THIS VERSION MAY CONTAIN INACCURATE OR INCOMPLETE PAGE NUMBERS. PLEASE CONSULT
THE PRINT OR ONLINE DATABASE VERSIONS FOR THE PROPER CITATION INFORMATION.
101
NOTE
HOW TO GET AWAY WITH COPYRIGHT
INFRINGEMENT: MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE
SAM CLAFLIN
1
CONTENTS
I. INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................ 102
II. BACKGROUND ............................................................................................ 104
A. History ............................................................................................ 104
i. Foundations of Copyright Law with Respect to Music ............ 104
ii. Music Sampling and Copyright ............................................... 105
B. The Fair Use Doctrine .................................................................... 107
i. Fair Use and Appropriation Art ................................................ 110
III. A CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVE ON MUSIC SAMPLING AND FAIR USE:
ESTATE OF SMITH V. CASH MONEY RECORDS, INC. ................................ 113
A. Background ..................................................................................... 113
B. Analysis An In-Depth Look at the Court’s Fair Use
Approach in Estate of Smith ........................................................ 114
i. Factor One .............................................................................. 115
ii. Factor Two ............................................................................. 118
iii. Factor Three ........................................................................... 118
iv. Factor Four ............................................................................. 119
IV. MODEL APPLICATION OF FAIR USE FOR MUSIC SAMPLING CASES ........... 120
A. Factor One: Purpose and Character of the Use ............................. 122
B. Factor Two: Nature of the Copyrighted Work ................................ 123
C. Factor Three: Amount and Substantiality of the Portion Used ...... 123
D. Factor Four: Effect on the Market ................................................. 124
CONCLUSION ................................................................................................... 129
1
I thank Professor Wendy J. Gordon for her immense help with this Note. She played an
invaluable role in its development and execution, from start to finish.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
102 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
I. INTRODUCTION
Music sampling is integral to the genres of hip hop and electronic music. Hip
hop and electronic musicians make their art, in part, by repurposing excerpts of
other artists music.
2
Musicians who employ sampling are presently required to
obtain consensual licenses for each use of a pre-existing song and to pay all the
fees associated with licensing.
3
The present state of the law has thus created a
significant barrier to entry and exorbitant creation cost for musicians making
sample-based music.
4
This is especially true because sampling can implicate
both musical work and sound recording copyrights, meaning that an artist may
need to obtain two licenses to legally use a sample.
5
Further, the more affordable
compulsory licensing framework that applies to cover songs does not govern
sampling.
6
The availability of compulsory licenses for cover songs encourages
reusing entire melodies, but the unavailability of compulsory licenses for
sampling discourages reusing only partial melodies and sound snippets from
existing songs. One should question why an artist can obtain a compulsory
license to reuse an entire melody, but cannot obtain a compulsory license to
reuse only part of a melody or select sounds from an existing recording.
7
Basic
fairness should ensure no musician faces disproportionate barriers from
copyright law simply by virtue of her preferred genre. Presently, however, some
untold number of fledgling sample-based musicians cannot release their art
2
See, e.g., Rebecca Haithcoat, Top 10 EDM/Rap Collaborations of All Time, BILLBOARD
(Aug. 15, 2014), https://www.billboard.com/articles/columns/the-juice/6221465/top-10-
edmrap-collaborations-of-all-time [https://perma.cc/WF7Z-ABD3]; see also Digital Music
Sampling: Creativity or Criminality?, NPR (Jan. 28, 2011, 1:00 PM),
https://www.npr.org/2011/01/28/133306353/Digital-Music-Sampling-Creativity-Or-
Criminality [https://perma.cc/E5AG-2LMK].
3
See Alex Holz, How You Can Clear Cover Songs, Samples, and Handle Public Domain
Works, ASCAP (Jan. 26, 2011),
https://www.ascap.com/playback/2011/01/features/limelight.aspx.
4
See Jimmy Ness, The Queen of Sample Clearance: An Interview with Deborah Mannis-
Gardner, FORBES (Feb. 19, 2016, 8:00 AM),
https://www.forbes.com/sites/passionoftheweiss/2016/02/19/the-queen-of-sample-clearance-
an-interview-with-deborah-mannis-gardner/#60efcbc64e18 [https://perma.cc/4EV7-GEFE].
5
Holz, supra note 3. But see VMG Salsoul, LLC v. Ciccone, 824 F.3d 871, 874 (9th Cir.
2016).
6
By cover songs I refer to the practice of [r]ecord[ing] or perform[ing] a new version
of (a song) originally performed by someone else. Cover, LEXICO.COM,
https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/cover [https://perma.cc/8W5V-BCTP].
7
Professor Gordon was instrumental in helping me articulate this idea. See Robert M.
Vrana, Note, The Remix Artists Catch-22: A Proposal for Compulsory Licensing for
Transformative, Sampling-Based Music, 68 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 811, 828-30 (2011). Using
a sample and performing a cover are arguably quite similar from a use-of-intellectual-property
standpoint. Nonetheless, the Copyright Act of 1976 carves out a special mechanical-licensing
framework for covers that does not apply to samples. See id.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 103
without paying licensing fees that only more-established artists can afford.
8
Clearing a single sample can cost hundreds of thousands of dollars.
9
Losing a
copyright infringement lawsuit for failing to clear a sample can cost
considerably more.
10
Thankfully, the Copyright Act of 1976 (the Act)
11
already provides a
solution for sample-based music, albeit one that has been woefully
underutilized. The fair use exception laid out in § 107 of the Act applies to
transformative, socially valuable second uses, and music sampling often seems
to be an appropriate example of such use.
12
Yet, despite sampling being an
ostensibly suitable fair use candidate, litigants and courts have been reluctant to
embrace sampling as fair use.
13
In 2017, the U.S. District Court for the Southern
District of New York became the first court to rule in a defendant’s favor on a
non-parody fair use defense in the music sampling context.
14
This Note will describe why more courts could, and should, embrace music
sampling as a fair use of copyrighted material in the context of both sound
recordings and musical works, for which the fair use analyses should be nearly
identical.
15
Music sampling is a prime candidate for fair use in many instances,
based on both the language of § 107 and fair use jurisprudence.
16
Moreover, a
fair use exception for music sampling would not detract from the constitutional
goals of U.S. copyright law. On the contrary, such an exception would serve to
promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts
17
by allowing more musicians
to create and share their art. In advancing these arguments, I draw comparisons
between fair use in the music-sampling context and the visual-art context
8
See id. at 849-50.
9
See Ness, supra note 4.
10
See Peter Relic, The 25 Most Notorious Uncleared Samples in Rap History, COMPLEX
(Apr. 22, 2013), http://www.complex.com/music/2013/04/the-25-most-notorious-uncleared-
samples-in-rap-history/ [https://perma.cc/WAY8-GK89].
11
For further discussion of the Copyright Act and a discussion of the fair use doctrine, see
infra Part II.
12
17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012); see generally Wendy J. Gordon, Fair Use as Market Failure:
A Structural and Economic Analysis of the Betamax Case and Its Predecessors, 82 COLUM.
L. REV. 1600, 1602-03 (1982).
13
Importantly though, no case has expressly foreclosed the possibility that music sampling
may fall under fair use. Even in Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. Dimension Films, 410 F.3d 792 (6th
Cir. 2005), in which Judge Guy issued his famous get-a-license-or-do-not-sample edict, the
courts rejection of a de minimis exception expressly left the door open for a fair use
argument. Id. at 801-02.
14
See Estate of Smith v. Cash Money Records, Inc., 253 F. Supp. 3d 737, 749-52
(S.D.N.Y. 2017).
15
See infra Part IV.
16
See id.
17
U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
104 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
where courts have been more accepting of creative borrowing as fair use.
18
Specifically, I compare music sampling to visual appropriation art.
Part II provides a basic introduction to copyright law with respect to music,
the fair use doctrine, and the practices of music sampling and appropriation art,
the knowledge of which is fundamental to understanding Parts III-V.
19
Part III
analyzes a 2017 case that embraced music sampling as a fair use of copyrighted
material.
20
Part IV provides a general, model approach to applying the fair use
doctrine in music-sampling cases, drawing on Parts I-III.
21
Finally, Part V
concludes by summarizing Parts I-IV, circling back to some of the policy
arguments that make this topic so important.
22
II. BACKGROUND
To understand why music sampling should often constitute fair use, one must
first understand the fundamentals of copyright law, the historical relationship
between copyright law and music sampling, and the basics of the fair use
doctrineincluding fair uses application to creative borrowing in other
contexts. These subjects form the proper analytical framework for applying the
fair use doctrine to music sampling.
A. History
i. Foundations of Copyright Law with Respect to Music
The United States Constitution, Article I, Section 8, Clause 8 empowers
Congress to legislate copyright and patent statutes.
23
The aim of this clause,
known as the Copyright Clause, is to incentivize authors to create by granting
authors limited monopoly right[s] over their creations.
24
The underlying goal
of this incentive scheme is explicit in the Copyright Clause, namely, to promote
the Progress of Science and the useful Arts.
25
Over time the common law
fleshed out the requirements for copyright protection, and now the threshold
requirements for copyrightability are spelled out in § 102(a) of the Act:
Copyright protection subsists, in accordance with this title, in original works of
authorship fixed in any tangible medium of expression, now known or later
developed, from which they can be perceived, reproduced, or otherwise
communicated, either directly or with the aid of a machine or device.
26
18
See, e.g., Cariou v. Prince, 714 F.3d 694 (2d Cir. 2013); Blanch v. Koons, 467 F.3d 244
(2d Cir. 2006).
19
See infra Part II.
20
See infra Part III.
21
See infra Part IV.
22
See infra Part V.
23
MARSHALL A. LEAFFER, UNDERSTANDING COPYRIGHT LAW 6 (6th ed. 2014).
24
Id.
25
U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8.
26
17 U.S.C. § 102(a) (2012).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 105
As far as the music industry is concerned, there are two main forms of
copyrightable subject matter: musical works and sound recordings.
27
A musical
work includes both the words of a song and its instrumental component, and
might be fixed, for instance, in the medium of musical notation written on
paper.
28
A sound recording, on the other hand is a captured performance, and
might be fixed, for example, in a phonorecord or digital audio file.
29
In the music
context, any medium in which a sound recording is embodied will most often
contain that sound recordings underlying musical work as well.
30
In other
words, when a consumer listens to her favorite song via a digital audio file, both
a sound recording copyright and its underlying musical work copyright are fixed
in that digital audio file.
[T]he owner of a sound recording copyright enjoys different exclusive rights
than the copyright owner of the musical . . . work captured in the sound
recording.
31
Specifically, the copyright owner of a sound recording may not
control its performance, while the copyright owner of a . . . musical . . . work
enjoys a full performance right.
32
This Note focuses on two exclusive rights
copyright owners of musical works and sound recordings hold in common: (1)
to reproduce the copyrighted work in copies or phonorecords, and (2) to
prepare derivative works based upon the copyrighted work.
33
The former is
self-explanatory, but the phrase derivative work is a term of art. The Act
defines derivative work as a work based upon one or more preexisting works,
such as a . . . musical arrangement, . . . sound recording, art reproduction,
abridgment, condensation, or any other form in which a work may be recast,
transformed, or adapted.
34
The discussion of music sampling and copyright law
that follows draws on the above concepts, terminology, and aims of the
copyright regime.
ii. Music Sampling and Copyright
Music sampling has been defined as mechanically or digitally using a portion
of a previous sound recording in a new recording.
35
Importantly, sampling also
encompasses copying sound in order to use the lyrics or pattern of notes from an
underlying musical work.
36
In this Note, sampling refers to both of these
27
See LEAFFER, supra note 23, at 141-44.
28
Id. at 141.
29
Id. at 142.
30
See id.
31
Id.
32
Id. (citing 17 U.S.C. § 114 (2012)).
33
17 U.S.C. § 106 (2012).
34
Id. § 101.
35
Robert M. Szymanski, Audio Pastiche: Digital Sampling, Intermediate Copying, Fair
Use, 3 UCLA ENT. L. REV. 271, 275 (1996) (quoting Robert G. Sugarman & Joseph P.
Salvo, Whose Rights? Sampling Gives Law a New Mix, NATL L.J., Nov. 11, 1991, at 21).
36
Professor Gordon was instrumental in helping me articulate this thought in this way.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
106 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
approaches.
37
The used portion of existing copyrighted material, called a
“‘sample, is generally short, ranging from less than one second to
approximately twenty-five seconds.
38
Sampling empowers artists to isolate
. . . specific aspects, and even particular instruments, [from] an existing musical
recording.
39
Once extracted, an artist can alter a samples sonic
characteristics by, for example, changing its pitch or tempo, or putting it on a
continuous loop.
40
The artist can then cut and paste the sample into a new song
in which the sample may function like an instrument.
41
As one popular example,
consider Aviciis 2011 hit Levels, which incorporates a vocal sample from
Etta Jamess 1962 single, Somethings Got a Hold on Me.
42
Sampling can reduce studio and musician costs, and it can relieve the
pressure placed on producers and sound engineers to achieve the right
sound.
43
That much is true if the artist can afford a license. Because sampling
amounts to literal copying of a sound recording, and by extension, at least in the
music context, often amounts to literal copying of a musical work, sample-based
musicians have faced intellectual-property challenges since samplings
inception.
44
One view, exemplified by the Sixth Circuit, is that sampling is clear-
cut infringement of a copyright holders reproduction and derivative work rights,
leaving a sample-based musician with no real choice but to clear a sample
through licensing.
45
In the Ninth Circuit, however, courts have recognized at least one limited safe
haven for sample-based musicians. In Newton v. Diamond, the United States
Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit held that a de minimis exception applies
to claims of infringement of a copyrighted musical work.
46
In that case, the
defendants, the Beastie Boys, had sampled a three-note flute sequence for which
they obtained a license in the sound recording but not the underlying musical
37
Note that not all sound recordings that a musician might sample contain underlying
musical works. For instance, a musician might sample a sound recording of animal
vocalizations recorded in nature. Such a recording may not contain an underlying
composition. For purposes of this Note, I refer to the digital sampling of songs, i.e., sound
recordings of popular songs, which do contain underlying musical works.
38
Szymanski, supra note 35, at 276 (citing E. Scott Johnson, Note, Protecting Distinctive
Sounds: The Challenge of Digital Sampling, 2 J.L. & TECH. 273, 274 (1987)).
39
Id. (alteration in original).
40
Id.
41
Id. at 277.
42
See Aviciis Levels Sample of Etta Jamess Somethings Got a Hold on Me, WHO
SAMPLED, https://www.whosampled.com/sample/111866/Avicii-Levels-Etta-James-
Something%27s-Got-a-Hold-on-Me/ [https://perma.cc/F4UG-48V9].
43
Szymanski, supra note 35, at 276 (citing Johnson, supra note 38, at 275).
44
See VMG Salsoul, LLC v. Ciccone, 824 F.3d 871, 877 (9th Cir. 2016); see also
Szymanski, supra note 35, at 273.
45
See, e.g., Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. Dimension Films, 410 F.3d 792, 801-02 (6th Cir.
2005).
46
Newton v. Diamond, 388 F.3d 1189, 1193 (9th Cir. 2004).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 107
work.
47
Thus, the case concerned alleged infringement of the musical work
copyright via digital sampling and did not concern the sound recording
copyright.
48
The court reasoned that if the average audience would not
recognize the appropriation because it is meager and fragmentary,
repurposing of a musical work via sampling can be de minimis, and therefore
non-infringing.
49
In 2016, the same court held that the de minimis exception also
applies to claims of infringement of a copyrighted sound recording.
50
A finding of de minimis copying appears to be the only way to absolve an
artist who has not obtained the necessary license(s) prior to sampling, and the de
minimis exception remains unavailable in the Sixth Circuit, as noted above.
51
But litigants and the courts have neglected an entire section of the Act. Whether
the fair use doctrine could similarly absolve sample-based artists remains a more
open question.
B. The Fair Use Doctrine
Section 107 of the Act provides that certain fair uses of copyrighted
material are not an infringement of copyright.
52
In addition to providing a
short, non-exhaustive list of purposes that indicate a use may be fair, Congress
included four factors for courts and the public to consider.
53
In numerical order,
the four factors are: (1) the purpose and character of the use, including its
commerciality; (2) the nature of the copyrighted work; (3) the amount and
substantiality of the portion used relative to the copyrighted work; and (4) the
uses effect on the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work.
54
The
Supreme Court has indicated that no single factor is dispositive, and has
generally avoided assumption in the fair use context this is to say that fair use
categorically entails a very fact-specific inquiry.
55
The first factor inquiry asks whether the new work adds something new, with
a further purpose or different character, altering the first with new expression,
meaning, or message; it asks, in other words, whether and to what extent the new
work is transformative.’”
56
Since its appearance in Campbell v. Acuff-Rose
Music, Inc., the transformative use doctrine has come to dominate fair use
47
Id. at 1190.
48
See id.
49
Salsoul, 824 F.3d at 878 (describing the courts earlier application of the de minimis
exception in Newton, 388 F.3d at 1193).
50
Salsoul, 824 F.3d at 887.
51
See Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. Dimension Films, 410 F.3d 792, 798 (6th Cir. 2005).
52
17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012).
53
Id.
54
Id.
55
See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 577 (1994).
56
Id. at 579 (emphasis added).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
108 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
jurisprudence.
57
Paradigmatic examples of transformative use in the major fair
use cases include the parodic alteration of lyrics from a famous romantic
ballad,
58
and the reprinting, in reduced size, of old Grateful Dead concert posters
in a book about the Grateful Dead.
59
The other prong of the first factor inquiry is commerciality.
60
If a work is
commercial, that commerciality cuts against fair use.
61
However, courts
generally give[] little substantive weight to commercialityin fact, the bulk
of decisions finding fair use have involved commercial, rather than
noncommercial, uses.
62
As transformativeness increases, the less will be the
significance of other factors, like commercialism, that may weigh against a
finding of fair use.
63
Transformativeness truly is paramount.
Factor two directs attention to the nature of the copyrighted work.
64
The
second factor generally recognizes a greater need to disseminate factual works
than works of fiction or fantasy.
65
Music is at the core of copyrightable subject
matter, meaning factor two will almost invariably cut against the defendant in
cases concerning the defendants use of the plaintiffs music.
66
The third factor directs us to examine the amount and substantiality of the
portion used in relation to the copyrighted work as a whole.
67
Under factor
three, copying may not be excused simply because it is insubstantial with respect
to the would-be infringing work; as Judge Learned Hand cogently remarked,
no plagiarist can excuse the wrong by showing how much of his work he did
not pirate.’”
68
Though section 107 ‘directs a comparison between the amount
taken and the copyrighted work as a whole,’ courts sometimes do apply factor
three to examine the portion used relative to the overall size of the accused’s
work.
69
Because factor three concerns the amount and substantiality of the
portion used, it is necessarily a highly fact-specific inquiry.
57
PAUL GOLDSTEIN, GOLDSTEIN ON COPYRIGHT § 12.2.2, at 12:33 (3d ed. 2005 & Supp.
2019).
58
Campbell, 510 U.S. at 569-71.
59
Bill Graham Archives v. Dorling Kindersley Ltd., 448 F.3d 605, 607 (2d Cir. 2006).
60
17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012).
61
See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579.
62
GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:28.
63
Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579.
64
Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 563 (1985).
65
Id.
66
Campbell, 510 U.S. at 586.
67
Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 564.
68
Id. at 565.
69
GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:55 (citing Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 565-66)
(emphasis added).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 109
Factor four take[s] account not only of [market] harm to the original but also
of harm to the market for derivative works.
70
One method courts use to assess
market effect is to ask if the contested use is complementary to the protected
work, which is more likely to be fair use, as opposed to a market substitute for
the protected work, which is less likely to be fair use.
71
An empirical study of
courts practical approaches to the fourth factor concludes that courts have very
rarely made specific factual findings under the factor. Instead, the vast majority
of the opinions simply conducted what amounted to little more than an
unstructured and conclusory rule-of-reason analysis.
72
The Supreme Court has stated that factors one and four are the most integral
to fair use analysis, weighing more heavily than factors two or three.
73
Professor
Barton Beebe determined that of the 141 [analyzed] opinions that found that
factor four disfavored fair use, 140 found no fair use.
74
Another important
aspect of the fair use defense is that courts have consistently treated fair use as
an affirmative defense, which puts the burden of establishing fair use on the
alleged infringer.
75
Additionally, courts remain mindful of policy concerns in
applying the four factors, and fair use can excuse an otherwise-infringing use if
the social benefit outweighs the loss to the copyright owner
76
and if some other
circumstance, such as market failure, is present.
77
With respect to music sampling, the Act could be read to suggest that courts
would be hostile to a fair use defense in all jurisdictions, at least regarding sound
recording copyrights. Section 114 leaves the sound-alike, or replay
78
avenue
available to musicians who might otherwise choose to sample a sound
recording.
79
In other words, an artist who wishes to sample a snippet of a song
70
Campbell, 510 U.S. at 590 (alteration in original) (quoting Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at
568).
71
Kienitz v. Sconnie Nation LLC, 766 F.3d 756, 758 (7th Cir. 2014) (citing Ty, Inc. v.
Publns Intl Ltd., 292 F.3d 512, 518 (7th Cir. 2002)).
72
Barton Beebe, An Empirical Study of U.S. Copyright Fair Use Opinions, 1978-2005,
156 U. PA. L. REV. 549, 618 (2008).
73
See, e.g., Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579 (stating that works deemed transformative under
factor one lie at the heart of the fair use doctrines guarantee of breathing space within the
confines of copyright); Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 566 (Th[e] last factor is undoubtedly
the single most important element of fair use); see also Beebe, supra note 72, at 584.
74
Beebe, supra note 72, at 617 (alteration in original).
75
GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:8.
76
Id. at 12:5.
77
See Gordon, supra note 12, at 1615.
78
See Computer Music, 11 Golden Rules if You Want to Replay a Sample, MUSICRADAR
(July 20, 2017), https://www.musicradar.com/tuition/tech/11-sample-replay-tips-555535
[https://perma.cc/V8YA-C8YJ] (“‘[R]eplays are essentially super-accurate cover versions
that are practically indistinguishable from the real thing).
79
17 U.S.C. § 114(b) (2012) (The exclusive rights of the owner of copyright in a sound
recording . . . do not extend to the making or duplication of another sound recording that
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
110 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
can instead replay that snippet herself, or hire a session musician to do so,
without any risk of infringing on the sound recording copyright for that song.
80
Thus, when a defendant raises a fair use defense to justify her sampling, and the
court asks as part of its fair use analysis, Did the Defendant need to do what
she did to achieve her goal/purpose?, the answer would appear to be, No,
cutting against fair use.
81
That example is specific to sound recordings because
§ 114 does not apply to musical works.
82
If the musical work is the copyright at
issue, and the court asks the same question regarding the defendants alternatives
to sampling in order to accomplish her goal, the answer is no longer a clear No.
Any recreation of a copyrighted pattern of notes or lyrics that is sufficiently
similar to the original appears infringing of that musical work copyright,
regardless of whether the recreation occurred via digital sampling or any other
means.
83
In the sound recording-replay example, though, the sampling musician
ostensibly has an easy non-infringing alternative to accomplish her artistic
vision, namely, the replay or sound-alike.
84
This seems to suggest that it is more
difficult to prevail on a fair use defense for a sound recording than a musical
work. However, this Note goes on to refute the argument that the Act suggests a
general hostility toward sampling as fair use with respect to sound recordings.
85
To provide further examples of how courts have applied fair use analysis to
subject matter closely related to music sampling, and similarly involving
creative borrowing, I now turn to notable fair use cases involving the visual arts
technique known as appropriation art.
i. Fair Use and Appropriation Art
Having discussed the four factors of fair use in detail, let us now consider an
artistic parallel to music sampling in visual art, which courts have deemed on
more than one occasion to be fair use.
86
In visual art terms, appropriation art is
the intentional borrowing, copying, and alteration of existing images and
objects.
87
One might consider collage, an abstract form of art in which
photographs, pieces of paper, newspaper cuttings, string, etc. are placed in
consists entirely of an independent fixation of other sounds, even though such sounds imitate
or simulate those in the copyrighted sound recording).
80
See Holz, supra note 3; see also MUSICRADAR, supra note 78.
81
See, e.g., Walt Disney Prods. v. Air Pirates, 581 F.2d 751, 758 (9th Cir. 1978).
82
17 U.S.C. § 114 (titled Scope of exclusive rights in sound recordings) (emphasis
added).
83
See 17 U.S.C. § 106 (2012). But see infra Section III.B.
84
See Holz, supra note 3; see also MUSICRADAR, supra note 78.
85
See infra Part IV.
86
See infra text accompanying notes 92-103.
87
Pop Art: Appropriation, MOMALEARNING,
https://www.moma.org/learn/moma_learning/themes/pop-art/appropriation/
[https://perma.cc/3ZAB-E7WD].
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 111
juxtaposition and glued to the pictorial surface,
88
the archetypal work of
appropriation art. Appropriation art is an important and well-respected style of
art, counting Andy Warhol, Roy Lichtenstein, and Robert Rauschenberg among
its more famous practitioners.
89
What appropriation art does with physical objects and images is analogous to
what music sampling does with music and sound. Both involve intentional
appropriation in an artistic medium and aim to create socially valuable
secondary uses. One commentator on the Beastie Boys influential hip hop
record, Pauls Boutique, opined that the album is universally recognized as a
landmark achievement, a masterpiece of rhyme and collage that changes in
sampling law had insured could never be repeated.
90
While critics might
attempt to distinguish between musical appropriation and visual appropriation
for purposes of fair use, one would be hard-pressed to articulate a principled
distinction. Because courts have regarded certain instances of appropriation art
as fair use,
91
so too should courts regard certain acts of music sampling as fair
use. For fair use purposes, there is no principled distinction between the two.
Cariou v. Prince remains perhaps the most well-known, influential, and
controversial case of appropriation art in copyright law.
92
In Cariou, artist
Richard Prince altered and incorporated several of [Patrick] Carious . . .
photographs into a series of paintings and collages.
93
Prince never sought
permission to use Carious photographs.
94
The court reasoned through each of
the four fair use factors, but repeatedly emphasized the first-factor
transformativeness inquiry and its influence on the remaining factors.
95
Summarizing its central conclusion, the court stated that while Prince used key
portions of certain of Carious photographs . . . we determine that in twenty-five
of his artworks, Prince transformed those photographs into something new and
different.
96
Ultimately, the Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit determined
that a majority of Princes works constituted fair use.
97
The court found that
twenty-five of Princes images g[a]ve Carious photographs a new expression,
and employ[ed] new aesthetics with creative and communicative results distinct
from Carious.’”
98
88
Collage, OXFORD ENG. DICTIONARY (2d ed. 1989).
89
See MOMALEARNING, supra note 87.
90
Julian Azran, Bring Back the Noise: How Cariou v. Prince Will Revitalize Sampling, 38
COLUM. J.L. & ARTS 69, 85 (2014) (quoting DAN LEROY, THE BEASTIE BOYS PAULS
BOUTIQUE (33 1/3) 4 (2006)) (emphasis added).
91
See, e.g., Cariou v. Prince, 714 F.3d 694 (2d Cir. 2013).
92
See id.
93
Id. at 698 (alteration in original).
94
Id. at 699.
95
See id. at 705-10.
96
Id. at 710.
97
Id. at 695.
98
Azran, supra note 90, at 97 (quoting Cariou, 714 F.3d at 708) (emphasis added).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
112 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
A similar factual situation to Cariou had arisen in Blanch v. Koons.
99
In that
case, artist Jeff Koons incorporated a version of a photograph he found in a
fashion magazine, without obtaining a license, into a collage that superimposed
various images over a pastoral landscape.
100
Andrea Blanch, the author and
copyright owner of the photograph, accused Koons of copyright infringement.
101
The court determined that Koons collage made fair use of the photograph,
reasoning, importantly, that a finding of transformativeness bled over into the
other factors of the fair use analysis.
102
In discussing transformativeness, the
majority characterized Koons work as adapting a fashion photograph from a
lifestyles magazine with changes of its colors, the background against which
it is portrayed, the medium, the size of the objects pictured, the objects details
and, crucially, their entirely different purpose and meaningas part of a
massive painting commissioned for exhibition in a German art-gallery space.
103
Note, however, that not every appropriation art case results in a finding of fair
use. In another case involving Jeff Koons, Koons created a sculpture that
replicated a postcard photograph which depicted people holding German
Shepherd puppies.
104
The court rejected Koons fair-use parody defense, finding
no parody of that particular photograph, and holding market substitution for the
postcard was likely.
105
Nonetheless, Cariou and Blanch serve as models for music sampling as fair
use. Both cases show how a finding of transformativeness can dominate a fair
use analysis in the appropriation context.
106
Importantly, while the court in
Blanch seemed to hold that transformative purpose was necessary to find fair
use,
107
the Cariou court expressly found no such purpose, nonetheless holding
that transformative expression was sufficient.
108
Just as the appropriation artist
may dissect an existing photograph and re-contextualize part of it among other
images, one who employs music sampling dissects an existing song and re-
contextualizes part of it among other music. Because appropriation art and music
sampling are so conceptually similar, the aforementioned cases have paved the
way for future courts to find that music sampling can often qualify as fair use.
To fully understand what a fair use analysis in a music-sampling case can look
like, consider the novel approach the court took in the following case from 2017.
99
Blanch v. Koons, 467 F.3d 244 (2d Cir. 2006).
100
Id. at 246-49.
101
Id. at 246.
102
Id. at 257-59.
103
Id. at 253 (emphasis added).
104
Rogers v. Koons, 960 F.2d 301, 304-05 (2d Cir. 1992).
105
See id. at 310, 312.
106
See generally Cariou v. Prince, 714 F.3d 694, 706 (2d Cir. 2013); Blanch, 467 F.3d at
256.
107
Blanch, 467 F.3d at 251.
108
Cariou, 714 F.3d at 706.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 113
III. A CONTEMPORARY PERSPECTIVE ON MUSIC SAMPLING AND FAIR USE:
ESTATE OF SMITH V. CASH MONEY RECORDS, INC.
A. Background
On May 30, 2017, the United States District Court for the Southern District
of New York found an instance of music sampling to be fair use, issuing what
may prove to be a watershed opinion for unlicensed music sampling.
109
In Estate
of Smith v. Cash Money Records, Inc., the estate of jazz musician James
Jimmy Smith sued Grammy Award-winning rapper Aubrey Drake Graham,
Drakes label, and others, for infringement of Smiths musical work
copyright.
110
The suit stemmed from Drakes sampling of about thirty-five
seconds from Smiths 1982 song Jimmy Smith Rap for use in Drakes own
single, Pound Cake / Paris Morton Music 2.
111
Drake obtained a license for
the sound recording of Jimmy Smith Rap, but not for the underlying
composition.
112
The portion Drake sampled, like all of Jimmy Smith Rap, was
entirely spoken-word.
113
Drake rearranged and, importantly, deleted some of
Smiths original lyrics.
114
Both sets of lyrics are reprinted below. The full lyrics
to Jimmy Smith Rap are as follows:
Good God Almighty, like back in the old days
You know, years ago they had the A & R men to tell you what to play, how
to play it and you know whether its disco rock, but we just told Bruce that
we want a straight edge jazz so we got the fellas together Grady Tate, Ron
Carter, George Benson, Stanley Turrentine.
Stanley was coming off a cool jazz festival, Ron was coming off a cool jazz
festival. And we just went in the studio and we did it.
We had the champagne in the studio, of course, you know, compliments of
the company and we just laid back and did it.
Also, Grady Tates wife brought us down some home cooked chicken and
we just laid back and we was chomping on chicken and having a ball.
Jazz is the only real music thats gonna last. All that other bullshit is here
today and gone tomorrow. But jazz was, is and always will be.
We may not do this sort of recording again, I may not get with the fellas
again. George, Ron, Grady Tate, Stanley Turrentine.
109
Estate of Smith v. Cash Money Records, Inc., 253 F. Supp. 3d 737, 752 (S.D.N.Y. 2017).
110
Id. at 743-44.
111
Id. at 743.
112
Id.
113
Id. at 742-43.
114
Id. at 743.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
114 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
So we hope you enjoy listening to this album half as much as we enjoyed
playing it for you. Because we had a ball.
115
The sample Drake used in the intro to Pound Cake / Paris Morton Music 2
consisted of the following:
Good God Almighty, like back in the old days.
You know, years ago they had the A & R men to tell you what to play, how
to play it and you know whether its disco rock, but we just went in the
studio and we did it.
We had champagne in the studio, of course, you know, compliments of the
company, and we just laid back and did it.
So we hope you enjoy listening to this album half as much as we enjoyed
playing it for you. Because we had a ball.
Only real music is gonna last, all that other bullshit is here today and gone
tomorrow.
116
Drake abridged or omitted several lines of Smiths original, and reordered
others.
117
The most crucial change, in the courts view, was Drakes truncating
the original line Jazz is the only real music thats gonna last, to Only real
music is gonna last.
118
Crediting the transformativeness of Drakes
appropriation, the court granted Drakes motion for summary judgment, finding
fair use of the unlicensed musical work alongside the licensed sound recording
sample.
119
B. Analysis An In-Depth Look at the Courts Fair Use
Approach in Estate of Smith
What makes Smith so significant is that no other case holds that non-parodic
music sampling, whether of a musical work or a sound recording, falls under fair
use. Newton and its Ninth-Circuit progeny found no infringement under a de
minimis rationale, so those cases never had occasion to address fair use.
120
Similarly, in Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. Dimension Films, the lower court found
no infringement under a de minimis rationale, so the Court of Appeals for the
115
Id. at 742 (emphasis added).
116
Id. at 743 (emphasis added).
117
See id. at 749-50.
118
Id at 749.
119
Id. at 752.
120
Recall that in Newton v. Diamond, 388 F.3d 1189, 1190 (9th Cir. 2004) and VMG
Salsoul, LLC v. Ciccone, 824 F.3d 871, 874 (9th Cir. 2016), the Ninth Circuit found only de
minimis copying, meaning the defendants in those cases were deemed not to have infringed
any of the plaintiffs copyrights, obviating the need to reach any other argument the
defendants may have raised, such as fair use.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 115
Sixth Circuit did not consider fair use on appeal.
121
Though the Sixth Circuit
explicitly authorized the district court to consider a fair use defense on remand,
the case settled, leaving fair-use aficionados to speculate.
122
To predict whether Smith might usher in a new line of cases wherein
defendant music-samplers seek refuge under the fair use defense, one should
consider the ways in which Judge William H. Pauley IIIs fair use analysis in
the music-sampling context of that case was correct and the ways in which it
may have been incorrect. Though Smith dealt with a musical work copyright
implicated by digital sampling, it is not clear how the courts fair use analysis
would have differed had the sound recording been at issue rather than the
composition.
123
In finding fair use of the Plaintiffs musical work, the court first
noted that courts should preclude a finding of infringement where the
copyright laws goal of promoting the Progress of Science and useful Arts . . .
would be better served by allowing the use than by preventing it.’”
124
The court
then systematically applied the four fair use factors.
125
i. Factor One
Under factor one, which the court referred to as [t]he heart of the fair use
inquiry, the court never explicitly considered whether Drakes use of the
sample was for commercial purposes.
126
Pound Cake / Paris Morton Music 2
was undoubtedly a commercial work, and while courts almost never regard
commerciality as dispositive under factor one, it is still odd that the court made
no mention of commerciality at all.
127
Even though courts generally give little
substantive weight to commerciality, the Act expressly directs courts to consider
a works commercial nature in fair use analyses.
128
The bulk of the courts reasoning under factor one dealt with
transformativeness.
129
Drake advanced three arguments supporting
121
Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. Dimension Films, 410 F.3d 792, 805 (6th Cir. 2005). One
might consider whether the bright-line approach adopted in Bridgeport actually leaves room
for a meaningful fair use defense in the Sixth Circuit, despite the courts express statement
that the fair use defense remained available.
122
Agreed Order of Dismissal at 1, Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. 11C Music, No. 3:01-00412
(M.D. Tenn. Jan. 17, 2006), ECF No. 676.
123
For a more detailed discussion of this idea, see infra Part IV.
124
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 748 (quoting Castle Rock Entmt, Inc. v. Carol Publg
Grp., Inc., 150 F.3d 132, 141 (2d Cir. 1998)).
125
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 748-52.
126
Id. at 749-51 (quoting Davis v. The Gap, Inc., 246 F.3d 152, 174 (2d Cir. 2001)).
127
Drake, Pound Cake / Paris Morton Music 2, on NOTHING WAS THE SAME (DELUXE)
(Cash Money Records 2013) SPOTIFY,
https://open.spotify.com/album/2gXTTQ713nCELgPOS0qWyt [https://perma.cc/XH5K-
CE4D] (the song has been streamed on Spotify over 129 million times as of Nov. 20, 2019);
see GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:28.
128
17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012); GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:28.
129
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 749-51.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
116 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
transformative use.
130
First, he argued that his new song fundamentally
alter[ed] the message of the original work . . . by editing the recording from Jazz
is the only real music thats gonna last to Only real music is gonna last,’” and
that he had thus transformed Jimmy Smiths dismissive comment into a
statement on the relevance and staying power of real music, regardless of
genre.
131
Second, Drake argued that by removing references to Smiths record,
Drake made the words apply to the making of his own album rather than
Smiths.
132
Drakes third transformativeness argument was that the addition of
background music, the rearrangement of some words, and the placement of the
recording in a seven-minute hip hop track render[ed] the[] use
transformative.
133
The court rejected the latter two arguments as not being
sufficiently transformative in purpose, though it acknowledged that these
arguments did indicate transformative form.
134
The court agreed with Drakes
first argument, however, finding that alteration of the key phrase Jazz is the
only real music thats gonna last to Only real music is gonna last made the
samples purpose transformative, and that the first factor thus supported a
finding of fair use.
135
The court was correct to weigh transformativeness so greatly, in light of
Supreme Court and Second Circuit precedent.
136
Thus, its conclusion that
Drakes changing the line Jazz is the only real music thats gonna last to Only
real music is gonna last made the samples purpose transformative comports
with precedent and reason.
137
The Second Circuit expressly deemed
transformative purpose a means of achieving transformativeness in Blanch,
138
and the statement Only real music is gonna last clearly differs in meaning from
the statement Jazz is the only real music thats gonna last, evincing Drakes
new purpose.
139
While the purpose of Smiths original statement was to extol
the supremacy of jazz over other genres, Drakes statement speaks to the lasting
power of real music, irrespective of its genre.
140
Further, the court was right to reject Drakes second argument for
transformative purpose: that by removing references to Smiths album, Drake
130
Id. at 749.
131
Id.
132
Id.
133
Id.
134
Id. at 749-50.
135
Id. at 750-51.
136
See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569 (1994); Cariou v. Prince,
714 F.3d 694 (2d Cir. 2013); Bill Graham Archives v. Dorling Kindersley Ltd., 448 F.3d 605
(2d Cir. 2006).
137
See Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 750-51; see also Blanch v. Koons, 467 F.3d 244,
253 (2d Cir. 2006).
138
See Blanch, 467 F.3d at 253.
139
See Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 750-51.
140
See id. at 749.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 117
made the lyrics apply to the making of Drakes own album rather than
Smiths.
141
The court was correct to reject this argument because the sampled
lines describing Smiths recording process, if taken to likewise describe Drakes
recording process, would serve only to recapitulate Smiths purpose for those
lyrics. In short, the purpose of those specific lyrics remained the same:
describing a recording process.
142
The court called Drakes appropriation of
these lyrics literally transformative in the sense that [Drake] does not
appropriate [Jimmy Smith Rap] verbatim.
143
This is odd, though, because the
lyrics Drake sampled regarding the recording process were sampled verbatim.
144
The court diverged from proper course under factor one by narrowing the
transformativeness doctrine to concern only transformative purpose or
message.
145
Under Cariou, appropriation that “‘add[s] something new and
present[s] [a plaintiffs work] with a fundamentally different aesthetic weighs
in favor of fair use.
146
In Cariou, it did not matter that Richard Prince explicitly
stated that he had no intention of creat[ing] anything with a new meaning or a
new message.
147
The Cariou court reasoned that some of Princes appropriation
of Carious photographs was nonetheless transformative in expression.
148
In light of Cariou, then, Drakes third argument for transformativeness
probably should have prevailed as well.
149
Drakes recontextualization of
Smiths voice and lyrics with background music, the rearrangement of some
words, and . . . placement . . . in a seven-minute hip hop track
150
rendered
Drakes use something new . . . with a fundamentally different aesthetic.
151
This recontextualization rationale should hold in other cases of music sampling,
mainly because it describes how music sampling is actually practiced and the
creativity that music sampling entails.
152
And from a stare decisis standpoint,
141
Id. at 749-50.
142
Id.
143
Id. at 750 (alteration in original).
144
See id. at 742-43.
145
See id. at 749-51; see also Cariou v. Prince, 714 F.3d 694, 708 (2d Cir. 2013).
146
Cariou, 714 F.3d at 708 (alteration in original) (quoting Leibovitz v. Paramount Pictures
Corp., 137 F.3d 109, 114 (2d Cir. 1998)).
147
Id. at 707 (alteration in original).
148
Id. at 706-08.
149
See Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 749; see also Cariou, 714 F.3d at 706-08.
150
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 749.
151
Cariou, 714 F.3d at 708 (citing Leibovitz, 137 F.3d at 114).
152
See generally Olufunmilayo B. Arewa, From J.C. Bach to Hip Hop: Musical Borrowing,
Copyright and Cultural Context, 84 N.C. L. REV. 547, 552 (2006); compare CYPRESS HILL,
Hits from the Bong, on BLACK SUNDAY (Ruffhouse Records 1993), with DUSTY SPRINGFIELD,
Son of a Preacher Man, on DUSTY IN MEMPHIS (Atlantic Records 1968).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
118 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
Drakes recontextualization rationale in no way contradicts Supreme Court
precedent and is entirely in line with the Second Circuits approach in Cariou.
153
ii. Factor Two
Under factor two, the nature of the copyrighted work, the court reasoned that
music falls under the core of creative expression that copyright is meant to
protect, but that the second factor is of limited value when the defendant’s use
is for a transformative purpose.
154
Thus, the courts analysis of factor two
conforms with precedent.
155
Factor two remains the least controversial or
contested within the fair use doctrine, leaving little if anything to say regarding
its application here.
156
iii. Factor Three
For factor three, the court reasoned that the commentary drawn from Jimmy
Smith Rap, in tandem with the key phrase concerning real music, serve[d]
to drive the point home . . . that many musicians make records in similar ways
(e.g. with the help of A & R experts or the stimulating effects of champagne),
but that only real musicregardless of creative process or genrewill stand
the test of time.
157
The court accordingly found that the amount Drake used was
reasonable in proportion to his transformative purpose, and appropriately found
that factor three favored fair use.
158
The courts approach is cogent, but factor three inevitably raises some
complexities.
159
Because the third factor has undergone a change over time, from
a focus on the amount and substantiality of the copied portion solely with respect
to the copyrighted work, to an additional emphasis on the copied portion with
respect to the defendants work on the whole, the state of the law is somewhat
unclear under the third factor.
160
Given this uncertainty, it would appear the
courts take in Smith was mostly on point.
161
The court focused on the amount
taken by Defendants . . . in proportion to the needs of the intended
transformative use, quoting in its analysis Blanch and Cariou.
162
153
See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 572 (1994); Harper & Row
Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 566 (1985); Cariou, 714 F.3d at 698-99.
154
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 751 (citing Bill Graham Archives v. Dorling
Kindersley Ltd., 448 F.3d 605, 611 (2d Cir. 2006)).
155
See, e.g., Campbell, 510 U.S. at 586.
156
See generally GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:45-54; Beebe, supra note 72, at 610-15.
157
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 751-52 (alteration in original).
158
Id.
159
See id.; see also Campbell, 510 U.S. at 586-589.
160
See supra text accompanying notes 67-69.
161
See supra text accompanying notes 68-69; see also Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at
751-52.
162
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 751.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 119
One rather puzzling remark is that the court, in its factor-three analysis, refers
to Drakes use as commentary, whereas the court makes no reference to
Drakes use as commentary under factor one.
163
Given that comment[ary]
is explicitly referenced in the statutory preamble to § 107 and has been a time-
tested haven for fair use in the courts,
164
it is a bit odd that the court would not
discuss Drakes use as commentary when addressing factor one, the purpose
and nature of the use, if the court did consider Drakes use commentary.
165
The courts opaque reference to the use as commentary under factor three
raises the question of what exactly it intended by using that descriptor.
166
iv. Factor Four
The court noted that the fourth factor, the uses effect on the potential market
for or value of the copyrighted work, was undoubtedly the single most
important element of fair use.
167
The court also remarked that the fourth factor
is . . . closely linked to the first, in the sense that the more the copying is done
to achieve a purpose that differs from the purpose of the original, the less likely
it is that the copy will serve as a satisfactory substitute for the original.’”
168
The
court then found that the target audience for Jimmy Smith Rap was sharply
different than the target audience for Drakes track and that the plaintiffs had
made no efforts to license derivative uses of Jimmy Smith Rap.
169
Those
findings, alongside the highly transformative nature of Drakes use and the
absence of evidence in the record suggesting market usurpation, prompted the
conclusion that factor four favored Drake.
170
The court then concluded that the
four factors, considered in light of the goals of copyright law and the facts in
the record, led to a finding of fair use.
171
Under factor four, the court largely stuck to precedent, punctuating its
analysis with the logical conclusion that Drakes use would not substitute in the
market for Jimmy Smith Rap or its derivatives.
172
One wrinkle is that the
court called factor four undoubtedly the single most important element of fair
163
Id. at 749-52.
164
See, e.g., Campbell, 510 U.S. 569; Katz v. Google, 802 F.3d 1178, 1183 (11th Cir.
2015); Equals Three, LLC v. Jukin Media, Inc., 139 F. Supp. 3d 1094 (C.D. Cal. 2015); see
also 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2012).
165
See Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 749-52.
166
See id.
167
Id. at 752 (quoting Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 566
(1985)).
168
Id. (quoting Authors Guild v. Google, Inc., 804 F.3d 202, 223 (2d Cir. 2015)); Castle
Rock Entmt, Inc. v. Carol Publg Grp., Inc., 150 F.3d 132, 145 (2d Cir. 1998).
169
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 752.
170
Id.
171
Id.
172
See id. (citing Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 592 (1994)); Castle
Rock, 150 F.3d at 145).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
120 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
use, after having referred to factor one as [t]he heart of the fair use inquiry.
173
Other commentators have remarked on the potential tension where courts
prioritize both factor one and factor four.
174
Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v.
Nation Enters., the Supreme Court case that first stressed the importance of
factor four, has not been overruled.
175
That said, invoking the near-controlling
importance of both the first and fourth factors in the same opinion as the court
did in Smith seems inadvisable, as the two may not always coincide.
176
The court grounded its fourth-factor reasoning in the fact that the target
audience for Jimmy Smith Rap was sharply different than the target
audience for Drakes track, and that the plaintiffs had made no efforts to license
derivative uses of Jimmy Smith Rap.
177
Even if both those statements are true,
one might reasonably question whether the target audience is the only
population who matters under factor four, and whether plaintiffs own efforts to
license samples should matter under factor four.
178
IV. MODEL APPLICATION OF FAIR USE FOR MUSIC SAMPLING CASES
Smith was a major milestone on the path to greater acceptance of music
sampling as fair use. That being said, the courts analysis may have been
deficient in some important respects. Later courts applying the exact same
approach would not be utilizing the fair use doctrine and precedent to their full
potential in cases of music sampling. Considering the factors in aggregate, music
sampling could often be a great candidate for application of the fair use doctrine.
This section provides a general, model approach to application of the fair use
doctrine in music-sampling cases, drawing particularly on lessons from Smith,
as well as from valuable precedent in the realm of visual appropriation art.
179
It
begins with a look at a possible narrow distinction in the fair use analyses for
musical work versus sound recording copyrights.
An important part of a courts overall fair use analysis is the question, Did
the Defendant need to do what she did to achieve her goal/purpose? with an
answer of Yes cutting in favor of fair use, and No cutting against fair use.
180
Recall also that replaying ostensibly provides an alternative to sampling a
173
See id. at 749-52 (first quoting Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471
U.S. 539, 566 (1985); and then quoting Davis v. The Gap, Inc., 246 F.3d 152, 174 (2d Cir.
2001)).
174
See Beebe, supra note 72, at 583; see also GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:32-33, 12:58.
175
Harper & Row, 471 U.S. 539; see also Campbell, 510 U.S. at 585.
176
See Beebe, supra note 72, at 583.
177
Estate of Smith, 253 F. Supp. 3d at 752.
178
For a discussion on fourth-factor issues, see infra Section IV.D.
179
Note that any general, model approach to fair use will be inherently limited to some
extent, because fair use is such a fact-specific inquiry. See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 577.
Nonetheless, such a model has value as a starting point for courts.
180
See supra text accompanying notes 78-81; see, e.g., Walt Disney Prods. v. Air Pirates,
581 F.2d 751, 758 (9th Cir. 1978).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 121
sound recording, meaning a musicians choice to sample a recording seems to
cut against fair use.
181
However, the mere fact that a sample-based musician
theoretically could have replayed part of a sound recording rather than sampling
it should not vitiate her fair use defense. Sampled artists voices or instrumental
tones may be so unique that even the best studio musician could not replicate
them exactly.
182
A sample-based musicians artistic vision may hinge on
repurposing those exact, unique sounds in her own track. Further, a sample-
based musician may not be proficient vocally, or on the instrument she wishes
to sample, and session musicians can be quite expensive.
183
Therefore, when
courts ask as part of their fair use analyses in cases wherein the defendant opted
to sample a sound recording rather than replay it, Did the Defendant need to do
it this way to achieve her goal/purpose?, the answer may actually be Yes,
weighing in favor of fair use.
184
This argument pertains to both sound recording
and musical work copyrights. When courts inquire about alternative methods, a
defendants inability to purchase licenses due to limited financial resources
185
indicates that by sampling, the artist achieved her artistic vision the only way
she could, weighing in favor of fair use. Ultimately then, it may be no more, or
less, difficult to prevail on a fair use defense for a sound recording than a musical
work, especially for defendants with limited financial resources.
186
Having acknowledged an important wrinkle in the model fair uses analyses
for sound recordings and musical works, the following subsections walk through
the four statutory fair use factors. Importantly, the application of the four fair
use factors should be the same regardless of whether a musical work or a sound
recording is the copyright at issue, as explained in more detail below.
181
See supra text accompanying notes 83-84; see also Holz, supra note 3; MUSICRADAR,
supra note 78.
182
See, e.g., David Cox, Is Your Voice Trustworthy, Engaging or Soothing to Strangers?,
THE GUARDIAN (Apr. 16, 2015), https://www.theguardian.com/science/blog/2015/apr/16/is-
your-voice-trustworthy-engaging-or-soothing-to-strangers [https://perma.cc/5CLH-QGAS]
(describing interactions between an array of different features from pitch to energy
accumulated over time, which all combine to give each voice its unique fingerprint or
signature); Five Guitarists Talk Tone Inspiration, GUITAR.COM (Mar. 21, 2018),
https://guitar.com/features/five-guitarists-spill-the-secrets-behind-their-tone/
[https://perma.cc/3STE-YFZ6] (discussing guitarists with unique guitar tones).
183
See Szymanski, supra note 35, at 276 (citing Johnson, supra note 38, at 275) (discussing
how sampling can reduce studio and musician costs, and relieve the pressure placed on
producers and sound engineers to achieve the right sound); see also Session Musicians
Know Your Rights, MUSIC INDUS. INSIDE OUT (Apr. 18, 2015),
https://musicindustryinsideout.com.au/session-musicians-know-rights/
[https://perma.cc/DD9B-KXP6] (noting the standard rate for session musicians in Australia
is approximately 100 Australian dollars per hour, which is equal to about 72 U.S. dollars per
hour).
184
See supra Part I; see, e.g., Disney, 581 F.2d at 758.
185
See supra Part I.
186
See supra Part I.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
122 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
A. Factor One: Purpose and Character of the Use
With respect to factor one, sampling can vary in transformativeness based on
how much of an existing song a musician samples, the specific elements a
musician samples, the extent to which the sampled portion is altered in a new
song, and the way in which the sample is accompanied by other music in a new
song. Indeed, artists employing samples often make something new, with a
further purpose or different character, altering the [portion of the original work]
with new . . . meaning[] or message.
187
This much is true whether the contested
copyright is in a musical work, a sound recording, or even if both are contested
when an artist repurposes or manipulates the sounds of a preexisting recording,
she likewise repurposes or manipulates the underlying lyrics or pattern of notes
in the composition.
Consider a musician who, through sampling, uses the minimal [amount]
necessary to accomplish [her] purpose;” such minimal use bespeaks
transformativeness.
188
If a musician alters a sampled portion of a song by
changing the tempo or pitch of the original, this adds to transformativeness.
189
If a new song has a different theme, mood, [or] tone than the song it
samples,
190
or uses sampled lyrics to convey a different message in a different
context than the lyrics did in the original song, the new song makes
transformative use of its sample. Further, if a sampled portion of an existing
song constitutes an inconsequential portion of a new song, the use is more
likely to be transformative.
191
Moreover, if the sample fits into a new song
among other music, and is played simultaneously with other sounds, the
resulting aural collage reinforces the argument for transformative use.
192
Transformative use can greatly influence the remaining factors.
193
If a commercial song incorporates sampling, its commercial nature
concededly cuts against sampling as fair use under factor one.
194
However,
commerciality is not dispositive, and the commerciality of a work does not
render its use of a prior work presumptively unfair.
195
Thus, a sufficiently
transformative commercial work may still fall under fair use.
196
187
Castle Rock Entmt, Inc. v. Carol Publg Grp., Inc., 150 F.3d 132, 141-42 (2d Cir. 1998)
(citing Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 579 (1994)).
188
Bill Graham Archives v. Dorling Kindersley Ltd., 448 F.3d 605, 611 (2d Cir. 2006)
(alteration in original).
189
Id. (alteration in original).
190
Bridgeport Music, Inc. v. UMG Recordings, Inc., 585 F.3d 267, 278 (6th Cir. 2009)
(alteration in original).
191
See Graham, 448 F.3d at 611.
192
See id.
193
See, e.g., Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 594 (1994).
194
GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:26.
195
See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 594.
196
See id.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 123
B. Factor Two: Nature of the Copyrighted Work
Factor two, the nature of the copyrighted work, calls for recognition that
some works are closer to the core of intended copyright protection than others,
with the consequence that fair use is more difficult to establish when the former
works are copied.
197
Music is among those subjects at the core of intended
copyright protection, so the creative nature of a sampled musical work and its
corresponding sound recording concededly cuts against sampling as fair use.
198
That said, this factor may be of limited usefulness where the creative work . . .
is being used for a transformative purpose.
199
Indeed, in both Cariou and
Blanch, the copied photographs were at the core of intended copyright
protection, yet both cases found fair use.
200
Thus, a sufficiently transformative
use of a preexisting song can still be fair use.
201
C. Factor Three: Amount and Substantiality of the Portion Used
The third factor inquiry asks whether the quantity and value used are
reasonable in relation to the purpose of the copying.
202
With respect to factor
three, the link to transformativeness is of the utmost importance.
203
Courts assess
the amount and substantiality of the portion used, relative to the original work
as a whole, in both quantitative and qualitative terms.
204
This is a highly fact-
specific inquiry, and a sliding scale.
205
In the context of recorded music and
sampling, the third-factor inquiry should not differ between musical works and
sound recordings. When a musician samples more of one or a more substantial
part of one, it would appear she samples more of, or a more substantial part of,
the other as well.
Samples that use quantitatively more of a prior song, or a qualitatively more
significant part of a prior song, are concededly less likely to be fair use.
206
Relatedly, samples that use quantitatively less of a prior song, or a qualitatively
less significant part of a prior song, are more likely to be fair use.
207
Given that
some courts examine the portion the defendant copied relative to the defendants
work as well, samples that form a less quantitatively or qualitatively significant
197
Id. at 586.
198
See id.
199
Bill Graham Archives v. Dorling Kindersley Ltd., 448 F.3d 605, 612 (2d Cir. 2006); see
also Castle Rock Entmt, Inc. v. Carol Publg Grp., Inc., 150 F.3d 132, 142 (2d Cir. 1998).
200
See supra text accompanying notes 92-103.
201
See, e.g., Campbell, 510 U.S. at 586.
202
Id.
203
See id. at 579.
204
See id. at 587.
205
See id. at 577.
206
See id. at 587-88.
207
See id.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
124 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
part of the defendants work are also more likely to be fair use.
208
Thus the fact-
dependent nature of this inquiry provides little general guidance, and courts
should be careful not to give the third factor too much weight in a multifactorial
balancing test that prioritizes the first and fourth factors.
209
However, because
transformativeness bears on this factor as well, and because samples may consist
of only minuscule and/or obscure parts of prior compositions and recordings, the
third factor should not vitiate the sampling-as-fair-use argument in very many
cases.
D. Factor Four: Effect on the Market
Under factor four, the proper inquiry is whether a new song will usurp the
market for the sampled/existing song, or usurp part of the derivative market for
songs sampling the existing song.
210
This much is true of sampled sound
recordings and their underlying musical works. There are markets for both, and
any alleged market usurpation of a recording logically coincides with alleged
market usurpation of its corresponding musical work, and vice versa.
Critics of music-sampling-as-fair-use might contend, relying on factor four,
that absolving musicians of the need to obtain licenses will deprive sampled
artists, or their rights-holders, of profits to which they are entitled.
211
This
argument has a superficial appeal. However, it rests on two flawed assumptions.
The first is that a plaintiffs lost licensing fee(s) from the defendant should
qualify as market harm under factor four.
212
The second is that sampling has an
empirically evident negative effect on the market for a sampled/existing song,
or on the market for other songs sampling that existing song.
213
Given that the
Supreme Court has called the fourth factor undoubtedly the single most
important element of fair use,
214
let us explore these flawed fourth-factor
assumptions in more detail.
Consider the first flawed assumption, that a plaintiffs lost licensing fee(s)
from the defendant should qualify as market harm. This contention is not
specific to the context of music or music sampling. Commentators and courts
have long debated whether a plaintiffs lost licensing fees from the defendant
208
See GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57 (citing Wright v. Warner Books Inc., 953 F.2d 731, 739
(2d Cir. 1991)).
209
See supra text accompanying notes 55-73.
210
See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 590-92.
211
See Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 589 (1985)
(Brennan, J., dissenting).
212
See Christina Bohannan, Copyright Harm, Foreseeability, and Fair Use, 85 WASH. U.
L. REV. 969, 978 (2007) ([T]he copyright owner typically argues that he or she suffered harm
because the defendant could have paid her a licensing fee for use of the work.).
213
Mike Schuster et. al., Sampling Increases Music Sales: An Empirical Copyright Study,
56 AM. BUS. L.J. 177, 208 (2019).
214
Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 566.
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 125
should qualify as market harm under factor four.
215
This author falls in the camp
of commentators who believe lost licensing fees from the defendant should not
qualify. To hold that they should qualify is circular logic:
216
It is wrong to
measure the detriment to plaintiff by loss of presumed royalty incomea
standard which necessarily assumes that plaintiff had a right to issue
licenses. . . . [and] that the defendants practices did not constitute fair use . . .
[O]ne cannot assume at the start the merit of the plaintiffs position.
217
In an
effort to avoid the circularity, some scholars have suggested courts should
infer[] harm from foreseeable uses.
218
Because one could argue that an
existing market is (or was) a foreseeable one, and because a robust market exists
for licensing musical works and sound recordings, the foreseeability approach
would appear to weigh in favor of the plaintiff in every case of unlicensed music
sampling.
However, this purportedly non-circular approach is similarly flawed. Just
because something happened does not mean it was foreseeable. Consider the
difference between cause-in-fact and proximate cause in tort law.
219
The mere
fact that a market exists for licensing musical works and sound recordings does
not necessarily imply such a market was foreseeable.
220
Moreover, if an existing
licensing market gives rise to an inference of fourth-factor harm, the implication
is that a large-scale occurrence in the world of economics and consumer
transactions (i.e., the development of a market for music licensing) swallows
what is supposed to be an individualized legal determination and analysis in fair
use cases, thereby doing the courts job for them.
The concept of foreseeable use renders an already difficult, subjective, and
abstract fair use analysis even more difficult, subjective, and abstract. This is
especially true in a context like music sampling, where the temptation of
hindsight bias makes it exceedingly difficult to determine whether the
development of the now-existing technology and practice of music sampling,
and markets for related licensing, were foreseeable.
221
Thus, the concept of
foreseeable use, and the practice of treating a plaintiffs lost licensing fee(s) from
the defendant as market harm under fair-use factor four, are ultimately not that
215
See generally GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:60-68.
216
See id. at 12:60.
217
Williams & Wilkins Co. v. United States, 487 F.2d 1345, 1357 n.19 (Ct. Cl. 1973)
(alteration in original).
218
See, e.g., Bohannan, supra note 212, at 973-74 (describing one definition of harm in
the fourth-factor context that attempts to evade a circular argument with respect to lost license
fees and market harm).
219
See, e.g., Charles E. Carpenter, Workable Rules for Determining Proximate Cause-Part
III, 20 CAL. L. REV. 470, 471-72 (1932) (distinguishing cause in fact from the higher standard
of proximate cause, and describing foreseeability as a factor in finding the latter, though both
are legal cause[s]).
220
See id.
221
See Matthew Africa, The Misuse of Licensing Evidence in Fair Use Analysis: New
Technologies, New Markets, and the Courts, 88 CAL. L. REV. 1145, 1148 (2000).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
126 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
helpful. Courts should look to demonstrable market harm under the fourth
factor. In the context of music sampling, this leads to the second flawed
assumption.
The second flawed assumption is that sampling has an empirically evident
negative effect on the market for a sampled/existing song, or on the market for
other songs sampling that existing song. The reality may be an insurmountable
evidentiary hurdle for plaintiffs, and perhaps even a framework that is
fundamentally inapplicable in the music-sampling context, pointing toward a
finding of fair use.
222
Of the four factors, the fourth-factor inquiry actually
provides perhaps the most compelling rationale for music sampling as fair use.
What does it mean for a song to be a market substitute for another song?
Presumably, under the conventional economic concept of market substitution,
223
it means that listeners can replace one song with another. Classic examples of
market substitutes include butter and margarine.
224
But the concept of market
substitution, typically applied in the context of goods,
225
is problematic in the
music context. Given the immense levels of subjectivity and individual
preference involved in music consumption,
226
the notion that two songs could
replace one another in the market for music is ultimately unrealisticit does
not take into account how music consumption actually happens.
Certainly, an individual listener will occasionally make a conscious choice to
listen to one song over another. But for a vast percentage of listeners, especially
those who listen to multiple genres, the songs they consciously choose to listen
to over others may bear little-to-no resemblance to the songs they have
foregone.
227
For such listeners with eclectic tastes, discussing songs as being
similar, or even partially identical in cases of obvious sampling, is unhelpful in
a market-substitution inquiry. A choice to listen to one song over another may
have little-to-nothing to do with any similar elements the songs share.
To further illustrate the standard fourth-factor inquirys shortcomings in the
music context, consider the substitute-versus-complement test the Seventh
222
See infra text accompanying notes 236-38.
223
See generally EDGAR K. BROWNING, MICROECONOMIC THEORY & APPLICATIONS 56-57
(6th ed. 1999).
224
Id. at 56-57 (explaining how to measure the willingness of a consumer to substitute one
good for another).
225
Id. at 57.
226
See generally Albert LeBlanc, An Interactive Theory of Music Preference, 19 J. MUSIC
THERAPY 28, 29-31 (1982).
227
See, e.g., Angela Balakrishnan, Presidential Playlist: Obama Opens Up His iPod, THE
GUARDIAN (June 25, 2008),
https://www.theguardian.com/world/2008/jun/25/barackobama.uselections2008
[https://perma.cc/8Z2W-LANL]; Alex Marshall, Donald Trump’s Unexpected Thoughts on
Music Revealed, BBC MUSIC (Nov. 9, 2016),
https://www.bbc.co.uk/music/articles/e5e4572a-0676-4120-9eb3-d34bbea34836
[https://perma.cc/4EAS-8BAQ] (noting an individual listener may be a fan of disparate
musical genres).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 127
Circuit has applied.
228
In that test, the court asks whether the contested use is a
complement to the protected work (allowed) rather than a substitute for it
(prohibited).
229
Nails are the quintessential complements to hammers, whereas
nails are substitutes for screws or pegs.
230
Using that analogy, is the relationship
between two similar songs more like that of hammer and nail, or that of a screw
and nail? Consider that the relationship, even between two songs that are
markedly similar, may more closely resemble the former: exposure to a song of
a certain style may ignite a passion in a listener for songs of that style, prompting
that listener to seek out other songs similar to the first.
231
Thus, appreciation for
a song does not preclude consumption of similar songs; instead, it may actually
promote consumption of similar songs.
232
This effect is well-documented in the
sampling context specifically, with research showing that listeners of a song
containing a sample are more likely to seek out the sampled song.
233
The difficulties of applying § 107s fourth factor in the music context may
reach even broader. Indeed, the concept of market substitution is problematic
across the entire entertainment sector. Imagine an individual consumer decides
to spend her afternoon watching a film. While perusing the films available to
her, that user may very well mull over several films, each of a different genre,
starring different actors, and the product of a different creative team. Does the
consumers choice to watch one film over the others she was considering mean
all the films she considered are market substitutes for each other, despite any
stark differences between them? Now, imagine that same individual consumer
decides she no longer wishes to watch a film at all, and instead chooses to listen
to some of her favorite records, or even to go outside and fly a kite. Might music,
kite-flying, and film each usurp the entertainment market for one another?
234
The difficulty of the market-substitution framework is evident for such
dissimilar activities which, despite their differences, can and do serve as
replacement activities for one another.
235
Thus, it is difficult to meaningfully apply the market-substitution framework
within the realm of music, and music sampling in particular. Not only might two
228
Kienitz v. Sconnie Nation LLC, 766 F.3d 756, 758 (7th Cir. 2014) (citing Ty, Inc. v.
Publns Intl Ltd., 292 F.3d 512 (7th Cir. 2002)).
229
Id.
230
Ty, 292 F.3d at 517.
231
See, e.g., Confusion, Watch Kanye West Talk About Early Influences and Meeting
Michael Jackson, COMPLEX (Nov. 26, 2013), https://www.complex.com/pigeons-and-
planes/2013/11/kanye-west-michael-jackson [https://perma.cc/KRE9-L5T5].
232
See id.
233
See Mike Schuster et al., Sampling Increases Music Sales: An Empirical Copyright
Study, 56 AM. BUS. L.J. 177, 178 (2019); Szymanski, supra note 35, at 321.
234
See generally Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 592 (1994) (stating
that courts should look for usurpation of market demand under factor four).
235
Cf. Rajendra K. Srivastava et al., Market Structure Analysis: Hierarchical Clustering of
Products Based on Substitution-in-Use, 45 J. MARKETING 38, 38-48 (1981) (examining the
boundaries for substitution and competition of product).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
128 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
songs containing the same sample differ significantly,
236
but, even among
admittedly similar songs, highly subjective and individualized user preferences
do not lend themselves to market-substitution analysis.
237
Under factor four,
asking whether a song that includes a sample may substitute in the market for
the sampled/existing song or for other songs sampling the existing song may be
a fruitless inquiry.
Consequently, the difficulties of applying the market-substitution framework
in the music-sampling context present an evidentiary problem for plaintiffs. In
fair use cases, the plaintiff typically must establish with reasonable probability
the existence of a causal connection between the infringement and a
[speculative] loss of revenue, shifting the burden to the infringer to show that
th[e] [alleged] damage would have occurred had there been no taking of
copyrighted expression.
238
Given the arguments above, how exactly would
plaintiffs demonstrate a causal connection between lost revenue and a song that
has sampled their song? Because of the problem the market-substitution inquiry
poses in the music-sampling context, plaintiffs cannot easily establish market
usurpation.
Precisely defining the markets for the plaintiffs work and for derivative
works is yet another difficulty with the fourth-factor inquiry in cases of music
sampling.
239
This author found no cases that address this problem head-on. One
might argue that the consumers in the relevant markets consist of, most broadly,
people who pay money to listen to music generally. Under this broad conception,
would every song be in competition with every other song? Such a conception
of the market is likely over-inclusive for purposes of the fair use doctrine. But
might a focus instead on target audience, however it is defined or determined,
be too limited? Narrowing markets for purposes of a fair use inquiry, without
being overly restrictive, is no easy feat.
In light of all the above difficulties that plaintiffs will encounter, it seems the
fourth factor will weigh in favor of fair use in many instances of unlicensed
music sampling. That is to say nothing of the fact that a finding of sufficient
transformativeness under factor one can itself seemingly dictate the outcome of
factor four in the defendants favor.
240
Given the importance of the fourth factor
in fair use analysis on the whole, what emerges is an understanding that music
sampling can often be fair use.
236
Compare, e.g., PRETTY LIGHTS, FINALLY MOVING (Pretty Lights Music 2006), with
AVICII, LEVELS (Interscope Records 2011).
237
See generally LeBlanc, supra note 226, at 29-31; see also supra text accompanying
notes 226-27.
238
Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 566-67 (1985)
(alteration in original).
239
See generally Campbell, 510 U.S. at 590-93 (explaining the importance of analyzing the
effect on the market for derivative works in fair use cases).
240
See id. at 569; Estate of Smith v. Cash Money Records, Inc., 253 F. Supp. 3d 737, 752
(S.D.N.Y. 2017).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
2020] MUSIC SAMPLING AS FAIR USE 129
However, one narrow hypothetical example of sampling may call into
question the above critique of the fourth factor inquiry in music-sampling cases.
Imagine a musician samples a song in its entirety with no changes or additions,
then she releases her new song, which is really an exact replica of the old
sound recording, under a new name and with a claim to authorship over the
new song. Is this new song not a market substitute for the original? It would
seem that market confusion very well could result. What should happen in such
a scenario, then? Market confusion is actionable under the Lanham Act,
241
in the
realm of those limited moral ownership rights afforded under United States law,
as opposed to the Copyright Act.
242
Conceding that market substitution likely
could result from this example of two virtually identical songs, one should also
recognize that copying exists on a spectrum.
243
The difficult question is, at
exactly what point down the line of similarity does market substitution surely
not exist?
Thankfully, even though the above hypothetical is perhaps thorny from a
fourth-factor standpoint, another dimension of fair use analysis renders it an easy
case. A court would surely deem such a blatant instance of total, literal copying
in an effort to pass the song off as ones own to be insufficiently transformative
under factor one to warrant a finding of fair use. Thus, any wise guy attempting
to pass off someone elses song as his own via sampling would be an
unsuccessful defendant in an infringement action, because a court would view
the character of such a use as not falling within the scope of § 107.
244
CONCLUSION
Copyright law has for too long unjustly discriminated against musicians who
make music via sampling.
245
Artists are stifled because their art cannot exist
without licenses, but they cannot afford licensing fees.
246
Would-be musicians
of limited means are silenced.
247
Courts should consider this policy argument in
their fair use analyses.
248
The fair use defense provides hope for sample-based
241
Lanham Act § 43(a), 15 U.S.C. § 1125(a) (2012).
242
See 3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 8D.02, Lexis (database updated Aug. 2019); Gilliam v.
Am. Broad. Cos., 538 F.2d 14, 24 (2d Cir. 1976).
243
Compare VMG Salsoul, LLC v. Ciccone, 824 F.3d 871, 874-77 (9th Cir. 2016)
(involving literal copying), with Selle v. Gibb, 741 F.2d 896, 905 (7th Cir. 1984) (holding that
plaintiffs evidence of striking similarity was not sufficiently compelling to prove access so
as to support element of copying).
244
See supra text accompanying notes 56-63.
245
See supra Part I.
246
See generally Vrana, supra note 7 (discussing how the laws treatment of sampling as
copyright infringement is a barrier for legitimate artists).
247
See supra Part I.
248
See GOLDSTEIN, supra note 57, at 12:5 (describing how courts remain mindful of policy
concerns in applying the four factors, and how fair use can excuse an otherwise-infringing
use if the social benefit outweighs the loss to the copyright owner).
CLAFLIN 2.14_KS EDITS (DO NOT DELETE) 4/13/2020 2:43 PM
130 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. [Vol. 26.1
musicians. Music sampling is transformative.
249
Music sampling does not harm
the incentives or the economic livelihood of the copyright owners of sampled
works.
250
Music sampling is akin to appropriation art, a creative approach courts
have deemed fair use.
251
Music sampling adds to the pool of creative works.
252
Music sampling as fair use is better for musicians, and better for music fans.
Music sampling as fair use is better for music.
249
See supra text accompanying notes 187-93.
250
See supra text accompanying notes 215-21.
251
See supra Section II.B.1.
252
See supra Section II.B.