Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
5 EV
Abstract:
Recent attention to character formation as the key to
moral education has also regarded personal and fictional
role models as appropriate means to this end. Moreover,
while one may have grave reservations about the influ
-
ence of personal role-models (perhaps upon the young by
those they happen to admire), serious fiction has often
been considered an inspirational source of moral exam
-
ple. Still, while this paper ultimately mounts a defence
of the moral educational potential of literature, it is also
concerned to press two significant reservations about any
and all attention to fictional character as a means to such
education. First, since the ultimate meaning of any fic
-
tional character and conduct is largely, if not exclusively,
confined to their narrative contexts, we should not sup
-
pose them to have any direct role-modelling application
to the affairs of human life beyond such contexts. Second,
and more significantly, since morality is also ultimately
more than and/or not entirely reducible to the contingen
-
cies of human character, attention to either fictional or
real-life character must anyway fall somewhat short of
full moral education.
Keywords: literature, fiction, character, virtue, moral edu
-
cation.
Resumen:
El interés reciente por la formación del carácter como aspecto
clave en la educación moral ha llevado a considerar también los
modelos de referencia personales y ficcionales como medios apro
-
piados para este fin. Además, aunque uno pueda albergar serias
reservas con respecto a la influencia de los modelos de referencia
personales (quizá la que ejercen sobre los jóvenes las personas
que estos admiran), la ficción seria se ha visto a menudo como
una fuente inspiradora de ejemplo moral. Aun así, a pesar de que
este artículo defiende el potencial de la literatura como promotor
de la educación moral, también expresa dos reservas importantes
sobre la atención dedicada a los personajes de ficción como medio
para dicha educación. En primer lugar, puesto que el sentido final
de cualquier personaje y conducta ficcionales está, en su mayoría
(si no en exclusiva), limitado a sus contextos narrativos, no debe
-
ríamos asumir que tienen alguna aplicación directa como mode-
lo de referencia en los asuntos de la vida humana fuera de esos
contextos. En segundo lugar, y aún más importante, puesto que
la moralidad es, en última instancia, algo más que (o no reducible
totalmente a) las contingencias del carácter humano, la atención
a un personaje de ficción o de la vida real no es suficiente, en
cualquier caso, para una educación moral completa.
Palabras clave: literatura, ficción, personaje, carácter, vir-
tud, educación moral.
Satan’s virtues:
On the moral educational prospects of fictional character
Las virtudes de Satanás: perspectivas de educación moral del personaje de ficción
David Carr, PhD. Emeritus Professor. University of Edinburgh ([email protected]).
David CARR
Date of reception of the original: 2023-10-13.
Date of approval: 2023-11-21.
Please, cite this article as follows: Carr, D. (2024).Satan’s virtues: On the moral educational prospects of fictional character [Las virtudes de Satanás:
perspectivas de educación moral del personaje de ficción]. Revista Española de Pedagogía, 82 (287), 5-16. https://doi.org/10.22550/2174-0909.3923
“Poetry is something more philosophic and of graver
import than history, since its statements are of the na-
ture more of universals, whereas those of history are
singulars. By a universal statement I mean one as to
what such or kind of a man will probably or necessarily
say or do, which is the aim of poetry.”
(Aristotle, 1941a, p. 1464)
David CARR
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
6 EV
“We touch here on a central dilemma of literature. If
literature is didactic, it tends to injure its own integrity;
if it ceases wholly to be didactic, it tends to injure its
own seriousness.”
(Frye, 1974, p. 169)
1. Theorising moral education
Briefly, the dial of modern academic thought about
moral learning and education seems to have swung
between two apparently opposite poles of attention to
rational thought and principle on the one hand and
focus on character and practical conduct on the other.
The former emphasis on thought and principle, un-
der the (probably main) influence of sociologist Emile
Durkheim (1973) and psychologists Jean Piaget (1932)
and Lawrence Kohlberg (1974), was to dominate moral
educational theorising for much of the twentieth cen-
tury. For all these theorists, it was basically an applica-
tion to educational practice of the deontological ethics
of the philosopher Immanuel Kant. On this view, mor-
al development is largely a matter of cultivation of
rational respect for universal principles of other-re-
garding rights and justice. On the other hand, the
emphasis on moral education more as the psycholog-
ical cultivation of character and correct practical con-
duct, while undoubtedly drawing some inspiration
from the learning theory of early twentieth century
(Russian and American) behaviourism, seems to have
been largely a late twentieth-century reaction to what
was perceived as the excessive rationalism and intel-
lectualism and insufficiently practical focus of cogni-
tive developmental theory (see, for example, Ryan &
Bohlin, 2003; Lickona, 2004).
A moment’s thought, however, should suffice to
show that any extreme swing of the pendulum be-
tween moral reason and practical conduct is hardly
helpful and that responsible moral agency (as in the
case of other human action) cannot be other than ap-
propriate conduct in the light of some form of reason.
In this light, it has seemed for many contemporary
theorists of moral education that final reconciliation
of any and all oppositions between moral educational
reason and conduct is to be found in a recently revived
ethics of virtue drawing mainly on Aristotle’s Nicoma-
chean ethics (1941b). On this view, to be sure, the key
components of moral life, commonly referred to in An-
glophone usage as virtues (via the Greek arete and the
Latin virtus) are basically qualities of good character.
Such qualities are considered good (morally and oth-
erwise) as conducive to the human well-being or flour-
ishing of Aristotle’s ethically naturalist conception of
eudaimonia. Virtues such as self-control, courage,
justice and fair dealing shape or condition human
conduct in generally positive or beneficial directions,
whereas human vices, such as indiscipline, cowardice
and deceit, are the source of human ill or harm.
However, such virtues are not merely mechanical or
conditioned routines or habits. Rather, they are dis-
criminating responses to the needs or requirements of
some particular human circumstances under the ra-
tional guidance of that intellectual virtue of practical
wisdom to which Aristotle refers as phronesis. It is via
the rational exercise of phronesis that we can come to
appreciate that courage, for example, is not always a
matter of mere fearlessness: in short, that as much
moral error may lie in store from the insufficient fear
or caution of recklessness as from the excessive fear
of cowardice.
To be sure, this is something that we may know
on the basis of familiar (empirical) human interactive
experience: those who are characteristically self-con-
trolled, courageous and respectful of the interests,
rights and feelings of others are generally regarded
as better and admired more than those who have no
self-control, pluck or fellow-feeling. Still, while such
considerations about good character appear well and
good up to a point, they are far from morally conclu-
sive or unproblematic. To start with, phronesis, or
practical wisdom, may have its uses for the right psy-
chological balance of rational perception and affect in
(say) the proper exercise of courage; thus, for exam-
ple, absence of fear may be as (morally or otherwise)
bad as excessive fear. However, it is less than clear
how it might serve well in advising us how to act in
those not humanly infrequent circumstances of moral
uncertainty wherein it is precisely unclear what we
should do. Thus, for example, in the famous soliloquy
of Shakespeare’s Hamlet, the prince asks (presumably,
about which is of more virtuous character): “Whether
’tis nobler in the mind to suffer the slings and arrows
of outrageous fortune or to take up arms against a sea
of troubles and by opposing end them?”. Here, whatev-
er phronesis may have to contribute to Hamlet’s grasp
of courageous action, it would hardly seem to help
much towards advising what he should do. And, to be
sure, Aristotle himself is fairly explicit that practical
wisdom, as a form of deliberation rather than knowl-
edge (Aristotle, 1941b), must fall short of any such ad-
vice in Hamlet’s or like circumstances. Indeed, all that
phronesis seems to offer to would-be virtuous agents is
Editorial
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
7 EV
the advice that there are no general rational principles
whereby such moral questions might be decided and
that what it might be right to do depends much upon
the agent’s particular context or circumstances. But
this is not much help to Hamlet either: he could be as
clear as day about his circumstances, but yet quite un
-
clear about precisely whether he should or should not
rightly slay his uncle and stepfather Claudius.
But it seems a no less serious problem about basing
morality on some notion of good or virtuous charac-
ter that, apart from the fact that agents of bad or vi-
cious character may sometimes perform good actions,
agents of virtuous or morally exemplary character can
act badly or even wickedly. It is neither logically con-
tradictory nor at odds with common experience that
genuinely temperate, courageous (or even mostly oth-
er-regarding) agents may often behave in quite moral-
ly wrong or unjustifiable ways. To be sure, it may be
insisted by some virtue ethicists that there can be no
genuine courage, temperance or other virtues unless
these character traits are directed towards morally
justified ends (see, for example, Geach, 1977); and it
is possible (though by no means certain) that Aristotle
himself may have subscribed to some such unity of vir-
tues thesis. Still, first, if this position is not just actu-
ally question-begging, it would certainly set an impos-
sibly high bar for most if not all common ascription of
temperance, courage or even kindness or forgiveness:
it makes perfectly good sense to regard a bank robber
as truly courageous person or as a genuinely kind fa-
ther even though he is not good or virtuous in other
respects. Secondly, however, it is far from clear how
(on a strict virtue ethical perspective) any such mor-
al justification might be grounded. For while Aristotle
certainly explored the idea of justice as both as charac-
ter trait and more general moral principle (supposing
this to be one likely yardstick of the moral), it there-
fore seems hard to construe virtuous character as oth-
er than largely strict observance of the principle. But
such dependency of character on principle would now
seem to jeopardise the status of virtue ethics as a strict
ethics of character. And it should here be recalled that
Elizabeth Anscombe, the founder of modern virtue
ethics, commended return to an Aristotelian ethics
of character precisely in view of her rejection of any
useful search for a more principled measure of moral
value (Anscombe, 1958).
Moreover, if we are to agree with Aristotle that the
human virtues (bearing in mind that ancient Greek
virtue and virtues could be other than human) of his
Nicomachean ethics are not innate, but acquired, this
last point brings into quite sharp relief the problem
of how such qualities of character might be developed
through experience or education. To be sure, Aristotle
affirms that regular practice of the virtues is a key
mechanism of virtuous character formation, but this
obviously cannot be in and of itself sufficient. Besides,
primary focus on habit formation risks some relapse
into cruder behavioural conceptions of character ed-
ucation and losing sight of the contextualised guid-
ance of Aristotelian phronesis, or practical wisdom.
Nonetheless, the same Aristotelian repudiation in the
name of phronesis of any appeal to general principles
of moral conduct, reinforced by Anscombe’s later dis-
missal of the principled ethics of duty (deontology)
and utility (utilitarianism or consequentialism) of her
day, would also seem to leave the nature of virtue ac-
quisition no less uncertain. In short, if virtuous char-
acter needs to avoid the devil of habituation to fairly
routine patterns of behaviour on the one hand and
the no less undiscriminating deep blue sea of appeal
to general moral principles on the other, how are as-
piring virtuous agents to learn or acquire the more
context-sensitive patterns of practical deliberation
and judgement that serve to define genuine virtuous
agency? Indeed, bearing in mind here that the virtues
of good character are far from synonymous with moral
conduct, by what measure might such judgements
count as moral rather than (say) merely prudential or
instrumentally opportune?
2. The prospects of moral learning from
character
In the event, those drawn to the contemporary
virtue ethical focus on qualities of so-called good char-
acter as the heart and soul of human moral life are
inclined to regard something like close (empirical) en-
counter with or observation of the motives and conduct
of others as the key means to moral learning. In short,
on this view, effective moral learning crucially requires
exposure to the moral example of others via the process
that is usually referred to as role-modelling. Indeed, it
might here be noticed that the function of role-model-
ling in moral learning has been strongly reinforced in
latter day virtue ethics by a theory of so-called “exem-
plarism” (Zabzebski, 2010, 2013; for insightful criti-
cism, see Szutta, 2019) that takes admiration of others
to be the key mechanism of moral learning. To be sure,
this perspective may appear compelling insofar as it
seems undeniable that much moral learning does ev-
idently follow from the influence of others, especially
David CARR
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
8 EV
those to whom the young are exposed in the persons of
such early custodians as parents and teachers. This,
in turn, speaks strongly in favour of some social and
professional case for ensuring, as far as possible, that
such early carers are persons of decent and responsible
character and conduct (see, for example, Carr, 2007).
Still, this line of argument may seem to be little more
than question-begging and to put the empirical cart
of admirable or imitable character before the horse of
moral or normative appreciation. For how is the po
-
tential moral learner to recognise that those to whom
they are exposed as appropriate role models come up
to reputable moral scratch? Indeed, the very social
and professional case for trying to ensure that early
carers are morally respectable agents itself rests upon
the commonly accepted fact that the influence of oth-
er people can be as often for moral ill as good: it is
all too clear, from the slightest acquaintance with past
human history and contemporary global politics, that
very large numbers of people have been and continue
to be all too easily influenced by persons of the worst
possible human character and conduct in the course of
close or more remote encounter, and thereby prompted
towards the perpetration of unspeakable human injus-
tices and atrocities. (For recent criticism of role-mod-
elling approaches to moral education, see Carr, 2023a.)
That said, virtue ethicists and other would-be char-
acter educators have been drawn to another rather
less immediately personal but clearly time-honoured
route to good or virtuous character formation via the
exposure of young or old to the rich heritage of lit-
erary narrative. A literary narrative which, from the
earliest days of oral and written storytelling, has in-
variably been directly concerned with often detailed
exploration of the consequences for (moral or other)
good or ill of human psychology and agency. Thus,
while moral and educational advocates of more nor-
matively principled deontological, or consequentialist,
ethics (of precisely the sort condemned by Anscombe)
have been largely indifferent to past literature as a
potential means to moral education, philosophers in-
terested in character as a key engine of moral agency
have been increasingly attentive to this possibility or
prospect. One notable example is the distinguished
twentieth century philosopher and popular novelist
Iris Murdoch. While more influenced by Plato than
Aristotle and perhaps not a virtue ethicist of recent
stamp, she has clearly defended non-literal narrative
or fiction as a key means to human understanding of
the moral implications of character in both her philo-
sophical and fictional writings (Murdoch 1970, 1973,
1997). For another, the highly influential (especially
with regard to various forms of educational and other
applied ethics) contemporary virtue ethicist Alastair
MacIntyre has insisted that fictional literature and
narratives (as distinct from the descriptive literature
or discourse of this or that empirical scientific en-
quiry) reflect or constitute the basic logical form of
human self-understanding in terms of moral agency
(MacIntyre, 1981). On such views, we may stand to
learn much if not everything about good or bad human
motives and conduct and what makes them so from
close attention to the past and present imaginative
works of Euripides, Shakespeare or Tolstoy (which
may also serve to explain why such fictions have so
often found their way into the educational curricula
of many if not most schools).
This general perspective on the moral educational
significance and prospects of what has been celebrated
as great or serious literature merits serious attention.
Various defences of this view, such as so-called ethi-
cism (Gaut, 1996) and moderate moralism (Carroll,
1996, 1998), have lately appeared in the literature of
aesthetic theory. That said, this view is neither un-
contested, entirely well formulated nor problem-free
(especially in any overstated form). In this light, we
may for the moment briefly notice and dismiss the
general drift of one familiar objection to the moral ed-
ucational potential of literature from the direction of
so-called aestheticism. Aestheticism (defended of late
with specific regard to fiction by Peter Lamarque; see,
for example, Lamarque & Olsen, 1990, or Lamarque,
1996) is the source of two main complaints about any
suggested moral educational use of literature. First,
insofar as fictions are artworks, no reading of them
for the purpose of moral edification may amount to
genuine literary appreciation. Second, insofar as such
works are imaginative creations, they cannot be ex-
pected and must fail to shed much if any light on real
human moral issues. Indeed, far from shedding fur-
ther light on human moral concerns, the ascription
of moral significance to any fictional literature would
appear to presuppose some already existing moral per-
spective on the part of readers. For present purposes,
however, the key flaw of aestheticism would seem to
be some serious conflation of the fairly distinct con-
cepts of the artistic and the aesthetic; indeed, of effec-
tive reduction of the former to the latter.
Briefly, for present purposes, while the distinction
between the aesthetic and the artistic has been various-
ly made in recent times (see, for example, Best, 1982;
Editorial
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
9 EV
Hepburn, 1984; Carroll, 1986; Carr, 1999; Stecker,
2005; McFee, 2005), it is clear that there are objects
or events of aesthetic concern (such as sunsets or
birdsong) that are of no artistic point or significance.
And (at least notionally) there are artistic concerns
or achievements (such as some conceptual works) of
little or no aesthetic import. To be sure, there is some
danger of overstating this distinction insofar as art-
works entirely devoid of aesthetic qualities (such as
perhaps Cage’s 4’33” ) seem to be also the exception
rather than the rule. Still, it seems safe enough to say
that while most literary artists are concerned to give
aesthetic form to their works, they are also mostly
concerned to express something of substantial artistic
point substance. Unlike sunsets or birdsongs, literary
works such as poems, novels or plays invariably have
some dramatic, psychological, moral or other point
or purpose. Thus, while such poets as Wordsworth,
Yeats and Eliot; such dramatists as Euripides and
Shakespeare, and such novelists as Austen, Dickens
and Dostoevsky are evidently creators of works of
aesthetically significant shape and form, they are no
less clearly concerned to express or convey substantial
points or lessons to readers about the world, human
association and psychological, moral or other human
nature. Indeed, any failure to appreciate this would
clearly miss the artistic point of such works almost
entirely. This said, unlike (say) histories or newspa-
pers, it is not the main point or intent of artworks
to report or comment directly on the happenings of
everyday human life and association. To this extent,
there would still seem to be something in the aestheti-
cist objection to which we will need to return follow-
ing some attention to the moral prospects and limita-
tions of any and all attention to the fictional depiction
of human character.
3. Fictional attention to human virtuous and
other character
There cannot, of course, be much doubt that books
(of all kinds and genres) comprise much of the educa-
tional input of modern literate societies and cultures.
To be sure, while some of this literature has sought to
transmit scientific and technical knowledge of human
material or economic progress, much has evidently
been concerned with the wider moral and spiritual
formation of societies and cultures. Thus, the Chris-
tian Bible and Shakespeare have been jointly cited as
the basic texts of western civilization. That said, the
plays of Shakespeare and other great literary figures
of the western canon, beginning perhaps with Homer
and the classic Greek tragedians, are evidently works
of fiction; as, indeed, the Christian Bible is also like-
ly to be considered by many, if not most people, in
the secular climate of contemporary western society.
Thus, on one extreme view, it may be said that such
works could or should have no significant influence
on anything of much modern concern. As already not-
ed, however, the virtue ethicist Alasdair MacIntyre
has compellingly argued (broadly in the spirit of
Aristotle) that the creative and imaginative narratives
of received culture are rich and indispensable sources
of moral and spiritual wisdom to which human agents
cannot avoid turning for guidance. From the very
dawn of humanity, on this view, such narratives have
been the main source or vehicle for exploration of the
complexities of character, motive and conduct (even
where these have been attributed to non-human
agents or animals) as implicated in the human search
for ultimate purpose and meaning in life.
In this light, MacIntyre (1981) regards narrative
as the basic logical form of human moral understand-
ing of self and others: as he puts it, humans essen-
tially understand themselves as characters in stories.
Again, however, this view has also been echoed by
other moral theorists and is perhaps most signifi-
cantly anticipated (though, from a rather different
Platonic perspective) by the distinguished twentieth
century philosopher and novelist Iris Murdoch. More
precisely, Murdoch argued that novelists should re-
gard it as the very purpose of fictional work to ex-
plore the moral complexities of human character and
association, and professed this to be her aim in her
own fictional work. While this view would appear
somewhat overstated (since novels and other fiction-
al literature have often set out with the rather less
ambitious purposes of entertaining or exploring other
aspects of human life), it is nevertheless consistent
with a time-honoured perspective on the role of fic-
tion and drama in the economy of human moral edi-
fication. Hence, exploration of moral character, asso-
ciation and conduct have certainly had a large, if not
pre-eminent, role in the works of such authors of the
western canon as Sophocles, Euripides, Shakespeare,
Cervantes, Jane Austen, Charles Dickens, William
Thackeray, Thomas Hardy, James, George Eliot, D.
H. Lawrence and countless others.
Still, alongside his defence of imaginative litera-
ture as a prime vehicle of moral and spiritual narra-
tives, MacIntyre also embraced (at least in his early
and more influential major works) a non-naturalist
David CARR
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
10 EV
ethics according to which virtues are socially con
-
structed products of essentially rival cultural and
moral traditions that have also often diverged to the
point of direct opposition or conflict. Hence, while still
following Aristotle in construing virtues as integral
to, or constitutive of, human flourishing, divergent
or rival social and cultural traditions have often en-
shrined or celebrated different virtues or moral pri-
orities. While this case is made by MacIntyre mainly
by reference to past cultural, theological and philo-
sophical trends (for example, in terms of the contrast
between the heroic virtues of past pre-modern societies
and the more compassionate virtues of Christendom,
or between the Christianity and pagan Aristotelian-
ism that Aquinas sought to reconcile), such moral
divergence might well be expected to show up quite as
conspicuously in past and present literature (and he
does illustrate this by reference to Icelandic sagas and
other literature). As I have elsewhere argued (Carr,
2017), Macintyre’s overall presentation of this case
seems questionable on the grounds that, while human
literary works could be hardly other than products
of their historical socio-cultural contexts, it is nev-
ertheless apparent that the work of most past great
authors (such as those already cited) is often notable
for its moral critique of the values of such authors’
own societies. All the same, it appears that attention
to imaginative literature does indeed reveal quite dra-
matic conflicts and ambivalences between conceptions
of virtue and moral flourishing, ancient and modern,
that also seem quite beyond MacIntyrean or other
(not least Aristotelian) resolution.
There can also, of course, be little doubt about the
enormous economic, social, cultural and other changes
that have overtaken human life and association (per-
haps most notably in developed western countries)
from antiquity to the modern day (for brief notice of
these, one might need only consult Marx’s Communist
manifesto.) With respect to present literary concerns,
however, we might observe two crucial periods of west-
ern European history. The first of these is the period of
complex transition from medieval feudalism to modern
industrialism that is generally termed the Renaissance.
While, on the one hand, often nostalgic for the ideals
and learning of classical antiquity, it is also a period
of shifting post-medieval social and economic trends
and of a new humanism of scientific discovery and ar-
tistic creation. This general period is witness to the
emergence of writers of such enduring stature, impact
and importance as Thomas More, Edmund Spenser,
Shakespeare, Cervantes, Francis Bacon and Christopher
Marlowe, whose works variously reflect such social and
economic transition from the medieval to the modern
(as evident, for example, in emerging class tension be-
tween an older feudal aristocracy and a rising economi-
cally powerful mercantile bourgeoisie).
Clearly, however, the other highly significant rev-
olutionary episode of European history, occurring
around the height of the Renaissance, was the Refor-
mation. Thus, from its early sixteenth century origin,
rejection of the traditional hegemony of the Roman
church by various movements of religious reform also
resulted (along with much bloodshed) in social, cultur-
al, moral, spiritual, intellectual (and, inevitably, liter-
ary) ferment and revolution from one end of Christen-
dom to the other.
In this light, one author whose work perhaps more
than any other reflects the cultural and intellectual
turmoil, tensions and ambivalences of such times (par-
ticularly in his own politically and religiously divided
country) is the English poet John Milton. The moral
and spiritual tensions and ambivalences in Milton’s
work are plain enough. On the one hand, as an advo-
cate of religious reform, Milton aspires to purify Chris-
tian faith of what he and other reformers construe as
the tyrannical and oppressive abuses of Roman eccle-
siastical hierarchy. However, he does so without any
fundamental rejection of the essentially authoritarian
Christian narrative of sin through disobedience and
redemption via (according to much Protestant theol-
ogy) fairly arbitrary divine grace and forgiveness. On
the other hand, however, as a proto-liberal champion
of freedom of conscience, thought and speech, Milton
is also an advocate of religious and political dissent
from unwarranted or arbitrary (especially secular) au-
thority or coercion.
Once these two inclinations or commitments on
Milton’s part are made explicit, their evident tensions
or conflicts are not hard to see. They are also conspic-
uously apparent in the literary work for which Milton
is best remembered: his remarkable blank verse epic
Paradise lost. To begin with, it is fairly evident that the
rebel angel Satan is the most prominent and memora-
ble character of Milton’s poem (if not, indeed, its actu-
al hero). To be sure, Satan is on the wrong side of the
Christian religious tracks and his downfall (in line with
orthodox Christian theology) is attributed to his disobe-
dience of a benevolent and merciful God. In this regard,
Milton’s narrative has Satan confessing at one point to
his ingratitude for God’s favours: “What could be less
Editorial
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
11 EV
than to afford him praise. The easiest recompense, and
pay him thanks. How due! Yet all his good proved ill in
me. And wrought but malice” (Milton, 2005).
On the other hand, Satan (in more the patrician
spirit of Aristotle) seems to see no compelling reason
for gratitude if divine or other benefits are bestowed
de haut en bas by imposed, if not arbitrary, authority:
“Lifted up so high, I denied subjection, and thought one
step higher would set me highest; and in a moment quit
the debt immense of endless gratitude, so burdensome
still paying, still to owe” (Milton, 2005).
At all events, leaving aside for the moment his the
-
ologically ambivalent stance, the most striking feature
of Satan is that he is a courageous rebel who is un-
willing to accept a destiny of submission to the will of
others and a life that is not self-determined, authentic
or self-determined. On the one hand, to be sure, such
self-assertion or refusal of any authority may some-
times appear to be no more than misplaced or perverse
pride, or hubris: indeed, the Devil’s tempting of Christ
to throw himself from the pinnacle of the temple in
the gospel narratives is evidently the theological war-
rant for regarding Satan’s pride in Paradise lost as the
last, worst and most unpardonable of sins. But Satan’s
defiance of authority may clearly also be regarded as
morally exemplary; as, precisely, a source of admirable
virtues of courage, initiative and resilience in the face
of unequal and (literally) hopeless odds and adversity.
Moreover, to those with some acquaintance with liter-
ary traditions and trends prior and subsequent to Par-
adise lost, it is impossible to ignore the conspicuous
(moral or other) literary predecessors and successors
to Milton’s Satan.
4. The devil’s ancestors, disciples and heirs
It would seem that Satan’s most conspicuous liter-
ary antecedent is the titan Prometheus of Greek myth,
memorably dramatized by the tragedian Aeschylus in
Prometheus bound. In defiance of Zeus, he stole fire
to liberate humans from impotent submission to a
divinely ordained state of nature. As Satan was pun-
ished by God to an eternity in hell, so Prometheus
was condemned by Zeus to crucifixion and eternal tor-
ment by daily devouring of his liver by an eagle. To
be sure, the obvious objection to any such parallel is
that whereas the mythical rebel Prometheus was an
apparent benefactor of mankind, Milton’s rebel Satan
plots the downfall of mankind by tempting Eve and
subsequently Adam to disobedient consumption of the
apple from the tree of knowledge. However, something
may here depend on theological interpretation of the
Genesis myth. For it seems that, in ancient gnostic pa-
gan and Christian versions of the narrative, the myth-
ical creator of Eden and its human occupants was not
the supreme ruling spirit of the universe, but a local
demiurge intent on keeping his creation in ignorant
thrall to his arbitrary will. Thus, in The Apocryphon of
St John (one of the non-canonical gospels discovered
at Nag Hammadi in 1945), an explicit dialogue on the
Genesis narrative occurs between the apostle John and
Jesus the saviour in which the latter takes full respon-
sibility for encouraging Adam and Eve to eat of the
tree of knowledge by asserting “But I was the one who
induced them to eat” (Meyer, 1998, p. 175.) On this
ancient reading of Genesis, the original temptation
opened up a spiritually progressive route to knowl-
edge or wisdom (enabling freedom from the tyranny
of a false deity). Thus, Jesus of the New Testament
gospels appears as a teacher of the knowledge (logos,
or Word) of the true world-transcendent God which
aspires to replace and transcend the oppressive and
repressive law of the Old Testament Jehovah. (Gnos-
tic construal of the Genesis story us also evident in the
cinematic narrative of the 1998 movie Pleasantville;
see Carr, 2023b.)
Moreover, this gnostic take on the Genesis narra-
tive is also fairly evident in the poetic works of the
early modern English author and artist who was an ar-
dent admirer of Milton: namely, the visionary painter
and poet William Blake. Thus, in Blake’s somewhat
perplexing Prophetic books, some such overall gnostic
drift seems evident in the general construction and
dramatis personae of these complex narratives. On
the one hand, Blake’s Urizen (identifiable with the
oppressive conventional morality of church and state
and/or the cold rationality of Newtonian scientific
reason) resembles the repressive demiurge of gnostic
theology. On the other hand, such characters as Los
(Urthona), Luvah and/or Orc are expressive (more or
less respectively) of imagination, love and passion as
largely opposed to such cold reason. Of course, the re-
bellious powers and sentiments opposed to Urizen are
inspired more by the altruistic virtues of the canonical
gospel Jesus than by Satanic pride. But Blake famous-
ly observed in his Marriage of heaven and hell that
“Milton…was of the Devil’s party without knowing
it”. His own work (along with that of such contempo-
raries as Wordsworth, Coleridge and Shelley) plays a
significant part in fueling a new romantic literary sen-
sibility of individual independence, self-determination
David CARR
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
12 EV
and emancipation from the repressive political, reli
-
gious, economic and other influences and institutions
of both traditional (feudal) and modern (industrial and
capitalist) society and culture. To be sure, while the
literary genius of early romantics may well have been
expressive and supportive of the distinctively new
modern politics of freedom and democracy pioneered
by the likes of John Locke and Jean Jacques Rousseau,
it should not be forgotten that Blake and Wordsworth
were no less strongly opposed to the utilitarianism,
philistinism and human degradation that the new po-
litical and economic liberalism of industrial capitalist
exploitation trailed in its wake.
In this light, one cannot doubt that the new mod-
ern moral sensibility of earlier and later literary ro-
manticism (broadly speaking, the main drift of fiction,
drama and poetry from the late eighteenth century to
the end of the nineteenth century, if not beyond) seems
more sympathetic to the rebellious, self-assertive
and iconoclastic virtues of Milton’s Satan than to the
Christian virtues of humility and service to others pro-
moted by official eastern and western churches for the
purpose of encouraging lower feudal orders to know
and accept their subordinate place. Thus, despite all
other significant and interesting differences, such
major English nineteenth century novelists as Jane
Austen, the Bröntes, Charles Dickens, George Eliot,
Thomas Hardy (as well as their foreign counterparts)
are much concerned to promote an essentially roman-
tic project of liberation of their heroes and heroines
from various constraints of social convention, class
prejudice or patriarchy that prevent them from real-
izing their mature moral growth, individual potential
or ambition. To be sure, it cannot be denied that the
fictional worlds invented by these authors (in which
their various self-affirming characters pursue their
imagined destinies) are (even in the case of an evident
non-believer such as Hardy) also informed by moral
ideals and virtues of some Christian provenance. That
said, it is fairly evident, as early as Matthew Arnold’s
mid-nineteenth poem “Dover Beach”, that a major
cultural and literary break with the traditional Chris-
tian moral basis of western culture is looming on the
horizon.
Moreover, it seems plausible to trace the decisive
break with traditional western European subscrip-
tion to the moral authority, or truth of the Christian
gospels (at least, in literary terms) to the work of the
nineteenth century German philosopher Friedrich
Nietzsche. While it is customary to regard Nietzsche
as a founding father (perhaps along with Soren
Kierkegaard) of twentieth century existentialism, he is
no less aptly regarded as a philosophical spokesman of
nineteenth century romanticism (itself a main source
of much later existentialism). While it is also of consid-
erable present interest that Nietzsche has lately been
lauded as a type of virtue ethicist (Swanton, 2003), the
virtues that he extolls could hardly be further away
from the moral and theological virtues celebrated by
(for obvious example) such major Christian theologians
as St Thomas Aquinas. In short, Nietzsche’s virtues
are not at all the Christian virtues of love, humility
and selflessness. On the contrary, they are significantly
closer to Miltonian satanic (or perhaps, in the terms
of later romanticism, Byronic) virtues of self-asser-
tion, personal independence, revolutionary action, re-
sistance to imposed authority and individuality of ex-
pression, showing thus much disdain for humility or
servility of character. Indeed, Nietzsche’s contempt for
and dismissal of what he evidently considered to be the
pusillanimous and feeble character of the specifically
western Christian social morality of humility and self-
lessness could hardly be more evident:
Our weak, unmanly social concepts of good and evil
and their tremendous ascendancy over body and soul
have finally weakened all bodies and souls and snapped
the self-reliant, independent, unprejudiced men, the pil-
lars of a strong civilization. (Nietzsche, 2012, p. 163)
Indeed, it is not merely that Nietzschean virtues
seem significantly satanic, but that they are invoked
and celebrated to the end of opposition to Satan’s very
own enemy, namely, the Christian God, whose final
demise was also famously pronounced by Nietzsche.
For many, of course, such radical departure from or
opposition to received Christian faith and morality
will be sufficient to dismiss the Nietzschean perspec-
tive as false, immoral and even demonic. In this light,
the influence of Nietzsche’s satanically virtuous Über-
mensch on the toxic twentieth century Nazi ideology
will also no doubt spring to mind. That said, aside
from his formative influence on the mid-twentieth
century philosophy and fictional literature of existen-
tialism, it is hard to think of a major literary figure
of early to middle years of that century who was not
influenced by some reading of Nietzsche, including,
amongst many others, James Joyce, Henrik Ibsen, D.
H. Lawrence, George Bernard Shaw, Eugene O’Neill,
Oscar Wilde, W. B. Yeats, Thomas Mann, Hermann
Hesse, Andre Gide and Albert Camus. Many new lit-
erary traditions (such as stream of consciousness fic-
tion, the neo-symbolist literature of existentialism and
Editorial
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
13 EV
new social realist fiction) were also undoubtedly influ
-
enced by the problematization of traditional Christian
morality of the new twentieth century climate of secu-
larism, to which Darwin and Marx, as well as Nietzsche,
clearly contributed. However, a large proportion of
such post-Nietzschean literature is aptly construed as
neo-romantic by virtue of its significant concern with
themes of the human search for authentic identity,
self determination and liberation from the shackles of
convention pioneered by nineteenth century forbears.
Thus, for example, the (especially female) protagonists
of D. H. Lawrence are much exercised with the issue
of escaping traditional patriarchal gender or sexu-
al constraints in a way that is not at all dissimilar in
spirit from the aspirations of Charlotte Brönte’s Jane
Eyre. Still, it may be that the Nietzschean quest for
the uncompromising honesty and integrity of personal
independence and authenticity is best captured by the
declaration (as well as the actions) of Dr. Stockman in
Ibsen’s Enemy of the people, that “the strongest man is
he who stands most alone”.
At all events, this abundance of past and more re-
cent fictional literature serves only to compound the
immense difficulties in the way of efforts to discern
any clear moral compass for human moral development
via primary or exclusive attention to human character
in the rich heritage of literary tradition. It cannot be
doubted that much (if not all) ancient and modern
imaginative literature has often primarily sought to
plumb the psychological and moral depths and com-
plexities of character in a potentially infinite range of
individual and social contexts and circumstances. How-
ever, the greatest, most memorable and enduring of
such literature has often been just as if not more con-
cerned to explore the frequent ambivalence and conflict
of such character and can rarely be taken (as aesthetic
formalists are wont to complain) to provide certain or
unequivocable advice of much direct relevance or appli-
cation to everyday human life. Indeed, we are all too of-
ten shown how agents of many admirable qualities (such
as Homer’s Achilles) can be capable of morally bad or
squalid conduct and those of weak, corrupt or deplorable
qualities (such as Sydney Carton in Dickens’ A Tale of
Two Cities) may yet be redeemed by actions of morally
positive or altruistic conduct. Thus, however sympa-
thetic we may be towards the desire of Shakespeare’s
Hamlet (perhaps the most conflicted and ambivalent
of all literary characters) for revenge on Claudius, it
might well seem ill-advised to endorse his final mur-
derous expression of this sentiment in similar circum-
stances (even if it might make any sense to speak here
of similar circumstances). Likewise, however much
we might admire Milton’s Satan for his impressive
courage and heroism (which the poet also shows to be
mixed with other morally less desirable qualities), we
might, at the very least, want to question the morality
of the ends to which such qualities are directed. In
any case, whether we finally judge such characters to
be morally good or bad, right or wrong, will ultimately
depend on moral values that we bring to such fictions
rather than derive from them.
5. Conclusion: art is not life
While we have lately taken modern aesthetic for-
malism to task on the grounds of its misguided con-
fusion between, or reduction of, artistic to aesthetic
significance, we are nevertheless now better placed
to comprehend the real point behind formalist or
aestheticist resistance to artistic moralism or other
instrumental construal of the ultimate ends or pur-
poses of art. To be sure, insofar as extreme aesthetic
formalism (of, as it were, art for art’s sake) has often
appeared to hold that genuine artistic appreciation
must be exclusively focused on the intrinsic formal
or aesthetic properties of artworks, it would seem to
confine all significant art to (perhaps non-cognitive)
entertainment or distraction. Thus, it precludes the
prospect of much real human instruction or learning
from literary or other art. But this clearly cannot be
right. In the first place, as our second prefatory quote
from Northrop Frye indicates, this risks emphasis
on the integrity of fictions to the exclusion of their
seriousness. In the second place, however, it also fa-
tally ignores the crucial distinction between the lan-
guage of history and other descriptive human literary
contexts or purposes and its more philosophical de-
ployment in poetry that Aristotle draws in our first
prefatory quote from his Poetics (a work that may also
be fairly considered the foundational text of western
aesthetic theory).
To be sure, Aristotle’s distinction is perfectly in line
with a very basic tenet of much post-Kantian formalist
and other modern aesthetic theory which aims to ob-
serve a quite fundamental distinction between the lan-
guage or semantics of ordinary descriptive discourse
(which is also employed in history or the sciences to
report the contingent facts of past or present human
experience) and the literary or other artistic language
or semantics of human imaginative creation of, for ex-
ample, tragedy or other art. Briefly, in the terms of
modern analytical (post-Fregean) philosophy and log-
David CARR
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
14 EV
ic, the fictional language or narrative of imaginative
artworks is intensional (not to be confused with in
-
tentional) rather than extensional. That is to say that,
while the propositions that we encounter in a novel,
such as Jane Austen’s Emma or Charles Dickens’
Oliver Twist, have evident sense, or meaning, within
such fictional contexts, they do not (unlike the prop-
ositions of ordinary, historical or scientific discourse)
have any reference to events in the actual world be-
yond such contexts. Thus, the narratives in which
such propositions or (pseudo) statements occur are
entirely the constructs or inventions of human imagi-
nation and should not be confused with the real world
of empirical experience. Moreover, while this point
might seem so trivial as to be hardly worth making, it
is of quite wide-ranging educational import. To begin
with, while most people of mature years will have lit-
tle difficulty distinguishing the non-literal or fictional
narratives of fairy story or Greek mythology from the
purportedly factual reports of history or science, much
modern mischief continues to be caused by failure to
distinguish what are clearly the myths of past religious
traditions (perhaps especially of the Old and New Tes-
taments of the Christian Bible) from actual historical
record. At all events, there can here be little doubt that
this basic distinction of the non-referential language
of art and fiction from forms of referential discourse
lies at the heart of latter-day aesthetic formalist objec-
tion to any and all attempts to derive moral or other
lessons from imaginative narratives.
That said, it seems no less mistaken to hold (as,
at least, more extreme of such aestheticists appear to
have held) that, because fictional narratives have no
direct external reference, there can be little or nothing
of any wider worldly value or relevance to be gained
from them. Indeed, this is quite evidently not the po-
sition of Aristotle in our introductory quote, where he
quite explicitly affirms that “poetry is something more
philosophic and of graver import than history”. Indeed,
it might here be noted that, while some distinguished
modern advocates of the educational significance of
fictional literature (such as Iris Murdoch 1970, 1227 )
seem to have held that narrative fiction has more hu-
man relevance the closer it approximates to real life,
it would to the contrary appear that the highest of lit-
erary regard has more often been accorded to works
of evidently pure fantasy (such as Sophocles’ King
Oedipus, Milton’s Paradise lost and Shakespeare’s The
tempest; not to mention the parables of Jesus) at the
very farthest remove from any actual (empirical) hu-
man experience. This, to be sure, clearly underscores
the general danger of failing to distinguish the real
human significance of imaginative fiction from that
of literal description. For while generations of readers
have greatly profited by way of profound human in-
sight from Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels or Cervantes’ Don
Quixote (without the least illusion as to the non-liter-
al or figurative character of such stories), it is evident
that many more have quite failed to appreciate the real
human import or significance of the no less fictional
narratives of Genesis or Kings by literal readings of
these biblical books.
But then, how can stories or narratives that clear-
ly do not report on or refer directly to actual human
events or affairs be said to have meaning outside or be-
yond their distraction or entertainment value? On the
face of it, Aristotle’s more particular response to this
question (at least, as applied to ancient Greek drama),
in terms of the cathartic power of tragedy to purge or
purify human emotions of pity or fear, may appear less
than helpful. While it may be true up to a point that
audiences are often moved in this fashion by tragedies
or other literary narratives, this does not seem to be
the case of all such works (though it would also appear
that other works are instructive in ways that tragedy is
not). Thus, the more generally compelling Aristotelian
point evidently lies in his understanding of the lan-
guage of poetry or other literary art (as distinct from
that of history) as concerned with the universalization
or typification more than description of human actions
or affairs. Following Aristotle’s lead, the great twenti-
eth century literary critic Northrop Frye usefully dis-
tinguishes the language and idioms of imaginative lit-
erature from the descriptive discourses of science and
other more literal enterprises as “myths of concern”
(Frye, 1974). It should also be clear here that Frye is
here strictly faithful to Aristotle’s own use of the term
myth to denote the stories or narratives of his purely
imaginative and fictional poetry. In these terms, while
such purely fictional constructs can have no direct ref-
erence to human actions or affairs (and it would be a
dire mistake to assume they have such application),
they may yet be potent sources of human instruction
or education by way of the characteristic poetic devices
of metaphor, analogy, parable, allegory, satire, irony
and other imaginative, semantic and conceptual tropes
and idioms that are no less clearly vehicles of insight
into the human condition. So, while it would be mere
folly to construe Swift’s Gulliver’s travels, Cervantes’
Don Quixote or Kafka’s The trial as reporting on actu-
al historical events, we may yet stand to learn much
about human folly as such from the large and small
Editorial
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
15 EV
characters of Swift’s Gulliver, about true human wis
-
dom and humanity from Quixote’s apparent madness,
and about the potential dystopian nightmare of human
bureaucracy from the fictional fate of K in Kafka’s
frightening parable.
With regard to particular present concerns about
moral learning from literature, then, we clearly need
to distinguish two different respects or levels in which
fictional literature may be implicated or embroiled in
moral (or, more specifically, character education). On
the one hand, we do need to take on board aestheticist,
or formalist, caution against drawing any clear directly
applicable conclusions for everyday practical conduct
from imaginative poetry or literature. Apart from the
consideration that the characters of fictional narratives
are just precisely characters in stories (so that the con-
duct attributed to them can have real point or purpose
only in the context of such stories), we have seen that
no very reliable moral conclusions can be drawn from
either real or fictional perceptions of human charac-
ter and that any such judgements that we may apply
to them must derive from other sources of reflection.
Indeed, as the introductory quote from Frye implies, in-
sofar as the primary aim of fiction or other art is not to
describe the actual world but to construct imaginative
possibilities, it is actually liable to artistic failure if it
explicitly professes any non-artistic and propagandist
function (as in the case perhaps of much so-called social
realist painting). Still, all this said, any extreme formal-
ist or aestheticist denial of the moral significance or val-
ue of fictional literature is no less clearly belied by the
Aristotelian distinction of the philosophical purposes of
poetry from the descriptive function of history. Thus,
while the heroic Satan of Milton’s Paradise lost (or oth-
er literary figures) may afford us little direct practical
guidance for conduct in the non-fictional world, this
fictional character, as well as others, can nevertheless
provide rich food for philosophical thought on the wider
and more general conceptual or normative contours of
potentially human character and conduct. This might
well be put by saying that although we would not be
well-advised to seek practical instruction on character
and conduct from Milton’s Satan, one may yet regard
Paradise lost as a potent source of education concern-
ing the wider and more principled normative and moral
contours of human life. In this regard, indeed, such
more philosophical, objective or disinterested acquain-
tance with great literary works may also serve to avoid
the potentially lethal hazards of currently vaunted per-
sonal role-modelling approaches to moral and charac-
ter education, which clearly risk exposing the young or
gullible to quite the wrong sorts of undesirable influ-
ence from others (Carr, 2023a). But while Milton’s mas-
terpiece may persuade us that Satan has virtues of some
such loose designation, we may therefore also hope to
gain from the wider context and scope of this powerful
narrative (and by comparison of this character and his
story with those of other great fictions) a broader or
more educated vision of the limits and defects of human
character and conduct as such.
References
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy,
33 (124), 1-19. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3749051
Aristóteles. (1941a). De Poetica. In R. McKeon (Ed.), The basic
works of Aristotle (pp. 1455-1487). Random House.
Aristóteles. (1941b). The Nicomachean ethics. In R. McKeon (Ed.),
The basic works of Aristotle (pp. 927-1112). Random House.
Best, D. (1982). The aesthetic and the artistic. Philosophy, 57
(221), 357-372. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819100050968
Carr, D. (1999). Art, practical knowledge and aesthetic objectivity.
Ratio, 12 (3), 240-256. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9329.00090
Carr, D. (2007). Character in teaching British Journal of Educa-
tional Studies, 55 (4), 369-389. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-
8527.2007.00386.x
Carr, D. (2017). Literature, rival conceptions of virtue and moral
education. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 51 (2), 1-16. https://
doi.org/10.5406/jaesteduc.51.2.0001
Carr, D. (2023a). The hazards of role-modelling for the education
of moral and/or virtuous character. Philosophical Inquiry in
Education, 30 (1), 68-79. https://journals.sfu.ca/pie/index.php/
pie/article/view/1529
Carr, D. (2023b). Love, knowledge and freedom in Pleasantville, re-
ligious scripture and wider western literature. Religion and the
Arts, 27 (3), 345-366. https://doi.org/10.1163/15685292-02703002
Carroll, N. (1986). Art and interaction. Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism, 45 (1), 57-68. https://doi.org/10.2307/430466
Carroll, N. (1996). Moderate moralism. British Journal of Aesthet-
ics, 36 (3), 223-37. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjaesthetics/36.3.223
Carroll, N. (1998). Moderate moralism versus moderate au-
tonomism. British Journal of Aesthetics, 38 (4), 419-24. https://
doi.org/10.1093/bjaesthetics/38.4.419
Durkheim, E. (1973). Moral education. Free Press of Glencoe.
Frye, N. (1974). The stubborn structure: Essays on criticism and
society. Methuen.
Gaut, B. (1998). The ethical criticism of art. In J. Levison (Ed.),
Aesthetics and ethics: Essays on the intersection (pp. 182-203).
Cambridge University Press.
Geach, P. T. (1977). The virtues. Cambridge University Press.
Hepburn, R. (1984). Contemporary aesthetics and the neglect of
natural beauty. In Wonder and other essays: Eight studies in
aesthetics and neighbouring fields. Edinburgh University Press.
Kohlberg, L. (1984). Essays on moral development: Volume 1.
Harper Row.
Lamarque, P. (1996). Fictional points of view. Clarendon Press.
Lamarque, P., & Olsen, S. H. (1990). Truth, fiction and literature: A
philosophical perspective. Clarendon Press.
Lickona, T. (2004). Character matters. Touchstone.
McFee, G. (2005). The artistic and the aesthetic. British Journal of
Aesthetics, 45 (4), 368-387. https://doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayi049
David CARR
Revista Española de Pedagogía
year 82, n. 287, January-April 2024, 5-16
16 EV
MacIntyre, A. C. (1981). After virtue. Notre Dame Press.
Meyer, M. (Ed.). (1998). The secret book of John. In The secret gos-
pels of Jesus (pp. 129-183). Harper San Francisco.
Milton, J. (2005). Paradise lost Arcturus Publications.
Murdoch, I. (1970). The sovereignty of the good. Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Murdoch, I. (1993). Metaphysics as a guide to morals. Penguin Books.
Murdoch, I. (1997). The sublime and the beautiful revisited. In I.
Murdoch (Ed.), Existentialists and mystics: Writings on philos-
ophy and literature (pp. 261-286). Chatto and Windus.
Nietzsche, F. (2012). Daybreak: Thoughts on the prejudices of
morality (M. Clark & B. Leiter, Eds.). Cambridge University Press.
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgement of the child. Free Press.
Ryan, K., & Bohlin, K. E. (2003). Building character in schools:
Practical ways to bring moral instruction to life. Jossey Bass.
Stecker, R. (2005). The interaction of ethical and aesthetic val-
ue. British Journal of Aesthetics, 45 (2), 138-150. https://doi.
org/10.1093/aesthj/ayi016
Swanton. C. (2003). Virtue ethics: A pluralistic view. Oxford Uni-
versity Press.
Szutta, N. (2019). Exemplarist moral theory - some pros and cons.
Journal of Moral Education, 48 (3), 280-290. https://doi.org/10
.1080/03057240.2019.1589435
Zabzebski, L. (2010). Exemplarist virtue theory. Metaphilosophy,
41 (1-2), 41-57.
Zabzebski, L. (2013). Moral exemplars in theory and practice. The-
ory and Research in Education, 11 (2), 192-306. https://doi.
org/10.1177/1477878513485177
Author’s biography
David Carr. Emeritus Professor of the University of
Edinburgh and was until recently Professor of Ethics and
Education at the University of Birmingham (UK) Jubi-
lee Centre for the Study of Character and Virtues. He is
author of four books, editor or co-editor of several major
collections of essays on philosophy and/or education and
his papers have appeared in such journals as Mind, Phi-
losophy, Philosophical Quarterly, Proceedings of the Aris-
totelian Society, Philosophical Studies, Journal of Value
Inquiry, British Journal of Aesthetics, Educational Theory
and Oxford Educational Review. Much of his work has ex-
plored aspects of virtue ethics and, more recently, the im-
pact of literature and various other arts on moral character.