claim for credit and the audience’s assessment of that claim
can create disputes that are risky for a claimant to pursue.
As with Scully, much of the room for disputes is created by
differences between what is known by an audience and
what is felt by contributors.
A second consequence of the dependence on an audi-
ence is the possibility of managing the process. Because
audiences are boundedly rational, claimants may be able to
manage an audience’s understanding. Solo efforts that are
public pose few difficulties for audiences: audiences at golf
tournaments do not waver in deciding that a shot deserves
applause. But communal efforts in private settings can
make it hard for audiences to sort out who contributed
what. Unlike property that can be physically possessed or
publically represented to prove title (e.g., share certificates,
deeds), the communal efforts of many organizational par-
ticipants make it hard to adjudicate bids. Work efforts are
frequently joint and establishing sufficient connectedness
to claim sole or major credit may be both difficult and
risky; difficult because efforts are multiparty and risky
because cooperation from wronged others may be needed
in the future. This provides an opening for the skillful use
of impression management, selective disclosure of infor-
mation, misrepresentation, and opportunistic behavior.
Third, audiences socially construct the criteria for
awarding credit, some of which may not be merit based.
When credit is awarded on criteria such as place in the
hierarchy, the resulting distribution of credit is unlikely to
be seen by all as equitable, particularly by those with less
power. When this happens—e.g., when a favored individ-
ual receives a promotion for a work effort with which he or
she had little connection—issues of ethics arise, even if the
promotion is justified by a widely acknowledged power-
based logic of the organization. In such cases, actors—
including senior executives—can proudly lay claim to the
work efforts of others, including subordinates and col-
leagues. This is a reminder that substantial differences can
exist between moral codes inside and outside the organi-
zation, one highlighted in Jackall’s (1988, p. 6, emphasis in
the original) quote from a former executive in a large firm:
‘what is right in the corporation is not what is right in a
man’s home or his church. What is right in the corporation
is what the guy above you wants from you. That’s what
morality is in the corporation.’
Fourth, audiences can be multiple and heterogeneous,
allowing claims for credit to be evaluated using quite dif-
ferent criteria and weights. As a result, peer and subordi-
nate resentments can co-exist with superior-granted credit.
Peers and subordinates may know more than do superiors
about who did what. This provides ample room for feelings
of antipathy towards the recipient of credit and its grantors.
Peers may feel resentment because superiors have unfairly
favored the credit recipient and subordinates may come to
see the recipient as untrustworthy, someone to be avoided
and worked around.
Ethics
Taking credit for one’s work activity is ethically unprob-
lematic when the credit is justified (again, the credit taken
matches the contribution to the work activity) and defen-
sible (again, is acceptable to civil society). Much of our
analysis focuses on the ethically problematic situation of
credit being claimed when there is insufficient entitlement.
It is important that individuals be able to claim credit for
their contributions within the workplace so that they can
establish a sense of competence and maintain a positive
workplace identity. Even here the claiming process can be
problematic for those who are entitled to credit, since
normative or political factors within the organization may
affect a claim for credit. For example, two individuals in a
team of five may have done the work but be compelled to
share credit with three laggards because of the organiza-
tion’s normative environment.
Our starting point of trying to understand why and when
credit is claimed is equally relevant for justified and
unjustified claims. Lesser ethical issues arise when those
who are entitled to credit are unable to take credit, either
because they are not motivated to do so, are uneasy with
the risk, uncomfortable with the self-promotion involved or
are prevented from doing so by structures and processes
within the organization. Ethical issues regarding credit
most often arise inside organizations when the credit taken
is unjustified—the claim is larger than what is warranted by
one’s contributions, as with Scully’s account of Gerson’s
credit taking. These unjustified claims are possible for a
Taking Credit
123
variety of reasons. Causality can be ambiguous because
multiple contributions (and contributors) make for imper-
fect judgments of which ones matter most. Audiences can
be naı
¨
ve, only partially engaged, boundedly rational,
allowing a claimant to frame and stage manage. Egocentric
biases can be a thumb on the scale (Bazerman 2006;
Mezulis et al. 2004; Miller and Ross 1975), causing
potential claimant’s to overvalue their contribution. In
addition, the internal logic within organizations may value
and reward behaviors that are not ethical and lead to the
acceptance of claims that are based on power and position
(Jackall 1988).
In the following discussion, we draw on a number of
psychological processes that can play a role in the ethics of
claiming credit. The recognition of cognitive biases and
other similar psychological processes has led to the notion
that individuals are bounded ethically (De Cremer et al.
2010; Banaji et al. 2003; Chugh et al. 2005). Just as
boundedly rational individuals may intend to be rational
but operate under cognitive and attention constraints
(Simon 1957), so may individuals intend to be ethical but
be constrained—both psychologically and cognitively—in
their ability to make ethical decisions. As a result, the
decision to make a claim for credit may be evaluated by a
boundedly ethical individual predominantly on its proba-
bility of success, with less attention paid to the ethics of
making the claim. Ethically bounded individuals may then
see themselves as ethical but fail to recognize that they are
acting unethically. As a result, processes may allow those
who make unjustified claims to credit to reduce their eth-
ical awareness to the point that they see themselves as
behaving ethically (or at least ease any ethical discomfort
by facilitating rationalization through a process of self-
deception).
The latter possibility is consistent with Tenbrunsel and
Messick’s (2004, p. 204) notion that ‘psychological pro-
cesses fade the ‘ethics’’ from an ethical dilemma,’’ thereby
facilitating a reframing process that abets rationalization.
An individual for whom the ethical dimensions have faded
will have difficulty seeing the ethical aspects, while an
individual with a sense of moral license can acknowledge
the act as wrongful but (ironically) feel that he or she can
successfully withstand the negative consequences because
of his or her prior good behavior (cf. Shapiro et al. 2011).
This process is nicely captured by Bazerman et al. (1997,
p. 91): ‘When presented with identical information, indi-
vidual perceptions of a situation differ dramatically
depending on one’s role in the situation. People first
determine their preference for a certain outcome on the
basis of self-interest and then justify this preference on the
basis of fairness by changing the importance of attributes
affecting what is fair.’ Thus, a claimant for credit who is
boundedly ethical (or for whom the ethical dimension of
making a claim for credit has faded) understands that they
are making a claim for credit but the ethical dimensions of
making that claim have disappeared or diminished.
Research on moral licensing points to a more calculative
view of the process. The core idea is that actions in one’s
past allow one to do things that would normally be dis-
crediting, but because of past good behavior the trans-
gression is not discrediting (Miller and Effron 2010).
Miller and Effron suggest that one basis for avoiding dis-
credit is Hollander’s (1958) notion of idiosyncratic credits.
An individual holding these credits can subsequently
deviate from group norms without being discredited.
Merritt et al. (2010) have applied the notion to moral sit-
uations and Merritt et al. (2012) have shown that strate-
gically pursuing one’s moral credentials can allow an
individual to manage how their morally dubious behavior
is seen. Drawing on this view, an individual might make a
claim for credit—even though they are not entitled—when
they feel their past behavior will allow them to transgress
without harming their reputation. A claimant who is cal-
culating might reason that their unjustified claim will
succeed without challenge or, if challenged, the claimant’s
prior meritorious behavior will uphold their claim to credit.
The preceding discussion points to the ease with which
ethical issues can arise when claims for credit are made.
Unjustified claims for credit may be made by those who are
unethical and opportunistic, but other factors can contribute
to the process. Organizational cultures may allow powerful
individuals to appropriate credit, cognitive biases can tilt
cognitive processes towards the claimant, boundedly ethi-
cal thinking can constrain perspective, ethical aspects can
fade and moral licensing may allow actors to draw on
previous good deeds to permit present transgressions.
These are all troubling and can easily lead to over-claiming
credit.
Summary
We use ‘credit taking’ to refer to an act in which an
individual makes a bid for credit. We use ‘credit giving’
to refer to an audience’s acknowledgement that the credit
claimed is deserved. ‘Credit’ means that an audience has
recognized a claim as deserved. An individual can make a
bid (take credit) but no credit exists until an audience has
given credit to the credit taker. Thus, credit exists when an
audience agrees with a claim (or when an audience gives
credit without being asked); there is no credit if an audi-
ence disagrees with a claim for credit. Alternatively put,
credit exists when there is convergence between what the
credit seeker justifiably claims and what the audience
acknowledges; when there is divergence there is no credit.
Because audiences operate under conditions of bounded
rationality, some bids are unfairly rejected (recognition is
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
deserved but withheld) while others are unfairly accepted
(recognition is undeserved but awarded). Ethical issues
arise when the credit taken exceeds what is justified by the
contribution and when the work efforts are not acceptable
to civil society.
A Model of the Credit-Taking Process
Recent surveys of US and Canadian employees report that
many organization members have had credit stolen from
them in the previous year (or had witnessed the taking of
unjustified credit). Percentages ranged from 23 of
employees of US organizations to 58 of Canadian
employees who saw others taking credit for their work
(McGinn 2009) and the 61 of Canadian human resource
managers who felt leaders in their organizations took too
much credit (Immen 2010). Unjustified credit taking is
apparently common enough in our own field to have pro-
vided an adequate sample for a study of disputes about
credit among co-authors of articles published in our leading
journals (Floyd et al. 1994). The latter study points to the
competing roles of power, status, merit and collegiality in
determining the order of names.
The ethics of taking credit for work done by others has
received some attention from academic researchers, pri-
marily as an item in a list of unethical behaviors. For
example, Donaldson (1996, p. 53) noted that ‘stealing
credit from a subordinate is nearly an unpardonable sin,’’ a
statement supported in several cross-national studies (see,
e.g., McDonald and Zepp 1988; Metha and Kau 1984).
Taking credit for the work of peers has similarly been
viewed as unethical: in a study of Australian and South
African managers, Abratt et al. (1992) found that taking
credit for the work of peers was seen as highly unethical.
Taking credit for work done by others has also been
regarded as a tactic for self-promotion (Dyke 1990) and for
impression management (Higgins and Judge 2004;
Schlenker 1980).
While recognizing that taking credit has multiple uses,
we regard taking credit as an overlooked everyday phe-
nomenon that merits attention for its own sake. It has
antecedents—psychological, situational and personality—
and consequences—emotional, behavioral and organiza-
tional—that are of importance for understanding organi-
zational behavior. Recent work by Pierce et al. (2001)on
psychological ownership, Brown et al. (2005) on territori-
ality and Bazerman (2006) and others (e.g., Epley and
Caruso 2004; Tenbrunsel and Messick 2004) on decision
making provide constructs that may be useful for under-
standing credit taking, as does the application of the fraud
triangle in forensic accounting (Cressey 1953) and the
corrosive effects of narcissism in organizations (Chatterjee
and Hambrick 2007).
Our opening paragraphs point to the myriad ways in
which credit can be taken—from the active and explicit to
the passive and implicit. The routes travelled to take credit,
and the factors that affect the likelihood of credit taking,
are similarly varied. In the interest of coherence and trac-
tability, we focus on five constructs that we believe are
useful for understanding credit taking: psychological
ownership, motive, opportunity, the ability to rationalize
and narcissism. We expect the first four produce main
effects and the fifth acts as a moderator. Figure 1 represents
our understanding of the credit-taking process. It is a
heuristic device intended to organize the panoply of claims.
We draw on these constructs to explain four kinds of bids
that we believe are the routes most often travelled by those
Fig. 1 Four paths to claiming credit
Taking Credit
123
who take credit at work: the credit claimed matches the
contribution, the credit claimed exceeds the contribution,
the claim is justified and strategically made after some
delay and no contribution is made but credit is claimed. We
use the four paths (Justified, Unjustified, Strategic, and
Imagined) as exemplars of credit taking. They are not
exhaustive of the domain since many gradations exist
between them. They are presented as pure types meant to
help make sense of a rich domain.
The first path, Path J (for Justified) represents the sim-
plest case: a contribution is made, feelings of territoriality
and psychological ownership are experienced and a justi-
fied claim for credit is asserted (the claim equals the con-
tribution). Claims on this path are not calculative and are
driven by a sense of ownership of the work effort: we wrote
this manuscript, acknowledged the contributions of others
and submitted it with our names on it. Path J raises no
ethical issues (and is also the least interesting of the four
paths).
Claims that follow Path U (for Unjustified) are calcu-
lative and opportunistic: a contribution is made, psycho-
logical ownership of the work effort is experienced, and
then motive, opportunity, the ability to rationalize and
narcissism can each enable the making of an unjustified
claim (the claim exceeds the contribution). It is the one
taken by those who seek to exaggerate their contribution,
as in Michael Gerson’s claim to sole authorship. The eth-
ical issue is evident: the claimant is bidding for more than
is deserved, denying others their due.
Path S (for Strategic) is a variant on the justified path: a
contribution is made, feelings of territoriality and psycho-
logical ownership are experienced, a calculation is made
about opportunity—most often about whether something is
enough of a contribution and whether this is the right time
and setting to make a claim—and, after some delay, a
justified claim for credit is made (again, the claim equals
the contribution). What differentiates the Strategic from the
Justified path is that there is a calculative element to the
Strategic path: claimants are sensitive to situational factors
about thresholds, time, and place. A contributor to a work
effort may experience a strong sense of psychological
ownership of the effort yet not make a claim for credit;
similarly, the absence of a claim may be a response to the
claimant’s recognition that a normative threshold—what is
enough of a contribution to warrant making a claim, or
what is an appropriate time or place to do so—first needs to
be reached. Further, someone who has done all the work on
a project may not explicitly claim credit because to do so
violates accepted anti-self-promotion norms of the occu-
pation or organization (Dyke 1990). Mathew Scully is an
example of someone who follows this route. He did not
make a claim for credit until Michael Gerson had done so,
perhaps because Scully was sensitive to the self-effacing
norms of the speechwriting profession. While these kinds
of claims, when made, are not ethically problematic, an
ethical issue does arise if a potential claimant, one who is
sensitive to normative constraints, is unable to claim credit
because an appropriate opportunity does not arise: the
potential claimant foregoes the right to credit that is
deserved.
Path I (for Imagined) is the route taken by those who
take egregiously unjustified credit: the credit taker has
made no contribution to the work effort yet claims credit
for it. It is the most ethically troubling path: it is a con-
scious act made without a conscience. Individuals on this
path may understand that, on the basis of effort, they are
not entitled to claim credit but, responding to motive,
opportunity, the ability to rationalize and narcissism, feel
that, given factors such as moral license, the overweening
sense of deservingness, an organization’s normative envi-
ronment that favors the powerful, an audience’s ignorance
or the claimant’s false memory, they can advance a claim
for credit.
The four paths are most readily distinguishable on two
factors: first, the match between the contribution and the
claim; and two, the degree of attention to the environment.
With regard to the match, the four paths differ in the
relationship between claim and contribution: claim
= contribution (Paths J and S), claim [ contribution (Path
U) and claim but no contribution (Path I). Second, claim-
ants on the four paths differ in their attention to the envi-
ronment. Those who follow Path J are attentive to their
contribution but are insensitive to the environment.
Claimants on Path U take advantage of an environment that
may allow them to exaggerate their claim, perhaps because
the audience is inattentive or grants them moral license to
do so. Those on Path S are sensitive to environmental
norms about thresholds, time and place, while claimants on
Path I rely on an amoral environment or the audience’s
ignorance to make their claim.
Despite their conceptual distinctiveness, the four paths
may not be readily distinguishable by an audience,
particularly audiences that are inattentive. As a result,
audiences may accept or reject a claim without appre-
ciating the path the claimant has travelled in making a
claim. One result is that sometimes credit is granted
when it is not deserved. Asymmetric risks are apparent
on each of these paths. A claimant on Path J may
deserve credit but be thought of as grasping if the claim
was presented at the wrong time or in a heavy-handed
way. Claimants travelling Path U risk ridicule and denial
of credit. Those on Path S who miscalculate the
threshold, timing or place may be scorned, while those
on Path I risk being called on it by an incensed col-
league who knows that the claimant’s contribution was
non-existent.
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
Psychological Ownership
We begin our theoretical development by thinking of credit
taking as a deliberate act of territoriality that is rooted in
feelings of psychological ownership (although the two can
be difficult to distinguish: see Avey et al. 2009). Pierce
et al. (2001, p. 299) note that ‘although ownership is
generally experienced toward an object, it can also be felt
toward non-physical identities, such as ideas, artistic cre-
ations and other people.’ Some of the early work on the
concept of psychological ownership has focused on feel-
ings of ownership towards the organization and its impact
on members (Van Dyne and Pierce 2004; Avey et al.
2009). Our focus is on feelings of ownership of work
efforts that are based on an individual’s contribution. These
feelings of ownership are not arrived at in a vacuum;
rather, they are products of a sensemaking process (Weick
1995) in which an individual comes to understand that a
contribution is his or hers. In making a claim for credit, an
individual is implicitly asking an audience to recognize and
confirm the legitimacy of his or her feelings of ownership.
Psychological ownership plays a role on Paths J, U, and S
of our model. On Path J, it is the major explanatory vari-
able in deciding whether or not to make a claim, while on
Paths U and S it forms part of the process; claims made on
Path I are not rooted in psychological ownership.
Pierce et al. (2001), tracing the idea that we own our
work effort (and its products) back to Locke (1690), argue
that psychological ownership fulfills a need for efficacy
and self-identity. In economic systems that define indi-
vidual worth in terms of the ability to create and trade work
product (Marx 1847), the inability to be associated with
one’s work effort is likely to be alienating and damaging to
an individual’s sense of self-esteem and workplace credi-
bility. Separating someone from his or her labor, including
its attendant recognition and rewards (both reputational and
economic) is socially undermining (Duffy et al. 2002),
interferes with the individual’s right to ownership of their
work and can leave the individual feeling diminished,
powerless, unjustly treated (and sometimes speechless).
Feelings of territoriality—either as part of psychological
ownership or as a result of it—may explain credit taking
when the claim is justified by the contribution (completely,
as on Path J, and partially, as on Path S). In highlighting the
behavioral aspects of territoriality in organizations, Brown
et al. (2005, p. 580) propose that ‘the stronger an indi-
vidual’s psychological ownership of an object, the greater
the likelihood he or she will engage in territorial behavior
towards the object.’ More recently, Brown and Robinson
(2011) have suggested that territorial infringements reli-
ably lead to strong emotional and behavioral reactions,
such as anger and defensiveness. Further, Avey et al.
(2009) see territoriality as a central part of the feeling of
psychological ownership and include it in their definition
of psychological ownership. We see the claiming of credit
as one form of territorial behavior.
The sense of psychological ownership and feelings of
territoriality drive the claiming on Path J. It may not be a
conscious process in which all relevant factors are con-
sidered. Rather, a sense of ownership is experienced and a
claim is made. This is most likely to occur in situations
where the claimant is the sole or the most substantial
contributor to a work effort. Strong feelings of territoriality
are less likely when the claimant understands that the effort
is joint and only seeks to have their individual contribution
acknowledged.
Claims for credit that arise from feelings of psycho-
logical ownership can also travel along Paths U and S. Path
S is calculative in the sense that the claimant pays attention
to the threshold, location and timing aspects of the
opportunity. The claims made on Path S are more innocent
than those made on Path U since there is a match between
contribution and claim on Path S. Path U is the most cal-
culative path, with a wide range of factors being considered
before a claim is made. Feelings of psychological owner-
ship are warranted, since a contribution was made, but the
claimant exaggerates the contribution and overstates the
claim. The Gerson/Scully example can be seen as just such
a case of an exaggerated claim: Gerson said that he wrote
the President’s speeches because he did write some of
them. Psychological ownership (as well as motive, oppor-
tunity, the ability to rationalize and narcissism) may have
led Gerson to take more credit than was warranted by his
contribution. Adding to this may be psychological and
cognitive biases that invite the claimant to overweight the
value of their contribution. Bounded ethicality (Banaji
et al. 2003) or moral fading (Tenbrunsel and Messick 2004)
can aid the rationalization (to oneself) of the unjustified
claims.
The starting point for claimants on Paths U and S is an
assessment of their contribution to a work effort. As with
claims made on Path J, Strategic claims are unbiased, while
the assessments made on Path U may be biased. One’s own
contributions may be more readily available in memory
than are those of others, providing an easy entry for the
self-serving biases of unjustified claims (cf. Banaji et al.
2003; Bazerman 2006; Mezulis et al. 2004). A palpable
sense of one’s own effort, coupled with an incomplete
awareness of the contributions of others, may enhance
feelings of psychological ownership that then can be
elaborated upon to produce claims for credit beyond what
is warranted. A claimant may feel their claim is justified
but, given the presence of bias, their claim for credit
overreaches that which is justified by their actual contri-
bution. Caruso et al. (2006) offer a straightforward cogni-
tive availability explanation for how these biased claims
Taking Credit
123
may start: self-serving biases begin with cognitive errors
that lead to the over-taking of credit, even when the
assessor is trying to fairly distribute credit between self and
others. This suggests that the initial stage can be an inno-
cent (cognitive) foot in the door, with the credit taker
unaware that he or she has claimed an exaggerated role in
the process. Caruso et al. (2006) attribute such behavior to
individuals paying greater attention to their own contribu-
tions (as well as being motivated to see themselves in a
favorable light). Caruso et al. (2006) cite the historical case
of Nobel Prize winners Frederick Banting and John Ma-
cLeod, each of whom downplayed the other’s role in the
discovery of insulin to magnify his own role. Viewing
speechwriting through this cognitive lens, Gerson simply
may have been more aware of his own work than those of
Scully and McConnell.
Thus, when we remember our own contributions—fre-
quently with the pride that accompanies recollection of
hard work in the face of adversity—it can be easy to see the
input of others as lesser, worthy of only a cursory nod. As a
consequence, the sense of psychological ownership may be
visceral for the claimant. This sense of psychological
ownership can then grow through self-serving biases in
which contributors make internal attributions (e.g., hard
work) while making external attributions for the contribu-
tions of others (e.g., luck), particularly in situations in
which an actor feels a threat to his or her identity
(Campbell and Sedikides 1999). In examining when indi-
viduals avoid some of the pitfalls associated with self-
serving bias, Campbell and Sedikides (1999) note that
participants did not deny all responsibility for failure but
did seek to take a little more credit than was justified when
they were successful. The Campbell and Sedikides (1999)
finding also suggests that while the bias may fade, it does
not eliminate the moral dimension of credit taking.
Friend (2003) provides evidence from the movie
industry that supports the Bazerman (2006) and Campbell
and Sedikides (1999) accounts of self-serving biases. He
notes that screenwriters are prone to embellishing their
claims to credit for screenplays (our Path U) and view
themselves as the wronged major contributors—perhaps
one reason that a third of the films produced annually in the
US go to the Screenwriter’s Guild for adjudication of
screenwriting credit. Those who lose in these credit con-
tests can feel an acute loss of what is due them when
arbitrators’ decisions about who wrote what separates them
from what they feel is their work.
Feelings of psychological ownership play no role on
Path I. It can be difficult to understand the audacious
claims for credit made by individuals who contributed
nothing. A likely explanation on this path is that feelings
of ownership—based on effort and contribution—are
replaced by a sense of entitlement—based on a normative
environment—that redistributes credit. Jackall (1988)
provides an example of organizations distributing credit on
the basis of rank and power, rather than effort. Some
understanding of how a sense of ownership can arise in the
face of no contribution may be provided by research on
elaborated imagination and source monitoring (see, e.g.,
Garry et al. 1996; Thomas et al. 2003). Originally devel-
oped to explain false memory effects regarding sexual
abuse, recent work by Sharman and Calacouris (2010) has
shown that when individuals think about an achievement-
related activity they can come to believe that they actually
performed the activity. In this way, individuals may come
to feel that they have contributed to a work activity when
all they have done is thought about what they could do. An
equivalent idea has been attributed to author Farley Mowat:
‘I have no difficulty remembering what should have hap-
pened.’ Such memories of past thoughts can endure and
lead individuals to think that they should be credited for
doing things they have only thought about doing.
Building on this work, we expect that the process of
psychological ownership will lead individuals to both
claim credit for their work, as in a claim by someone who
is responsible for a work effort (Path J), Gerson’s exag-
gerated claim (Path U), and defend against rival claims
asserted by others, as in Scully’s response to Gerson (Path
S), as well as those who have only imagined their contri-
bution (Path I). Perelman’s lack of motivation to assert a
claim (and to contest Yau’s claim) is an exception in search
of an explanation. One possibility is that individuals with a
stronger sense of identity are less interested in asserting
claims: being certain about whom you are and what you
have done may lessen the motivation to make a territorial
claim.
Proposition 1 The stronger an individual’s psychologi-
cal ownership of a work effort, the more likely the indi-
vidual will make and defend a claim for credit.
Some features of the work effort may increase the sense
of psychological ownership on all four paths. Here, we
briefly identify three: the distinctiveness and size of the
contributions and the normative contexts in which such
feelings develop. Distinctive contributions may increase
psychological ownership because they represent strong
expressions of the self, the uniqueness of the individual.
Those behaviors that are unique to us are what differentiate
us from others, thus helping to create our distinctive
identity (Brewer
1991). Distinctive contributions need not
be large: a low level of effort can produce a contribution
that is a strong expression of self. A speech writer may
effortlessly coin a phrase that later takes on great signifi-
cance (e.g., ‘Axis of evil’’). The speech writer may feel a
strong sense of psychological attachment to the words,
even though the size of the investment may have been
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
slight. Thus, Yau points out the unique ways in which he
contributed to solving the Poincaire Conjecture and
screenwriters point to the particularly clever dialogue they
inserted into the final screenplay (Friend 2003).
Proposition 1a The more distinct an individual’s con-
tribution to a work effort, the stronger an individual’s
psychological ownership of a work effort.
A second factor that is likely to affect psychological
ownership is the size of the contribution. Larger contri-
butions are likely to increase an individual’s identification
with a work effort, seeing the work activity as one’s own,
thereby increasing the sense of entitlement to recognition
from others. This is consistent with Pierce et al.’s (2001)
proposition that the greater the individual employee’s
investment in a target, the greater the ownership felt toward
the target. Size can have an effect that is independent of
distinctiveness simply because it is difficult to abandon
something in which one is heavily invested. This is con-
sistent with the general finding that the more one invests (in
an effort, project, idea, cause) the more an individual
(team, organization, state) comes to identify with it (Staw
and Ross 1987). Concomitantly, small contributions may
temper an actor’s willingness to seek credit from an audi-
ence, since seeking credit for small efforts can bring scorn
or ridicule if the individual is seen as petty (McGinn 2009),
grasping and insufficiently team-oriented, as in Scully’s
view of Gerson.
Thus, efforts may need to reach a quantitative threshold
before credit is sought without sullying one’s reputation,
whether the claimant is following Path J, U, or S. Such
contributions can be large in either an absolute or relative
sense. Completing 90 % of a project makes that contribu-
tion large in an absolute sense whereas doing more than
others on a team makes the contribution large relative to
the contributions of others. The size of the contribution will
not always be determined by the time invested. Obtaining
the funding necessary for a project may not have taken the
most time but may have been the key to proceeding on the
project.
Proposition 1b The larger an individual’s contribution
to a work effort, the stronger an individual’s psychological
ownership of a work effort.
Feelings of psychological ownership may be strength-
ened when the normative context supports such feelings.
The normative environment will be supportive of feelings
of psychological ownership when it encourages individuals
to be associated with their work effort, accepts justified
claims to ownership, and rewards claimants for their
accomplishment. When the context is not supportive, cri-
teria other than effort and accomplishment may determine
who is associated with a contribution and the subsequent
rewards. In these circumstances, wronged parties have the
choice of voicing their displeasure (or waiting their turn
using whatever set of criteria the organization is using to
determine creditable contributions). The latter is nicely
captured by Jackall (1988, p. 21): ‘A subordinate whose
ideas are appropriated is expected to be a good sport about
the matter; not to balk at so being used is one attribute of
the good team player.’
In considering entitlement to credit, feelings of psy-
chological ownership can be important but because credit
is socially constructed, feelings of psychological ownership
are likely to be strengthened when the normative context in
which they are nurtured supports these feelings (and con-
strained when the context is unsupportive). An individual
who feels a strong sense of psychological ownership and is
supported by a normative environment that provides psy-
chological safety (Edmondson 1999) may be more likely to
advance a claim for credit than would be true for an indi-
vidual who works in a normative environment where
power—rather than contribution—provides entitlement to
credit.
Proposition 1c The more supportive the normative con-
text, the stronger an individual’s psychological ownership
of a work effort.
The Fraud Triangle
While psychological ownership is the primary explanatory
variable for credit claims that follow Path J and plays an
important role on Path S, psychological ownership pro-
vides only a partial explanation for the claims that follow
Path U (and it provides no help in understanding
claims that follow Path I). We draw on the fraud triangle
(Cressey 1953; Murphy and Dacin 2011; Public Company
Accounting Oversight Board 2005) to help explain the
credit-taking behavior of those who make claims for credit
that follow Path U and the wholly fabricated claims made
on Path I. The fraud triangle was developed within forensic
accounting as a tool to help narrow the field of suspects
who may have taken tangible assets in the workplace.
Tangible assets are clearly owned and can be identified
since there are paper trails, serial numbers and the like.
Investigators begin by looking for those who had the
motive and opportunity to commit fraud and a way of
explaining the act to themselves. In comparison with tan-
gible assets, the intangible and socially constructed nature
of credit can provide even more tempting possibilities for
those who want to claim responsibility for a work effort.
Former Enron executive Sherron Watkins has drawn on
the framework of the fraud triangle to help explain the
unethical behavior at Enron before the fall. Pressures to
enhance financial results provided the motive to report that
Taking Credit
123
earning’s goals had been achieved, the plasticity of
accounting rules provided ample opportunity for burying
financial details, and the recourse to technically correct
accounting practices provided the room to rationalize the
misrepresentation (Beenen and Pinto 2009). Watkins
asserts that together these encouraged corrupt behaviors
(and helped produce the demise of Enron).
Building on this perspective, we argue that motive,
opportunity, and the ability to rationalize may provide a
useful way of thinking about credit taking on Paths U and I.
The fraud triangle argues that all the three components
must be present for fraud to occur: the presence of one
factor alone would not be sufficient to identify a suspect.
Translating literally, this argues for a three-way interaction
between motive, opportunity, and the ability to rationalize.
But unlike fraud, which does not rely on an audience for
possession, we regard each of the three sides of the triangle
as a potential foundation for claiming credit, with their
conjunction making claims even more likely.
Motive
One base of the fraud triangle is motive, where motive
refers to the incentives that exist for making a claim. For
forensic accountants, motive serves as a situational clue in
fraud investigations that may help identify who would
benefit from misrepresentation or theft. For credit-seeking
behavior, the motives include the standard list of organi-
zational incentives: enhanced reputations, better perfor-
mance evaluations, larger bonus pay, faster promotions,
and future opportunities. Those who have more credits may
have a better chance to make a positive impression and are
given greater rewards (Crant and Bateman 1993). Accu-
mulating credits may also provide an individual with the
right to deviate from group norms (Hollander 1958)by
giving those with moral credits a sense of license or enti-
tlement that permits a transgression to be forgiven because
of past good deeds (Miller and Effron 2010). Further,
credits may allow greater risk taking, protection from
failure, and, as recently reported by Shapiro et al. (2011),
make it possible for leaders to violate organizational
norms, including taking credit for the accomplishments of
others.
Perelman offers an interesting example of someone who
was not motivated to take credit for his solution to the
Poincaire Conjecture. He may be thought of as a proto-
typical example of someone who could follow Path J, given
the longstanding challenge presented by the Poincaire
Conjecture to mathematicians, the originality of his solu-
tion and the concomitant sense of psychological ownership.
Despite this he did not follow Path J and make a claim, nor
did he press a claim along Path S even when there was
substantial opportunity to do so.
In contrast, those who make exaggerated claims along
Path U may do so because of the rewards that can flow
from accumulating credits. On Path I, the possibility of
being rewarded may increase the desire to make a claim
and encourages the claimant to accept the risks that a claim
based on opportunism presents. Thus, our base proposition
is that those who have a stronger incentive to make a claim
may be more likely to make claims.
Proposition 2 The greater the motivation to make a
claim, the more likely the individual will make and defend
a claim for credit.
Four factors may increase the motivation to make a
claim: the valence of the outcome, the presence of indi-
vidual-based reward systems, deadlines for evaluation, and
spoiled reputations. Each represents temptations that some
organization members may find difficult to resist (cf. Dunn
and Schweitzer 2005). First, the motivation to make and
defend a claim for credit may be stronger when the claim is
expected to be successful and to lead to formal rewards that
are highly valued. Put differently, the motivation to take
credit may be lower when the rewards are less attractive.
This is consistent with the classic motivational effects of
more positively valenced rewards: the more attractive the
reward the more likely the behavior (Vroom 1964). Thus,
Gerson and Yau saw public recognition as something of
value for their reputations and asserted their claims.
Proposition 2a The more favorable the expected reward,
the greater the motive to take credit.
An organization’s formal reward system is likely to
influence an individual’s decision to take credit. Organi-
zations that operate career tournaments—such as Enron’s
‘rank and yank’ evaluation system described by Watkins,
Beenen and Pinto (2009)—can put strong performance
pressures on individuals, thereby increasing the likelihood
that individuals will claim credit to advance (or survive).
Reputational enhancement, getting the attention of gate-
keepers, and the attraction of scarce rewards all create
pressures to be associated with valued organizational
efforts. Thus, screenwriters who compete in reputational
tournaments—in which accumulating (literal) screenwrit-
ing credits for successful movies increases the chances that
they will be asked to work on future projects (Bielby and
Bielby 1999)—are motivated to make claims or to chal-
lenge claims made by others.
Reward systems that are based on individual results may
be particularly likely to encourage aggressive credit
claiming. This is especially problematic when there is a
mismatch between the unit of the work activity and the
unit of rewards (e.g., when the work is team based and
the rewards are individual based; cf. Colquitt et al. 2001).
Toffler (2003) provides an example of one such
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
dysfunctional reward system that was in place during the
waning days of Arthur Anderson. When she was working
there in ethical consulting, the reward system was based on
four components—people management, quality, thought
leadership and financial performance—which she charac-
terized as ‘three pebbles and a bolder’ (p. 105). She
quickly learned to ignore the first three after she saw that
generating fees was the only one that was rewarded.
Proposition 2b The more the reward system emphasizes
individual results, the greater the motive to take credit.
There may be critical times in individual-based reward
systems when individuals choose to make claims, such as
just before important milestones. Borrowing from Bolino’s
(1999) analysis of citizenship behaviors that are timed for
impression management purposes, we expect that motiva-
tion to claim credit will be greater when critical evaluation
moments approach (e.g., performance reviews, promotion
decisions). Employees are likely to appreciate the potential
benefits of emphasizing accomplishments that have hap-
pened recently and strategically time their efforts to create
favorable impressions. Performance reviews become part
of the individual’s career narrative and having one’s efforts
acknowledged in a formal review or a promotion
announcement can help crystallize a previously underde-
fined reputation.
Proposition 2c The nearer the deadline for evaluation,
the greater the motive to take credit.
Finally, individuals whose reputations have suffered
may be especially likely to make claims for credit in an
attempt to rebuild their images. When past deeds have
eroded the way in which an individual is seen, the indi-
vidual (or allies) may be particularly motivated to repair
their reputation by associating the individual with merito-
rious efforts. Those who have been scapegoated or whose
self-esteem has been threatened by a recent failure may
be highly motivated to do things that will burnish their
reputations (cf. Bolino 1999; Boeker 1992; Cialdini et al.
1976).
Proposition 2d The higher the perceived need to restore
one’s reputation, the greater the motive to take credit.
Opportunity
Opportunity represents a second situational factor that
affects the likelihood that credit will be claimed and
defended. In ordinary language ‘opportunity’ refers to
chance, occasion, circumstance, or opening to do some-
thing, a usage that is consistent with its use in the orga-
nizational literature (see, e.g., Barsness et al. 2005; Kanter
1977, Chap. 6; Stevenson and Greenberg 2000). This is the
sense of opportunity to which those following Path S are
sensitive: is this enough of a contribution, is the timing
right and should I make a claim now? But in the language
of the fraud triangle, particularly for financial forensic
investigators, ‘opportunity’ means access to assets in the
absence of control mechanisms such as regular audits,
proper oversight, dual signing authority or tight inventory
control. It is in this sense that opportunity forms a second
side of the fraud triangle, one that applies to Paths U and I.
Opportunity also plays a role on Path S, but on this path,
opportunity refers to the opening to make a claim that is
normatively appropriate.
A letter submitted to a business advice columnist (Pin-
ker 2005) provides an example of how opportunity can
arise in a work setting (and the adroit ways in which effort
can be framed). Janet, an elementary school teacher, sug-
gested to her principal that a Science Day be organized for
senior students. The principal was initially against the idea
but agreed to the proposal after being pressed by Janet.
Janet organized and supported student projects and arran-
ged for help from local industries and colleges. She kept
parents updated and actively promoted the event to them in
(unsigned) notes home. On the day of the Science Fair, the
principal welcomed the parents and spoke of how hard the
school had worked to put on the fair, her hopes of making
it an annual event, and her gratitude for the community
support. The principal neither mentioned Janet in her
speech nor did she give Janet the opportunity to address the
parents.
The day was highly successful. Several parents wrote
the school expressing their thanks for the day, noting how
much their children had gotten out of being involved in the
Science Day. The principal then put together a package of
these letters and forwarded them to her direct supervisor at
the board of education. The supervisor’s performance
review of the principal praised the principal for her inno-
vative approach to education and her willingness to do
more than what was required for the children in her school.
Later, the principal gave Janet a favorable performance
review, noting that Janet was supportive of the Science
Day. The principal saw the Science Day as an opportunity
to frame the day’s success as something for which she
could take credit.
The Cohen et al. (1972) garbage can model of organi-
zational decision-making provides an organizing frame-
work for thinking about how claimants can use
opportunities to attach themselves to efforts, particularly
when the arena for credit is unoccupied. Where Cohen
et al. (1972) see problems, solutions, and decision-makers
swirling about, connecting when decision-makers attach
favorite solutions to current problems, we see claimants
attaching themselves to efforts when the opportunity arises.
If we accept Scully’s portrayal of the situation in the White
Taking Credit
123
House, Gerson could be seen as exploiting just such a void
(on Path U). The norms of the profession—expecting
speech writers to remain in the background and to avoid the
public eye—allowed Gerson to fill the void and claim sole
credit. While Scully had the opportunity to make a claim
for credit, the norms of the profession may have made it
unlikely that it would occur to Scully to do so, and he
would not be able to rationalize this type of claim to
himself for this and other reasons; that left Scully with the
options of making a claim on Path S or remaining silent.
Proposition 3 The greater the opportunity to take credit,
the more likely the individual will make and defend a claim
for credit.
Several aspects of situations contribute to the opportu-
nity to take credit. Below we identify five, each of which
can provide openings for unjustified claims to credit, and
all of which are present in the White House and the school
settings: access, complexity, information asymmetry,
power differences, and the absence of existing claims.
First, because organizational efforts are frequently joint,
several individuals can plausibly make claims. For exam-
ple, the teacher and the principal are both likely to feel a
sense of psychological ownership of the Science Day: the
teacher proposed the idea and did most of the work, while
the principal provided the resources and framed the results.
The principal, however, had a better opportunity to take
credit for the day because her position gave her easier
access to relevant audiences (parents and the district
supervisor), the situation was complex (there were many
contributors), information asymmetry abounded (the audi-
ence—parents and the school board supervisor—did not
know who did what), power differences were large (the
principal had more formal and informal power than the
teacher), and no one else had made a claim.
Privileged access to relevant audiences may increase
opportunity, whether on Path U or I, because entre
´
eto
those in a position to grant or withhold credit can provide a
greater chance to sustain claims. Access allows for the
construction of narratives, frequently in circumstances
where it is difficult to challenge the claim. As noted long
ago by Mechanic (1962), access to persons, information,
and instrumentalities provide ways of getting what one
wants in organizations. Gerson had easier access to net-
works, both figuratively and literally, and the principal had
easier access to the audience of parents on Science Day and
to her supervisor at the Board office.
Proposition 3a The greater the access to relevant audi-
ences, the greater the opportunity to take credit.
Complexity—most often created by multiple contribu-
tors, multiple locations, and lengthy processes with multi-
ple iterations—may increase opportunities for claims.
Complexity can create uncertainty and confusion for actors
and audiences alike, enabling self-serving behavior (Dun-
ning et al. 1989; Sedikides and Strube 1997). This uncer-
tainty makes it more difficult for audiences to disentangle
who did (and deserves) what. Indeed, the very complexity
of many situations has been identified as an important
origin of self-serving biases in ethical decision-making
(Rogerson et al. 2011). Complexity provides opportunities
for actors to construct credible narratives, as with Gerson
on Path U, and the complexity of coordinating large
numbers of individuals over months of work provided the
principal with the opportunity to take credit.
Proposition 3b The greater the complexity of the work
effort, the greater the opportunity to take credit.
Agency theory (Jensen and Meckling 1976) and trans-
action cost economics (Williamson 1975) both recognize
that information asymmetry provides an opportunity for
individuals to exploit their privileged knowledge for their
own benefit. The degree of information asymmetry
between actors and audiences may be a third contributor
to opportunity. Audiences may not have the time, ability,
or inclination to assess the relative contribution of each
individual. When audiences know little about who did
what, astute actors can seize the opportunity to make
claims about their contributions. Boundedly rational audi-
ences may be willing to accept the story as recounted by
the claimant, thus providing an opportunity for individuals
to fashion the narrative in their own interest. Gerson and
the principal made contributions (to the speeches and the
Science Day, respectively) but may have overstated the
importance of their contributions (Path U), something that
members of the relevant audiences may be unable or
unwilling to sort out. In other cases, opportunists may
maintain their distance from a project to provide deniability
(in case the project fails), but lay claim to and embellish
their contribution once the project is a success (Path U, as
in the Dilbert cartoon about tweaking an idea quoted ear-
lier, Adams 2011).
Proposition 3c The greater the information asymmetry
between actor and audience, the greater the opportunity to
take credit.
Power differences may increase opportunity because it
improves the chances of sustaining a claim by those with
more power. Power’s contribution to opportunity is nicely
articulated in the opening quote from Jackall (1988), taken
from his ethnographic work in corporate settings. There he
showed that superiors felt entitled to take credit from their
subordinates (but not their superiors) because the organi-
zation’s norms and reward system gave them the license to
do so. In the three corporations that Jackall studied—and in
Eichenwald’s (
2005) account of Enron before the fall—it is
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
clear that the norms in these organizations justified the
taking of credit by those with more power; indeed, the
acceptance of this logic seemed necessary for individual
survival. Jackall (1988, p. 21) asserts that ‘credit flows up
in this structure and is usually appropriated by the highest
ranking officer involved in a successful decision or reso-
lution of a problem; authority provides a license to steal
ideas, even in front of those who originated them.’ Simi-
larly, the principal–teacher example illustrates the potential
that the power embedded in hierarchy has for taking
unjustified credit. Partnership tournaments (such as law and
consulting) allow seniors to take the credit and its con-
comitant rewards, while the juniors who do the backstage
work are left to struggle with the vicissitudes of the tour-
nament, perhaps hoping that their turn will come some day
(Galanter and Palay 1991).
Proposition 3d The greater the power difference between
potential claimants, the greater the opportunity for the more
powerful to take credit.
Finally, existing claims can be a barrier to potential
claimants; conversely, the absence of existing claims may
contribute to the opportunity to make a claim unencum-
bered by the claims of others. The first claimant for a
successful effort might be more likely to receive the
credit, a kind of first mover advantage: once asserted it can
be hard to dislodge an established narrative. Claims for
recognition may not be made immediately, sometimes
because of risk aversion—the outcome is not yet known—
and sometimes because of modesty—the potential claimant
may be (or want to be seen as) humble and modest. Delays
between efforts and outcomes can create an ownership
vacuum into which opportunists can slip. The Perelman–
Yau example illustrates a first mover advantage, with Yau
stepping up with an assertion of credit. Perelman may have
felt that his work spoke for itself and his silence provided
the opportunity for Yau.
Proposition 3e The fewer the existing claims, the greater
the opportunity to take credit.
Ability to Rationalize
The ability to rationalize—the ease with which one can
explain an act to oneself—is a third base of the fraud tri-
angle. The ability to rationalize is not an issue for justified
claims to credit since they do not need to be explained
to oneself (Paths J and S). Rationalization can abet the
unjustified claims of Path U that are based on exaggerated
(or, on Path I, non-existent or imagined) contributions, as
well as a wide range of unethical activities, such as bribery,
corruption and kickbacks (Collins et al. 2009). Of course,
the ability to explain a claim to oneself does not necessarily
mean that the claim can be explained easily to others. This
is particularly likely to be true for the imagined contribu-
tions of Path I.
The ability to rationalize and the other two legs of the
fraud triangle can be related. This can be seen in the larger
literature on motivated reasoning (see, e.g., Cohen 2003;
Haidt 2012). In contrast to conventional accounts about
thinking and reasoning—information gathering, assessing
the merits of arguments, and then reaching a position on an
issue—the motivated reasoning account suggests that we
decide what we want and then marshal reasons for sup-
porting what we want. In the realm of credit taking, this
would mean that once we decide to take credit for some-
thing we then look for grounds that support the taking.
While the concept of the ability to rationalize is
underdeveloped in the forensic accounting literature, recent
work by Anand et al. (2004) and Murphy and Dacin (2011)
has helped illuminate the many ways in which individuals
can use their view of the situation to explain their actions
to themselves. These rationalizations range from appealing
to higher loyalties, necessity, and selective social com-
parisons, to euphemistic labeling, minimizing the conse-
quences of the act and denial of injury. It is also possible
that rationalization will be enabled when credit is incor-
rectly awarded by another or a claim for justified credit is
unreasonably enlarged by a naı
¨
ve audience. In both
instances, the passive nature of the claim may facilitate
rationalization. Rationalizing the taking of unjustified
credit may be easier than rationalizing theft of goods
because the former is not illegal and what is being claimed
(credit) only exists when an audience recognizes it.
Rationalization also may operate at a more holistic
level, as in the case of moral licensing—where past good
behavior may be used as a basis for rationalizing the
commitment of a wrongful act (Miller and Effron 2010)or
in the case of accumulated idiosyncratic credits that are
used to rationalize deviations from acceptable organiza-
tional norms (Shapiro et al. 2011). Thus, our base propo-
sition is that individuals may be more likely to make a
claim for credit when a rationalization strategy is readily
available.
Proposition 4 The easier it is to rationalize a claim, the
more likely the individual will make and defend a claim to
credit.
Here, we briefly identify three conditions that may affect
the ability to rationalize a claim for credit: norms that
promote rationalization, gaps between rewards and previ-
ous contributions and the salience of contributions. Ariely
(2008) points out that many workplaces mix economic and
social norms. It may be more difficult to rationalize taking
unjustified credit (as on Paths U and I) when social norms
are strong: when the workplace is seen as collegial and
Taking Credit
123
psychologically safe, norms of reciprocity may limit a
claimant’s ability to take unjustified credit because social
norms reduce the ability to rationalize the taking. Con-
versely, an emphasis on economic norms (with their sur-
vival of the fittest rationales) may facilitate rationalization.
The workplaces described by Jackall (1988), Toffler
(2003), and Watkins (in Beenen and Pinto 2009) all
exemplify the predominance of economic norms over
social norms, a situation that can invite unjustified credit
taking.
It may be much easier to rationalize one’s claims to
credit when rationales of opportunistic claims are embed-
ded in organizational norms. These rationales may vary
from ‘‘everyone does it’’ to ‘‘you have to in order to survive
around here.’’ As Jackall notes, many of these logics tacitly
flow down the hierarchy. Murphy and Dacin (2011) argue
that such logics allow an action to be viewed as acceptable.
Some of this may be benign, as in organizations that have
informal heuristics about how credit is assigned; these can
facilitate the automatic assignment of credit and its ratio-
nalization. For example, the chair of a committee might be
viewed as the customarily appropriate person to receive
credit for the committee’s accomplishments—and have the
report named for the chair—even though other members
may have made more substantial contributions. Other
fields, such as politics, exist on the (usually) unacknowl-
edged work of backstage players. Such heuristics can
provide ready ways to rationalize the taking of credit.
The basis for rationalization may be provided by norms
within the organization. In the organizations studied by
Jackall (1988), credit is claimed by those who are senior
and these claims can be seen as appropriate within the
norms of the organizations—at least to those in positions to
receive some credit for the work of others. Rationalization
implies an understanding that some larger norm or ethical
standard has been deviated from and that some grounds are
required to explain the bid to oneself. When the normative
environment accepts an action there is, in effect, no devi-
ance to rationalize. As the ethical dimension of taking
credit fades, the claimant’s need to rationalize is reduced.
This is the kind of ethical fading that can lead to a numbing
(Tenbrunsel and Messick 2004) that, over time, mitigates
and finally removes the need for rationalization: the
behavior becomes routine, taken for granted, acceptable
(Kelman and Hamilton 1989).
While our focus has been at the individual level,
unjustified credit can also be taken by collectivities, such as
organizations as a whole. Annual reports, press releases,
and other communications with external audiences can
portray organizations as agents of change, despite the
exogenous factors that can overwhelm agency (Bettman
and Weitz 1983; Staw et al. 1983). Although insiders may
understand that these claims for credit are overstated, they
can provide the imitative grounds for the organization’s
members to rationalize his or her own exaggerated claims,
as on Paths U and I (Anand et al. 2004): when institutions
enact norms of opportunistic credit taking, individual
members may be likely to follow suit.
Proposition 4a The stronger the organizational norm to
take unjustified credit, the greater the likelihood that
individuals will rationalize a claim for credit.
Equity theory (Adams 1965) may provide an (ironic)
rationalization for balancing the ledger between inputs and
rewards (Anand et al. 2004). Those who feel that their past
contributions have not been fairly recognized may feel
more entitled to take future credit, even when unjustified.
Just as employees who have been unfairly treated may use
their sense of inequitable treatment as the basis for theft
(Greenberg 1990), so too may those who feel neglected for
their past contributions take some unjustified credit as a
way of evening the score (perhaps followed by an act of
cleansing as contrition, Zhong and Liljenquist 2006).
Equity theory is primarily a motivational theory but it can
also provide the basis for justifying a claim for credit. We
also note that this close association between motivation and
rationalization will not always hold. A claimant might be
motivated to claim credit because of an upcoming perfor-
mance appraisal and then rely on an equity theory-based
rationalization to justify the claim to themselves.
Proposition 4b The greater the perceived gap between a
potential claimant’s past contributions and the credits
received, the greater the likelihood that individuals will
rationalize a claim for credit.
The differential salience of one’s own contributions may
abet the ability to rationalize. As noted earlier, it can be
easy to see one’s own work as especially important when
individuals think about their contributions. The rationali-
zation process may be further aided by psychological
processes such as the self-serving biases described by
Bazerman (2006
) that fade the ethical dimensions of the
decision (Tenbrunsel and Messick 2004).
Proposition 4c The greater the salience of an individ-
ual’s contributions to the claimant, the greater the likeli-
hood the individual will rationalize a claim for credit.
Narcissism
Several aspects of personality are likely to play moderating
roles in the credit-taking process. Three individual differ-
ences that are likely to affect the probability of credit
taking are dominance, conscientiousness, and narcissism.
Here, we use the construct of narcissism to illustrate ways
in which personality can moderate the effects of the
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
previously identified factors in the credit-taking process.
Narcissism can be seen as both a personality disorder
and a dimension of personality. As described by Ellis
(1898), narcissism includes tendencies toward excessive
self-admiration, seeing others as extensions of oneself and
approval seeking. Psychometrically, there are four com-
ponents of narcissism: entitlement, authority, arrogance,
and self-absorption (Emmons 1987). The entitlement
component of narcissism provides the most direct entry to
seeing why narcissistic individuals may be more prone to
taking credit than are others who are less narcissistic. Scale
items such as ‘I will never be satisfied until I get all that I
deserve’ and ‘I insist upon getting the respect that is due
me’ (Raskin and Hall 1979) point to likely connections
between narcissism and credit taking. While narcissists
may have an inflated sense of self, their self-image may be
quite fragile and in need of constant reinforcement, bol-
stering and validation by others (Morf and Rhodewalt
2001). This fragility may explain why narcissists also tend
to diminish the contributions of those who outperform
them (Morf and Rhodewalt 1993).
At the other end are those individuals who avoid taking
credit and actively seek opportunities for others to get the
credit. Meyerson (2001, 2003) describes quiet leaders who
make efforts to ensure that subordinates get and receive the
credit that would ordinarily go to themselves. While the
reputations of such quiet leaders can be enhanced—they
may be seen as excellent at developing future leaders
their personal visibility may suffer, including receiving less
direct credit for their efforts.
A fragile ego and a tendency to underappreciate the con-
tributions of others, when coupled with the narcissist’s
increased tendency to workplace deviance (Judge et al. 2006),
suggests that narcissists may be chronic first movers who
make claims for credit as a way of calling attention to them-
selves, even when the claims are non-existent (Path I) or
exaggerated (Path U). In the organization-level literature,
highly narcissistic CEOs (e.g., those who’s pictures and words
are prominent in annual reports and press releases) are more
likely to make bolder decisions, pursue more expensive and
moregrandiose strategies, make largerand riskier acquisitions
that produce more volatile performance, and are emboldened
by media praise (Chatterjee and Hambrick 2007, 2011).
Highly visible successes may help confirm self-views of worth
and draw attention to the narcissist. Such behaviors are con-
sistent with the idea that narcissists seek settings in which
they can get attention for their bold efforts. While we view
personality as a moderator of the relationship between contri-
butions and claims, this suggests a main effect for narcissism.
Proposition 5 The more narcissistic the individual, the
more likely the individual will make and defend a claim for
credit.
Narcissism may also affect the level of contribution or
the threshold needed before an individual makes a claim
for credit. Organizational members may have very different
standards for deciding when a claim is warranted, some
seeing small accomplishments as deserving approbation,
while others await the end of a major project before making
a claim. We have noted that narcissists may have lower
thresholds for making claims. More modest individuals
may be less disposed to claim credit, preferring to be the
organizational equivalent of the anonymous donor (or in
Perelman’s case, not challenging a rival’s lesser claim).
Although this may be true along all four paths, we expect
that the moderating effect of narcissism may be most
pronounced on Paths U and I.
Proposition 5a Narcissism moderates the relationship
between contribution and unjustified claims, with more
narcissistic individuals making claims for smaller contri-
butions than may less narcissistic individuals.
Summary
We have presented the process of taking credit as one in
which individuals make a bid for an audience’s approba-
tion on the basis of their psychological state, situational
cues, and personality. We have argued that individuals may
be more likely to take and defend claims to credit when
some or all these are present. Psychological ownership may
be most useful in explaining why justified claims to credit
are made (Paths J and S), psychological ownership, and an
environmentally sensitive form of opportunity may be the
primary factors in explaining justified but delayed claims
(Path S), while motive, opportunity, the ability to ratio-
nalize and narcissism may be useful in explaining unjus-
tified claims to credit (Paths U and I). While the usefulness
of these lenses for explaining credit taking has not been
directly tested, each is supported by indirect evidence that
suggests that it may help explain and predict credit taking
in organizations.
The Ethics of Taking Credit
Jackall’s (1988, p. 6) stark distinction between ethics inside
and outside organizations and the four opening quotes
point to some very mixed views about the ethics of credit
taking. While all four suggest that credit taking can be a
problem, their advice is quite different: it is better to do the
work and not worry about getting the credit (Confucius,
Gandhi, Truman), versus just take the credit when you can
(Jackall). That taking credit continues to be a problem is
evident in a recent article in the business press about
organizational politics: Johnson (2012, p. 12) says that
Taking Credit
123
those seeking to run many large organizations ‘spend their
entire time backstabbing, stealing credit from rivals and
waging turf wars.’ Given such competition for credit and
the conflicting advice about credit taking, it is not sur-
prising that individuals can be confused about the ethics of
taking credit. Workplace advice columns regularly feature
ethical issues that are concerned with when and how to
take credit. One column recently posed this question:
‘You’re asked by your boss to come up with a strategy for
launching a tough, new product. You seek the input of a
new junior who comes up with some brilliant tactics you
never would have thought of. Your report gets rave
reviews—and you get all the credit. You know that sharing
the accolades would help your subordinate—but might also
make you look not so smart after all. Do you give the junior
credit, or quietly enjoy your success?’ (Globe and Mail
2006, C2)
All 16 printed responses said that the credit should be
shared right away, either publicly or with the advice see-
ker’s boss, arguing that it is the right thing to do, would set
a good example and raise the quality of team culture,
cooperation, motivation, and loyalty. Others pointed to a
more calculative side: it would enhance the advice seeker’s
reputation for generosity, fairness, skill in developing a
subordinate, and being a trustworthy team player, as well
as the attraction that others would have for working with
the advice seeker (and the possibility that the subordinate
may someday be the boss). Some did see the fair appor-
tionment of credit as an ethical issue, arguing that failing to
credit the subordinate was equivalent to theft, an under-
handedness that was likely to discourage future contribu-
tions, abet a bad culture or risk later exposure.
These responses point to the complex interplay of ethics
and self-interest, doing the right thing and seizing the
opportunity. Tournament, contest, or other survival of the
fittest rationales tend to stress the opportunity dimension
and underplay the ethical dimension of organizational
dilemmas (cf. Ariely 2008; van Zyl and Lazenby 2002).
Individuals who see credit taking as instrumental to their
career progress may simply not see the ethical side of it, or
if they do, choose to ignore both. In contrast, those who are
removed from the situation read columns on business
ethics, reflect on the dilemmas posed by them, and take the
time to write in may be more likely to be sensitive to the
ethical dimension than those who are just trying to advance
in career tournaments (cf. Cooper et al. 1993). This con-
trast is consistent with the more general finding that
compared to action takers, advice givers are more psy-
chologically distant, more idealistic, place greater empha-
sis on ends, and are less pragmatic about the situation
(Danziger et al. 2012).
Thus far our main concern has been with the antecedents
of credit taking. We have used variants on ‘the justified
taking of credit’ throughout this article; embedded in the
phrase is a judgment about fairness (and, as noted by one
reader of an earlier version of this manuscript, less concern
about the defensibility of the work effort outside the
workplace). Separating someone from the fruit of their
labor, including its attendant recognition and rewards, is a
situation loaded with moral difficulties. Some would see
the taking of credit as an ethical decision. For example,
virtue ethics (Taylor 2002) focuses on strategies that
individuals can use to develop desirable character traits
such as honesty and fairness; taking unjustified credit is
unlikely to develop these virtues. In Rawls’ (1971) theory
of distributive justice, it is likely that ethical individuals
would select a rule that entitled all to be associated with
their effort and accomplishments. Such a view would also
be central to entitlement theory (Nozick 1974), where the
ability to trade one’s labor and talents forms a legitimate
basis of exchange. Taking credit from another would be to
come by the credit and the attendant rewards other than by
fair exchange.
Two systematic ways of thinking about the ethics of
taking credit within the organization are teleological and
deontological perspectives (Cole et al. 2000). A teleologi-
cal approach would assess the appropriateness of the credit
taking by evaluating the outcome. It is likely that many
schemes for apportioning credit are decided on the basis
that the apportionment is for the greater good of the work
group, department or organization, even if this is not fair to
some individuals. A point-in-time analysis might justify
this type of conclusion but over the longer run individuals
who are not appropriately recognized may be more likely
to withdraw or exit, doing harm to the team, unit, or
organization. While teleological approaches can produce
ethical outcomes if all consequences are fully considered,
they can also support rationalizations that are used to jus-
tify outcomes that are unfair to some individuals.
Kant’s (1785, 1788) categorical and practical impera-
tives and their deontological derivatives (see, e.g., Broad
1930; Zuboff 2005) provide a second basis for the ethical
guidance sought by those with the conscience to wonder
about what to do about justifiably seeking credit: ‘‘Act only
according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time
will that it should become a universal law.’’ In our domain,
this means that taking credit in a given situation is to will
the act to be a universal law. From this perspective, an
ethical credit taker would not take more credit than is due
because to do so would be to will this to be a universal law.
Kant’s practical imperative, which requires that individuals
be treated as an end rather than as a means to an end,
perhaps captures the sentiment more directly. Using
someone by taking credit for his or her contributions to
access the associated rewards contravenes the practical
imperative. Those who consistently adopt a deontological
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
approach may be less likely to be accused by the aggrieved,
such as Scully, more likely to be admired by their col-
leagues, such as the quiet leaders described by Meyerson
(2001, 2003), and more likely to give credit to the teacher
and to the junior employee in the examples above (but
perhaps more likely to suffer in career tournaments that
reward short-term success in credit taking). Adopting a
deontological approach may be easier when organizational
cultures and norms encourage collegial behavior, promote
a sense of psychological safety and discourage the mono-
maniacal pursuit of self-interest (cf. Greve et al. 2010;
Kaptein 2010; Weber and Murnighan 2008).
The categorical imperative also addresses the defensible
aspect of ethical credit taking since it discourages acts that
are unethical in the world outside the organization. Acting
on the categorical imperative may help to reduce bound-
edly ethical decision-making because it asks an actor inside
the organization whether he or she would be able to defend
the act in civil society. Zuboff (2005, p. 91) translates the
categorical imperative into practical terms for a business
audience by suggesting that ‘‘the next time you’re poised to
participate in a wrong that’s cloaked as normal, ask your-
self how you’d explain this to your children’’ (or to viewers
if you were continuously broadcast). This translation is
meant to be a check on an actor’s temptation to do what-
ever is necessary to progress in a career tournament or do
whatever the person above wants (Jackall 1988, p. 6). As a
case in point, Gerson, McConnell and Scully might have
paused mid-speech writing and asked ‘is this something I
can defend outside the walls of the White House?’
Ways Forward
We have examined some possible antecedents of credit
taking in the interest of beginning the process of system-
atically thinking about an everyday organizational phe-
nomenon. We have argued that taking credit is rooted in
feelings of psychological ownership, particularly when
justified credit is taken. We have also contended that taking
unjustified credit may stem from feelings of psychological
ownership, the presence of motive, opportunity, the ability
to rationalize and narcissism. We believe that these con-
structs may provide useful starting points for research on
when credit is taken.
A wide range of methods could be used to increase our
understanding of the credit-taking process, including
qualitative methods, archival and survey research, sce-
nario-based methodologies and experimental procedures.
Qualitative research may be particularly useful for under-
standing how more successful long-lived teams deal with
issues of credit that arise after theft or breach of trust (e.g.,
retaliation, forgiveness). The consequences of theft and
breach may be especially harmful in knowledge-based
enterprises where there are few tangible outputs. Because
teamwork depends on trust and psychological safety, an
individual who takes credit that belongs to the team can be
seen as failing to display the integrity that is part of being a
team member (Mayer et al. 1995). Comparing the process
of credit taking in successful long-lived teams and that of
less successful short-lived teams, may be one way of
examining how teams deal with the struggles of credit
taking. Thus, our first suggestion is to use qualitative
methods that focus on knowledge-based teams and ask how
the five factors affect credit taking and the ways in which
teams that vary in success and longevity deal with issues
that arise from credit taking. The question to be asked is
how variance in success and longevity both causes and is
affected by the way team members’ deal with issues of
credit.
Archival research may be another attractive way to
examine whether and how our model accounts for credit
taking. We have used several examples to illustrate the
effects of the five factors in credit taking. The model
emerged from our attempts to make sense of these exam-
ples but it would be useful to draw on a wider range of
cases to assess whether our model exhausts the useful ways
of thinking about taking credit. Archival research may be
particularly helpful in finding counter-examples, ones
where the conditions for credit taking are present but
individuals do not claim credit, as in Perelman’s failure to
press his claim for credit (and in the Gandhi and others’
opening quote about those who do the work and those who
take the credit). A number of situations might exist (other
than when there is a secondary market for credit) where
individuals are willing to see others take credit for their
work, as when an individual no longer feels a need for the
rewards that credit may provide, such as those individuals
who have entered the generative phase of their career
(Levinson 1978). Identifying such cases may help pinpoint
the boundaries for the model of credit taking presented
above.
Survey methods and scenario-based research also could
be used to assess the contributions to credit taking of the
five factors we have identified, plus others uncovered by
qualitative and archival research. Such work may rely on
self- and other-reports about contributions and bids, with
all the cognitive biases this can entail (Bazerman 2006).
Better control over measurement issues can be gained
using experimental procedures to manipulate factors such
as size of contribution and reward, power differences and
past inequities, examine the moderating effect of narcis-
sism, and observe their separate and joint effects on whe-
ther, how, when, and in what portions credit is taken and
defended. Each of these approaches would be sensible to
pursue once qualitative and archival research has helped fill
Taking Credit
123
out our understanding of the factors that influence the
taking of credit. While it would be tempting to quickly
enter the laboratory and manipulate or measure each factor,
we think it would be wiser to first use qualitative and
archival procedures to assess the completeness of the
account we have presented (cf. Cialdini 1980).
While we have focused on the conditions that promote
credit taking, we noted at the outset that we expect that the
way in which credit is taken and given can have important
consequences for both individuals and organizations.
Before closing we would like to return to the issue of
consequences and the process questions that underlie them.
Unfair recognition of one individual may diminish other
individuals’ feeling of worth and identity, negatively
impact organizational justice systems, undermine inter-
personal relationships, erode feelings of psychological
safety and break-down trust. How credit is given is a par-
ticularly critical practical issue, especially in collective
situations. Sometimes violations of fairness can be healthy
for team well-being. For example, when one team member
is in a better position to redeem credit, perhaps because of
privileged access to gatekeepers, then the whole team may
benefit when one individual takes the credit. Similarly,
heuristics such as ‘the chair of the committee gets the
credit’ might be viewed as fair if the heuristic is under-
stood beforehand and consistently followed. But negative
consequences are likely when one member of a work group
gets credit that is neither distributed nor accepted by the
rest of the team. The research question here is to under-
stand how the process of taking credit affects individuals,
groups, and organizations.
Secondary markets for credit can ameliorate some
feelings of unfairness. Speechwriters, key aids, and back-
room operatives all understand that they will not receive
public credit for their work. Similarly, mentors may allow
prote
´
ge
´
s to take full credit for a shared accomplishment
because they understand that they will receive credit in a
secondary market that acknowledges employee develop-
ment (as well as the simple pleasures that flow from seeing
a prote
´
ge
´
flourish). The functioning of these secondary
markets and their impact on individuals represent another
research area that contains interesting process questions at
the individual, group, and organizational levels.
A final process issue of interest is how disputes over
credit can be resolved when they arise. While Scully found
a national platform from which to correct the record, the
teacher’s main recourse was to write an anonymous letter
to a business advice columnist. We suspect that most
aggrieved parties just sit with their silent rage. Recognizing
the problem, a variety of institutions such as universities,
professional associations (e.g., the American Psychological
Association 2002) and publishers of professional journals
have developed formal procedures that are intended to
resolve disputes about credit. We noted earlier that the
Screenwriter’s Guild of America has a formal process for
dealing with conflicting claims for screenwriting (Friend
2003). When a movie is finished a studio submits a tenta-
tive apportionment of writing credit to the Guild, after
which screenwriters can formally dispute the apportion-
ment of credit. An arbitration hearing is held if one or more
persons challenge the apportionment (and is automatic if
someone in a position of power—producer or director—
claims screenwriting credit). Friend (2003) points out that
the arbitration process often pits members against each
other, gives rise to prolonged underground discussions
about who really wrote what, and has not resulted in much
satisfaction with the process. Others, such as the Journal of
the American Medical Association, have detailed docu-
ments that are intended to guide authors through authorship
disputes, and formulas have been suggested for deciding on
the order of authorship for publications (Winston 1985;
Fine and Kurdek 1993). The existence of guidelines has not
eliminated the discontent (Sandler and Russell 2005) and
what remains unknown is whether any of these procedures,
guidelines, and formulas is useful in reducing or resolving
disputes over credit.
Throughout we have noted that the taking of credit is a
process that can be influenced by cognitive and psycho-
logical processes that allow unjustified claims to credit to
be viewed as appropriate by the claimant (Banaji et al.
2003; Chugh et al. 2005; De Cremer et al. 2010). These
processes may allow those who make unjustified claims to
see themselves as behaving ethically and to fade the ethical
dimension of their decision (Tenbrunsel and Messick
2004), thereby facilitating rationalization. Self-serving bias
and false memory effects are psychological processes that
can affect how individuals view their contribution to an
effort and entitlement to credit. Since credit requires
audience recognition, we expect that psychological process
will play an important role in understanding the process. In
closing, we simply note that it seems likely that other
cognitive and psychological processes will be found that
play roles in contributing to making unjustified claims
seem ethical to claimants.
Conclusion
The process of taking credit can have significant emotional,
motivational, and ethical consequences for individuals,
groups, organizations, and civil society. We have suggested
ways of thinking about credit taking in organizations that
draw on psychological, situational, and personality con-
structs. Our interest is in making a start in understanding
some of the dynamics of the process. While credit taking in
organizations has not received much research attention, we
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
think an understanding of the process can help illuminate
an everyday aspect of organizational behavior that matters
to organization members.
Acknowledgments We thank Robert Jackall for setting the hook,
Monica Luthra for her early interest, Peter Dacin for his withering
critique, Pam Murphy for her candidacy, Colette Hoption for her
research assistance, Blake Ashforth and Susan Pinker for their
encouragement, the reviewers and Siva Jayaprakash for their help,
Edmund Byrne for his patience, and Perry Bamji, Peter Dunnett, Dave
Ramsden and Alan Whitehorn for sharing their many experiences.
Finally, a special thanks to the many path-takers whose behavior we
have known, some exemplary, some not.
References
Abratt, R. D., Nel, D., & Higgs, N. S. (1992). An examination of the
ethical beliefs of managers using selected scenarios in a cross-
cultural environment. Journal of Business Ethics, 11, 29–35.
Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. In L. Berkowitz
(Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 2,
pp. 267–299). New York: Academic Press.
Adams, S. (2011). September 19, Dilbert.
American Psychological Association. (2002). Ethical principles of
psychologists and code of conduct. American Psychologist, 57,
1060–1073.
Anand, V., Ashforth, B. E., & Joshi, M. (2004). Business as usual:
The acceptance and perpetuations of corruption in organizations.
Academy of Management Executive, 18, 39–53.
Ariely, D. (2008). Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that
shape our decisions. New York: HarperCollins.
Avey, J. B., Avolio, B. J., Crossley, C. D., & Luthans, F. (2009).
Psychological ownership: Theoretical extensions measurement,
and relation to work outcomes. Journal of Organizational
Behaviour, 30, 173–191.
Babiak, P., & Hare, R. (2006). Snakes in suits: When psychopaths go
to work. New York: Harper Collins.
Banaji, M., Bazerman, M., & Chugh, D. (2003). How (un)ethical Are
You? Harvard Business Review, 81, 56–64.
Barsness, Z. I., Diekmann, K. A., & Seidel, M. D. L. (2005).
Motivation and opportunity: The role of remote work, demo-
graphic dissimilarity, and social network centrality in impression
management. Academy of Management Journal, 48, 401–419.
Bazerman, M. (2006). Judgment in managerial decision making.
New York: Wiley.
Bazerman, M. H., Morgan, K. P., & Lowenstein, G. F. (1997). The
impossibility of auditor independence. Sloan Management
Review, 38(4), 89–94.
Beenen, G., & Pinto, J. (2009). Resisting organizational-level
corruption: An interview with Sherron Watkins. Academy of
Management Learning and Education, 8, 275–289.
Bettman, J. R., & Weitz, B. A. (1983). Attributions in the board room:
Causal reasoning in corporate annual reports. Administrative
Science Quarterly, 28, 165–183.
Bielby, W. T., & Bielby, D. D. (1999). Organizational mediation of
project-based labor markets: Talent agencies and the careers of
screenwriters. American Sociological Review, 64, 64–85.
Boeker, W. (1992). Power and managerial dismissal: Scapegoating at
the top. Administrative Science Quarterly, 37, 400–421.
Bolino, M. C. (1999). Citizenship and impression management: Good
soldiers or bad actors? Academy of Management Review, 26,
82–98.
Brewer, M. B. (1991). The social self: On being the same and
different at the same time. Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin, 17, 475–482.
Broad, C. D. (1930). Five types of ethical theory. New York: Harcourt
Brace.
Brown, G., Lawrence, T., & Robinson, S. L. (2005). Territoriality in
organizations. Academy of Management Review, 30, 577–594.
Brown, G., & Robinson, S. L. (2011). Reactions to territorial
infringement. Organization Science, 22, 210–224.
Burt, R. S. (2004). Structural holes and good ideas. American Journal
of Sociology, 110, 349–399.
Campbell, W. K., & Sedikides, C. (1999). Self-threat magnifies the
self-serving bias: A meta-analytic integration. Review of General
Psychology, 3, 23–43.
Caruso, E. M., Epley, N., & Bazerman, M. (2006). The costs and
benefits of undoing egocentric responsibility assessments in
groups. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91,
857–871.
Chatterjee, A., & Hambrick, D. C. (2007). It’s all about me:
Narcissistic chief executive officers and their effects on company
strategy and performance. Administrative Science Quarterly, 52,
351–386.
Chatterjee, A., & Hambrick, D. C. (2011). Executive personality,
capability cues, and risk taking: How narcissistic CEOs react to
their successes and stumbles. Administrative Science Quarterly,
56, 202–237.
Chugh, D., Banaji, M., & Bazerman, M. (2005). Bounded ethicality
as a psychological barrier to recognizing conflicts of interest. In
D. Moore, M. Cain, G. Lowenstein, & M. Bazerman (Eds.),
Conflicts of interest: Problems and solutions from law, medicine,
and organizational settings. London: Cambridge University
Press.
Cialdini, R. B. (1980). Full cycle social psychology. In L. Bickman
(Ed.), Applied social psychology annual (Vol. 1, pp. 21–47).
Beverly Hills, CA: SAGE.
Cialdini, R. B., Borden, R. J., Thorne, A., Walker, M. R., Freeman, S.,
& Sloan, L. R. (1976). Basking in reflected glory: Three
(football) field studies. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 34, 366–375.
Clive, R. B. (2011). Corporate psychopaths: Bullying and unfair
supervision in the workplace. Journal of Business Ethics, 100,
367–379.
Cohen, G. L. (2003). Party over policy: The dominating impact of
group influence on political beliefs. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 85, 808–822.
Cohen, M. D., March, J., & Olsen, J. (1972). A garbage can model of
organizational choice. Administrative Science Quarterly, 17,
1–25.
Cole, D., Sirgy, M. J., & Bird, M. M. (2000). How do managers make
teleological evaluations in ethical dilemmas? Testing part of and
extending the Hunt–Vitell model. Journal of Business Ethics, 26,
259–269.
Collins, J. D., Uhlenbruck, K., & Rodriguez, P. (2009). Why firms
engage in corruption: A top management perspective. Journal of
Business Ethics, 87, 89–108.
Colquitt, J. A., Wesson, M. J., Porter, C., Conlon, D., & Ng, K.
(2001). Justice at the millennium: A meta-analytic review of 25
years of organizational justice research. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 86, 425–445.
Confucius. no date, The Lun Yu
¨
.
Cooper, W. H., Graham, W. J., & Dyke, L. S. (1993). Tournament
players. Research in Personnel and Human Resource Manage-
ment, 11, 83–132.
Crant, M. J., & Bateman, T. S. (1993). Assignment of credit and
blame for performance outcomes. Academy of Management
Journal, 36, 7–27.
Taking Credit
123
Cressey, D. R. (1953). Other people’s money. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.
Danziger, S., Montal, R., & Barkan, R. (2012). Idealistic advice and
pragmatic choice: A psychological distance account. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 102, 1105–1117.
De Cremer, D., Tenbrunsel, A. E., & van Dijke, M. (2010).
Regulating ethical failures: Insights from psychology. Journal
of Business Ethics, 95, 1–6.
Donaldson, T. (1996). Values in Tension. Harvard Business Review,
74, 48–62.
Duffy, M. K., Ganster, D. C., & Pagon, M. (2002). Social
undermining in the workplace. Academy of Management Jour-
nal, 45, 331–351.
Dunn, J., & Schweitzer, M. E. (2005). Why good employees make
unethical decisions: The role of reward systems, organizational
culture, and managerial oversight. In R. E. Kidwell Jr. &
C. L. Martin (Eds.), Managing organizational deviance (pp.
39–68). Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Dunning, D. J., Meyerowitz, A., & Holzberg, A. D. (1989).
Ambiguity and self-evaluation: The role of idiosyncratic trait
definitions in self-serving assessments of ability. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 1082–1090.
Dyke, L. S. (1990). Self-promotion in organizations, Unpublished
doctoral dissertation. Kingston: Queen’s University.
Edmondson, A. (1999). Psychological safety and learning behavior in
work teams. Administrative Science Quarterly, 44, 350–383.
Eichenwald, K. (2005). Conspiracy of fools. New York: Broadway
Books.
Ellis, H. (1898). Auto-erotism: A psychological study. Alienist and
Neurologist, 19, 260–299.
Emmons, R. (1987). Narcissism: Theory and measurement. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 11–17.
Epley, N., & Caruso, E. M. (2004). Egocentric ethics. Social Justice
Research, 17, 171–188.
Fine, M. A., & Kurdek, L. A. (1993). Reflections on determining
authorship credit and authorship order on faculty–student
collaborations. American Psychologist, 48, 1141–1147.
Floyd, W. W., Schroeder, D. M., & Finn, D. M. (1994). Only if I am
first author: Conflict over credit in management scholarship.
Academy of Management Journal, 37, 734–747.
Fortin, M., & Fellenz, M. R. (2008). Hypocrisies of fairness: Towards
a more reflexive ethical base in organizational justice research
and practice. Journal of Business Ethics, 78, 415–433.
Friend, T. (2003, October 20). Credit Grab, The New Yorker, 161–
169.
Frum. D. J. (2007, November). David Frum’s diary. National Review
(online).
Galanter, M., & Palay, T. (1991). Tournament of lawyers: Transfor-
mation of the big law firm. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Garry, M., Manning, C. G., Loftus, E. F., & Sherman, S. J. (1996).
Imagination inflation: Imagining a childhood event inflates
confidence that it occurred. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 3,
208–214.
Gerson, M. J. (2007). Heroic conservatism: Why republicans need to
embrace America’s ideals (and why they deserve to fail if they
don’t). New York: HarperOne.
Gessen, M. (2009). Perfect rigor: A genius and the mathematical
breakthrough of the century. New York: Houghton Mifflin
Harcourt.
Globe and Mail. (2006, October 1). Workplace ethics, C2, Toronto,
Canada.
Greenberg, J. (1990). Employee theft as a reaction to underpayment
inequity: The hidden cost of pay cuts. Journal of Applied
Psychology, 75, 561–568.
Greve, H. R., Palmer, D., & Pozner, J. E. (2010). Organizations gone
wild. Academy of Management Annals, 4, 53–107.
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind why good people are divided by
politics and religion. New York: Pantheon.
Higgins, C. A., & Judge, T. A. (2004). The effect of applicant
influence tactics on recruiter perceptions of fit and hiring
recommendations: A field study. Journal of Applied Psychology,
89, 622–632.
Hollander, E. P. (1958). Conformity, status, and idiosyncrasy credit.
Psychological Review, 65, 117–127.
Immen, W. (2010, March 5). When leaders become glory hounds.
Globe and Mail, B15–16.
Jackall, R. (1988). Moral mazes: The world of corporate managers.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, T. (2001). Cultural values and management ethics: A
10-nation study. Human Relations, 54, 1267–1302.
Jensen, M. C., & Meckling, W. H. (1976). Theory of the firm:
Managerial behavior, agency costs and ownership structure.
Journal of Financial Economics, 3, 305–360.
Johnson, L. (2012). The lunatics have taken over the boardroom.
Financial Times, March 7.
Judge, T., LePine, J., & Rich, B. L. (2006). Loving yourself abundantly:
relationship of the narcissistic personality to self- and other percep-
tions of workplace deviance, leadership, and task and contextual
performance. Journal of Applied Psychology, 91, 762–776.
Kant, I. (1785). Groundwork of the metaphysic of morals, various
editions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (1788). Critique of practical reason, various editions.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kanter, R. M. (1977). Men and women of the corporation. New York:
Basic Books.
Kaptein, M. (2010). The ethics of organizations: A longitudinal study
of the US working population. Journal of Business Ethics, 92,
601–618.
Kelman, H. C., & Hamilton, L. (1989). Crimes of obedience. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Levinson, D. J. (1978). The seasons of a man’s life. New York:
Ballantine.
Locke, J. (1690). Two treatises on government. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Marx, K. (1847). Wage, labour and capital, various editions.
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Mayer, R. C., Davis, J. H., & Schoorman, F. D. (1995). An integrative
model of organizational trust. Academy of Management Review,
20, 709–734.
McDonald, G. M., & Zepp, R. (1988). Ethical perceptions of Hong
Kong Chinese business managers. Journal of Business Ethics, 7,
835–845.
McFarlin, D. B., & Sweeney, P. D. (1992). Distributive and
procedural justice as predictors of satisfaction with personal
and organizational outcomes. Academy of Management Journal,
35, 626–637.
McGinn, D. (2009, November 17) Brilliant Idea! I’ll Steal It. Globe
and Mail, L1–2.
Mechanic, D. (1962). Sources of power for lower participants in
complex organizations. Administrative Science Quarterly, 7
,
349–364.
Merritt, A. C., Effron, D., Fein, S., Savitsky, K., Tuller, D., & Monin,
B. (2012). The strategic pursuit of moral credentials. Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 48, 774–777.
Merritt, A. C., Effron, D. A., & Monin, B. (2010). Moral self-
licensing: When being good frees us to be bad. Social and
Personality Psychology Compass, 4, 344–357.
Metha, S., & Kau, S. (1984). Marketing executives’ perceptions of
unethical practices. Singapore Management Review, 6, 25–35.
Meyerson, D. E. (2001) Radical change, the quiet way, Harvard
Business Review, 92–100.
W. J. Graham, W. H. Cooper
123
Meyerson, D. E. (2003). Tempered radicals: How everyday leaders
inspire changes at work. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Mezulis, A., Abramson, L., Hyde, J., & Hankin, B. (2004). Is there a
universal positivity bias in attributions? A meta-analytic review
of individual, developmental, and cultural differences in the self-
serving attributional bias. Psychological Bulletin, 130, 711–747.
Miller, D. T., & Effron, D. A. (2010). Psychological license: When it
is needed and how it functions. Advances in Experimental Social
Psychology, 43, 115–155.
Miller, D. T., & Ross, M. (1975). Self-serving bias in the attribution of
causality: Fact or fiction? Psychological Bulletin, 82, 213–225.
Morf, C., & Rhodewalt, F. (1993). Narcissism and self-evaluation
maintenance. Explorations in Object Relations. Personality and
Social Psychology Bulletin, 19, 668–676.
Morf, C., & Rhodewalt, F. (2001). Unraveling the paradoxes of
narcissism. A dynamic self-regulatory processing model. Psy-
chological Inquiry, 12, 177–196.
Murphy, P. R., & Dacin, M. T. (2011). Psychological pathways to
fraud: Understanding and preventing fraud in organizations.
Journal of Business Ethics, 101, 601–618.
Nasar, S., & Gruber, D. (2006, August 28). Manifold destiny, The
New Yorker, 44–57.
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic
Books.
Pierce, J., Kostova, T., & Dirks, K. (2001). Toward a theory of
psychological ownership in organizations. Academy of Manage-
ment Review, 26, 298–310.
Pinker, S. (2005, May 25). Problem Solving, The Globe and Mail, C5.
Pozner, J. E. (2007). Stigma and settling up: An integrated approach
to the consequences of organizational misconduct for organiza-
tional elites. Journal of Business Ethics, 80, 141–150.
Public Company Accounting Oversight Board. (2005). Consideration
of fraud in a financial statement audit, AU Section 316. www.
pcaobus.org.
Raskin, R. N., & Hall, C. S. (1979). Narcissistic personality
inventory. Psychological Reports, 45, 590.
Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Rogerson, M. D., Gottlieb, M. C., Handelsman, M. M., Knapp, S., &
Younggren, J. (2011). Nonrarional processes in ethical decision
making. American Psychologist, 66, 614–623.
Sandler, J., & Russell, B. (2005). Faculty–student collaboration:
Ethics and satisfaction in authorship credit. Ethics and Behav-
iour, 15, 65–80.
Schlenker, B. R. (1980). Impression management: The self-concept,
social identity, and interpersonal relations. Monterey, CA:
Brooks/Cole.
Scully, M. (2007). Present at the creation. The Atlantic, 300, 77–88.
Sedikides, C., & Strube, M. J. (1997). Self-evaluation: To thine own
self be good, to thine own self be sure, to thine own self be true,
and to thine own self be better. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in
experimental social psychology (Vol. 29, pp. 209–269). New
York: Academic Press.
Shapiro, D. L., Boss, A. D., Salas, S., Tangirala, S., & Von Glinow,
M. A. (2011). When are transgressing leaders punitively judged?
An Empirical Test. Journal of Applied Psychology, 96, 412–422.
Sharman, S. J., & Calacouris, D. S. (2010). Do people’s motives
influence their susceptibility to imagination inflation? Experi-
mental Psychology, 57, 77–82.
Simon, H. A. (1957). Models of man. New York: Wiley.
Simon, S. A., & Eby, L. T. (2003). A typology of negative mentoring
experiences: A multidimensional scaling study. Human Rela-
tions, 56, 1083–1106.
Staw, B. M., McKechnie, P. I., & Pfuffer, S. M. (1983). The
justification of organizational performance. Administrative Sci-
ence Quarterly, 28, 582–600.
Staw, B. M., & Ross, J. (1987). Behavior in escalation situations:
Antecedents, prototypes and solutions. Research in Organiza-
tional Behavior, 9, 39–78.
Stevenson, W. B., & Greenberg, D. (2000). Agency and social
networks: Strategies of action in a social structure of position,
opposition, and opportunity. Administrative Science Quarterly,
45, 651–678.
Stone, T. H., & Cooper, W. H. (2009). Emerging credits. The
Leadership Quarterly, 20, 785–798.
Taylor, R. (2002). An introduction to virtue ethics. Amherst, MA:
Prometheus Books.
Tenbrunsel, A., & Messick, D. (2004). Ethical fading: The role of
self-deception in unethical behavior. Social Justice Research, 17,
223–236.
Thomas, A. K., Bulevich, J. B., & Loftus, E. F. (2003). Exploring the
role of repetition and sensory elaboration in the imagination
inflation effect. Memory and Cognition, 31, 630–640.
Toffler, B. L. (2003). Final accounting: Ambition, greed, and the fall
of Arthur Andersen. New York: Broadway Books.
Van Dyne, L., & Pierce, J. L. (2004). Psychological ownership and
feelings of possession: Three field studies predicting employee
attitudes and organizational citizenship behavior. Journal of
Organizational Behaviour, 25, 439–459.
van Zyl, E., & Lazenby, K. (2002). The relation between ethical
behaviour and workstress amongst a group of managers working
in affirmative action positions. Journal of Business Ethics, 40,
111–119.
Vroom, V. H. (1964). Work and motivation. New York: Wiley.
Weber, J. M., & Murnighan, J. K. (2008). Dilemmas. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 95, 1340–1353.
Weick, K. (1995). Sensemaking in organizations. Thousand Oaks,
CA: SAGE.
Williamson, O. (1975). Markets and hierarchies: Analysis and
antitrust implications. New York: Free Press.
Winston, R. (1985). A suggested procedure for determining order of
authorship in research publications. Journal of Counseling and
Development, 63, 515–518.
Zhong, C.-B., & Liljenquist, K. (2006). Washing away your sins:
Threatened morality and physical cleansing. Science, 313,
1451–1452.
Zuboff, S. (2005, January). A starter kit for business ethics. Fast
Company, 91.
Taking Credit
123